Solutions for exercises in chapter 1 = 2, 3, 1, 4 ; = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2 1 S 1 1 S 0 = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2, 1, 4,1,3. 1, 1,..., 1, S 0

Μέγεθος: px
Εμφάνιση ξεκινά από τη σελίδα:

Download "Solutions for exercises in chapter 1 = 2, 3, 1, 4 ; = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2 1 S 1 1 S 0 = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2, 1, 4,1,3. 1, 1,..., 1, S 0"

Transcript

1 E1.1 Verify that and Solutions for exercises in chapter 1 S 0 S 1 = 2, 3, 1, 4 (S 0 S 1 ) ( S 1 S 0 ) = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2, 1, 4, 1,3. S 0 S 1 = 2 S 0 S 1 = S 1 = 2, 3, 1, 4 ; (S 0 S 1 ) ( S 1 S 0 ) = 2 (S 0 S 1 ) ( S 1 S 0 ) = 2 2 S 0 S 1 2 S 1 S 0 = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2 1 S 1 1 S 0 = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2, 1, 4,1,3. E1.2 Prove that there is a sentential formula of each positive integer length. If m is a positive integer, then is a formula of length m, it is m 1 times {}}{ 1, 1,..., 1, S 0 m 1 times {}}{ S 0. E1.3 Prove that m is the length of a sentential formula not involving iff m is odd. Proof. : We prove by induction on ϕ that if ϕ is a sentential formula not involving, then the length of ϕ is odd. This is true of sentential variables, which have length 1. Suppose that it is true of ϕ and ψ, which have length 2m+1 and 2n+1 respectively. Then ϕ ψ, which is 1 ϕ ψ, has length 1 + 2m n + 1 = 2(m + n + 1) + 1, which is again odd. This finishes the inductive proof.. We construct formulas without with length any odd integer by induction. S 0 is a formula of length 1. If ϕ has been constructed of length 2m + 1, then S 0 ϕ, which is 1, S 0 ϕ, has length 2m + 3. This finishes the inductive construction. E1.4 Prove that a truth table for a sentential formula involving n basic formulas has 2 n rows. We prove this by induction on n. For n = 1, there are two rows. Assume that for n basic formulas there are 2 n rows. Given n + 1 basic formulas, let ϕ be one of them. For the others, by the inductive hypothesis there are 2 n rows. For each such row there are two possibilities, 0 or 1, for ϕ. So for the n + 1 basic formulas there are 2 n 2 = 2 n+1 rows. 1

2 E1.5 Use the truth table method to show that the formula (ϕ ψ) ( ϕ ψ) is a tautology. ϕ ψ ϕ ψ ϕ ϕ ψ (ϕ ψ) ( ϕ ψ) E1.6 Use the truth table method to show that the formula [ϕ (ψ χ)] [(ϕ ψ) (ϕ χ)] is a tautology. Let θ be the indicated formula. ϕ ψ χ ϕ ψ ϕ χ (ϕ ψ) (ϕ χ) ψ χ ϕ (ψ χ) θ E1.7 Use the truth table method to show that the formula (ϕ ψ) (ϕ ψ) is not a tautology. It is not necessary to work out the full truth table. ϕ ψ ϕ ψ ψ ϕ ψ (ϕ ψ) (ϕ ψ)

3 E1.8 Determine whether or not the following is a tautology: S 0 (S 1 (S 2 (S 3 S 1 ))). Suppose that f is an assignment making the indicated formula false; we work towards a contradiction. Thus (1) S 0 [f] = 1 and (2) (S 1 (S 2 (S 3 S 1 )))[f] = 0. From (2) we get (3) S 1 [f] = 1 and (4) (S 2 (S 3 S 1 ))[f] = 0. From (4) we get (5) S 2 [f] = 1 and (6) (S 3 S 1 )[f] = 0. From (6) we get S 1 [f] = 0, contradicting (3). E1.9 Determine whether or not the following is a tautology; an informal method is better than a truth table: ({[(ϕ ψ) ( χ θ)] χ} τ) [(τ ϕ) (θ ϕ)]. Suppose that f is an assignment which makes the given formula false; we want to get a contradiction. Thus we have (1) ({[(ϕ ψ) ( χ θ)] χ} τ)[f] = 1 and (2) [(τ ϕ) (θ ϕ)][f] = 0. By (2) we have (3) (τ ϕ)[f] = 1 and (4) (θ ϕ)[f] = 0. By (4) we have (5) θ[f] = 1 and (6) ϕ[f] = 0. By (3) and (6) we get (7) τ[f] = 0. By (1) and (7) we get (8) {[(ϕ ψ) ( χ θ)] χ}[f] = 0. 3

4 It follows that (9) [(ϕ ψ) ( χ θ)][f] = 1 and (10) χ[f] = 0. Now by (6) we have (11) (ϕ ψ)[f] = 1, and hence by (9), (12) ( χ θ)[f] = 1. By (5) we have (13) ( θ)[f] = 0, and hence by (12), (14) ( χ)[f] = 0. This contradicts (10). E1.10 Determine whether the following statements are logically consistent. If the contract is valid, then Horatio is liable. If Horation is liable, he will go bankrupt. Either Horatio will go bankrupt or the bank will lend him money. However, the bank will definitely not lend him money. Let S 0 correspond to the contract is valid, S 1 to Horatio is liable, S 2 to Horatio will go bankrupt, and S 3 to the bank will lend him money. Then we want to see if there is an assignment of values which makes the following sentence true: (S 0 S 1 ) (S 1 S 2 ) (S 2 S 3 ) S 3. We can let f(0) = f(1) = f(2) = 1 and f(3) = 0, and this gives the sentence the value 1. E1.11 Write out an actual proof for {ψ} ψ ϕ. This can be done by following the proof of Lemma 1.9, expanding it using the proof of the deduction theorem. Following the proof of Lemma 1.9, the following is a {ψ, ψ}-proof: (a) ψ (b) ψ ( ϕ ψ) (1) (c) ϕ ψ (a), (b), MP (d) ( ϕ ψ) (ψ ϕ) (3) (e) ψ ϕ (c), (d), MP (f) ψ (g) ϕ (e), (f), MP Now applying the proof of the deduction theorem, the following is a {ψ}-proof: (a) [ ψ [( ψ ψ) ψ]] [[ ψ ( ψ ψ)] ( ψ ψ)] (2) 4

5 (b) ψ [( ψ ψ) ψ] (1) (c) [ ψ ( ψ ψ)] ( ψ ψ) (a), (b), MP (d) ψ ( ψ ψ) (1) (e) ψ ψ (c), (d), MP (f) [ ψ ( ϕ ψ)] [ ψ [ ψ ( ϕ ψ)]] (1) (g) ψ ( ϕ ψ) (1) (h) ψ [ ψ ( ϕ ψ)]] (f), (g), MP (i) [( ϕ ψ) (ψ ϕ)] [ ψ [( ϕ ψ) (ψ ϕ)]] (1) (j) ( ϕ ψ) (ψ ϕ) (3) (k) ψ [( ϕ ψ) (ψ ϕ)] (i), (j), MP (l) [ ψ [( ϕ ψ) (ψ ϕ)]] [[ ψ ( ϕ ψ)] [ ψ (ψ ϕ)]] (2) (m) [ ψ ( ϕ ψ)] [ ψ (ψ ϕ)] (k), (l), MP (n) ψ (ψ ϕ) (g), (m), MP (o) ψ ( ψ ψ) (1) (p) ψ (q) ψ ψ (o), (p), MP (r) [ ψ (ψ ϕ)] [( ψ ψ) ( ψ ϕ)] (2) (s) ( ψ ψ) ( ψ ϕ) (n), (r), MP (t) ψ ϕ (q), (s), MP Solutions for exercises in Chapter 2 E2.1 Give an exact definition of a language for the structure (ω, <). The quadruple ({11},,, rnk), where rnk is the function with domain {11} such that rnk(11) = 2. E2.2 Give an exact definition of a language for the set A (no individual constants, function symbols, or relation symbols). The quadruple (,,, ). Note that the last is the empty function. E2.3 Describe a term construction sequence which shows that + v 0 v 0 v 1 is a term in the language for (R, +,, 0, 1, <). v 0, v 0 v 0, v 1,+ v 0 v 0 v 1. E2.4 In any first-order language, show that the sequence v 0, v 0 is not a term. Hint: use Proposition 2.2. Suppose that v 0, v 0 is a term. This contradicts Proposition 2.2(ii). E2.5 In the language for (ω, S, 0, +, ), show that the sequence +, v 0, v 1, v 2 is not a term. Here S(i) = i + 1 for any i ω. Hint: use Proposition 2.2. Suppose it is a term. By Proposition 2.2(ii)(c), there are terms σ, τ such that +, v 0, v 1, v 2 is + σ τ. Thus v 0, v 1, v 2 = σ τ. So the term v 0 is an initial segment of the term σ. By Proposition 2.2(iii) it follows that v 0 = σ. Hence v 1, v 2 = τ. This contradicts Proposition 2.2(ii). 5

6 E2.6 Prove Proposition 2.5. We show by complete induction on i that ϕ i Γ for all i < m. So, suppose that i < m and ϕ j Γ for all j < i. By the definition of formula construction sequence, we have the following cases. Case 1. ϕ i is an atomic formula. Then ϕ i Γ by (i). Case 2. There is a j < i such that ϕ i is ϕ j. By the inductive hypothesis, ϕ j Γ. Hence by (ii), ϕ i Γ. Case 2. There are j, k < i such that ϕ i is ϕ j ϕ k. By the inductive hypothesis, ϕ j Γ and ϕ k Γ. Hence by (iii), ϕ i Γ. Case 4. There exist j < i and k ω such that ϕ i is v k ϕ j. By the inductive hypothesis, ϕ j Γ. Hence by (iv), ϕ i Γ. This completes the inductive proof. E2.7 Show how the structure (ω, S, 0, +, ) can be put in the general framework of structures. (ω, S, 0, +, ) can be considered to be the structure (ω, Rel, Fcn, Cn ) where Rel =, Cn is the function with domain {8} such that Cn (8) = 0, and Fcn is the function with domain {6, 7, 9} such that Fcn (6) = S, Fcn (7) = +, and Fcn (9) =. E2.8 Prove that in the language for the structure (ω, +), a term has length m iff m is odd. First we show by induction on terms that every term has odd length. This is true for variables. Suppose that it is true for terms σ and τ. Then also σ + τ has odd length. Hence every term has odd length. Second we prove by induction on m that for all m, there is a term of length 2m + 1. A variable has length 1, so our assertion holds for m = 0. Assume that there is a term σ of length 2m + 1. Then σ + v 0 has length 2m + 3. This finishes the inductive proof. E2.9 Give a formula ϕ in the language for (Q, +, ) such that for any a : ω Q, (Q, +, ) = ϕ[a] iff a 0 = 1. Let ϕ be the formula v 1 [v 0 v 1 = v 1 ]. E2.10 Give a formula ϕ which holds in a structure, under any assignment, iff the structure has at least 3 elements. v 0 v 1 v 2 ( (v 0 = v 1 ) (v 0 = v 2 ) (v 1 = v 2 )). E2.11 Give a formula ϕ which holds in a structure, under any assignment, iff the structure has exactly 4 elements. v 0 v 1 v 2 v 3 ( (v 0 = v 1 ) (v 0 = v 2 ) (v 0 = v 3 ) (v 1 = v 2 ) (v 1 = v 3 ) (v 2 = v 3 ) v 4 (v 0 = v 4 v 1 = v 4 v 2 = v 4 v 3 = v 4 )). E2.12 Write a formula ϕ in the language for (ω, <) such that for any assignment a, (ω, <) = ϕ[a] iff a 0 < a 1 and there are exactly two integers between a 0 and a 1. v 0 < v 1 v 2 v 3 [v 0 < v 2 v 2 < v 3 v 3 < v 1 v 4 [v 0 < v 4 v 4 < v 1 v 4 = v 2 v 4 = v 3 ]]. 6

7 E2.13 Prove that the formula v 0 = v 1 (Rv 0 v 2 Rv 1 v 2 ) is universally valid, where R is a binary relation symbol. Let A be a structure and a : ω A an assignment. Suppose that A = (v 0 = v 1 )[a]. Then a 0 = a 1. Also suppose that A = Rv 0 v 2 [a]. Then (a 0, a 2 ) R A. Hence (a 1, a 2 ) R A. Hence A = Rv 1 v 2 [a], as desired. E2.14 Give an example showing that the formula is not universally valid. v 0 = v 1 v 0 (v 0 = v 1 ) Consider the structure A def = (ω, <), and let a : ω ω be defined by a(i) = 0 for all i ω. Then A = (v 0 = v 1 )[a]. Now A = (v 0 = v 1 )[a 0 1 ] since 1 0, so A = v 0(v 0 = v 1 )[a]. Therefore A = (v 0 = v 1 v 0 (v 0 = v 1 ))[a]. E2.15 Prove that v 0 v 1 ϕ v 1 v 0 ϕ is universally valid. Assume that a : ω A and A = v 0 v 1 ϕ[a]. Choose u A so that A = v 1 ϕ[a 0 u ]. In order to show that A = v 1 v 0 ϕ[a], let w A be given. Then A = ϕ 01 uw. It follows that A = v 0 ϕ[u 1 w ]. Hence A = v 1 v 0 ϕ[a], as desired. Solutions to exercises in Chapter 3 E3.1 Do the case Rσ 0...σ m 1 for some m-ary relation symbol and terms σ 0,..., σ m 1 in the proof of Theorem 3.1, (L3). We are assuming that v i does not occur in Rσ 0...σ m 1 ; hence it does not occur in any term σ i. A = (Rσ 0...σ m 1 )[a] iff iff iff σ0 A (a),..., σr m 1 (a) RA σ0 A (b),..., σr m 1 (b) RA (by Proposition 2.4) A = (Rσ 0...σ m 1 )[b]. E3.2 Prove that (L6) is universally valid, in the proof of Theorem 3.1. Assume that A = (σ = τ)[a] and A = (ρ = σ)[a]. Then σ A (a) = τ A (a) and ρ A (a) = σ A (a), so ρ A (a) = τ A (a), hence A = (ρ = τ)[a]. E3.3 Prove that (L8) is universally valid, in the proof of Theorem 3.1. Assume that A = (σ = τ)[a]. Then σ A (a) = τ A (a). Assume that A = (Rξ 0...ξ i 1 σξ i+1...ξ m 1 )[a]; hence ξ A 0 (a),..., ξ A i 1(a), σ A (a), ξ A i+1(a),..., ξ A m 1(a) R A ; hence ξ A 0 (a),..., ξa i 1 (a), τa (a), ξ A i+1 (a),..., ξa m 1 (a) RA ; hence A = (Rξ 0...ξ i 1 τξ i+1...ξ m 1 )[a]; 7

8 hence (L8) is universally valid. E3.4 Finish the proof of Proposition 3.9. If i = 0 then ϕ itself is the desired segment, unique by Proposition 2.6(iii). If i > 0 then actually i > 1 so that ϕ i is within ψ, and the inductive hypothesis applies. E3.5 Finish the proof of Proposition Suppose inductively that ϕ is ψ. Thus ϕ is 1 ψ. It follows that i > 0, so that ϕ i appears in ψ; then the inductive hypothesis applies. Suppose inductively that ϕ is ψ χ. Thus ϕ is 2 ψ χ. It follows that i > 0, so that ϕ i appears in ψ or χ; then the inductive hypothesis applies. Finally, suppose that ϕ is v s ψ with ψ a formula and s ω. Thus ϕ is 4, 5(s+1) ψ. Hence i > 0. If i = 1, then 5(s+1) is the desired segment, unique by Proposition 2.6(iii). Suppose that i > 1. So ϕ i is an entry in ψ and hence by the inductive assumption, there is a segment ϕ i, ϕ i+1,...ϕ m which is a term; this is also a segment of ϕ, and it is unique by Proposition 2.6(iii). E3.6 Indicate which occurrences of the variables are bound and which ones free for the following formulas. v 0 (v 0 < v 1 ) v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ). v 4 + v 2 = v 0 v 3 (v 0 = v 1 ). v 2 (v 4 + v 2 = v 0 ). First formula: the first and second occurrences of v 0 are bound, and the third one is free. The first occurrence of v 1 is free, and the other two are bound. Second formula: the occurrence of v 3 is bound. All other occurrences of variables are free. Third formula: the two occurrences of v 2 are bound. The other occurrences of variables are free. E3.7 Prove Proposition Induction on ϕ. Suppose that ϕ is ρ = ξ. Then by Proposition 3.13, σ occurs in ρ or ξ. Suppose that it occurs in ρ. Let ρ be obtained from ρ by replacing that occurrence of σ by τ. Then ρ is a term by Proposition Since ψ is ρ = ξ, ψ is a formula. The case in which σ occurs in ξ is similar. Now suppose that ϕ is Rη 0...η m 1 with R an m-ary relation symbol and η 0,..., η m 1 are terms. Then the occurrence of σ is within some η i. Let η i be obtained from η i by replacing that occurrence by τ. Now ψ is Rη 0...η i 1 η i...η m 1, so ψ is a formula. Now suppose that the result holds for ϕ, and ϕ is ϕ. Then σ occurs in ϕ, so if ψ is obtained from ϕ by replacing the occurrence of σ by τ, then ψ is a formula by the inductive assumption. Since ψ is ψ also ψ is a formula. Next, suppose that the result holds for ϕ and ϕ, and ϕ is ϕ ϕ. Then the occurrence of σ is within ϕ or is within ϕ. If it is within ϕ, let ψ be obtained from ϕ by replacing that occurrence of σ by τ. Then ψ is a formula by the inductive hypothesis. Since ψ is ψ ϕ, also ψ is a formula. If the occurrence is within ϕ, let ψ be obtained 8

9 from ϕ by replacing that occurrence of σ by τ. Then ψ is a formula by the inductive hypothesis. Since ψ is ϕ ψ, also ψ is a formula. Finally, suppose that the result holds for ϕ, and ϕ is v k ϕ. If i = 1, then σ is v k, and by hypothesis τ is some variable v l. Then ψ is v l ϕ, which is a formula. If i > 1, then σ occurs in ϕ, so if ψ is obtained from ϕ by replacing the occurrence of σ by τ, then ψ is a formula by the inductive assumption. Since ψ is v k ψ also ψ is a formula. E3.8 Indicate all free and bound occurrences of terms in the formula v 0 = v 1 + v 1 v 2 (v 0 + v 2 = v 1 ). v 0 is free in both of its occcurrences. v 1 is free in all three of its occurrences. v 2 is bound in both of its occurrences. v 1 + v 1 is free in its occurrence. v 0 + v 2 is bound in its occurrence. E3.9 Prove Proposition 3.17 Induction on ϕ. If ϕ is atomic, then ψ is equal to ϕ, and θ is equal to χ and hence is a formula. Suppose the result is true for ϕ and ϕ is ϕ. If ψ = ϕ, again the desired conclusion is clear. Otherwise the occurrence of ψ is within the subformula ϕ. If θ is obtained from ϕ by replacing that occurrence by χ, then θ is a formula by the inductive hypothesis. Since θ is θ, also θ is a formula. Now suppose the result is true for ϕ and ϕ, and ϕ is ϕ ϕ. If ψ = ϕ, again the desired conclusion is clear. Otherwise the occurrence of ψ is within the subformula ϕ or is within the subformula ϕ. If it is within ϕ and θ is obtained from ϕ by replacing that occurrence by χ, then θ is a formula by the inductive hypothesis. Since θ is θ ϕ, also θ is a formula. If it is within ϕ and θ is obtained from ϕ by replacing that occurrence by χ, then θ is a formula by the inductive hypothesis. Since θ is ϕ θ, also θ is a formula. Finally, suppose the result is true for ϕ and ϕ is v i ϕ. If ψ = ϕ, again the desired conclusion is clear. Otherwise the occurrence of ψ is within the subformula ϕ. If θ is obtained from ϕ by replacing that occurrence by χ, then θ is a formula by the inductive hypothesis. Since θ is v i θ, also θ is a formula. E3.10 Show that the condition in Lemma 3.15 that the resulting occurrence of τ is free is necessary. Hint: use Theorem 3.2; describe a specific formula of the type in Proposition 3.15, but with τ not free, such that the formula is not universally valid. Consider the language for (ω, S), and the formula v 0 = v 1 ( v 1 (Sv 0 = v 1 ) v 1 (Sv 1 = v 1 )). Taking an assignment a : ω ω with a 0 = a 1 makes this sentence false; hence it is not provable, by Theorem 3.2. E3.11 Do the case of implication in the proof of Lemma Suppose inductively that ϕ is χ θ. 9

10 Case 1. The occurrence of σ in ϕ is within χ. Let χ be obtained from χ by replacing that occurrence by τ, such that that occurrence is free in ψ, hence free in χ. By the inductive hypothesis, σ = τ (χ χ ). Since ψ is χ θ, a tautology gives the desired result. Case 2. The occurrence of σ in ϕ is within θ. Let θ be obtained from θ by replacing that occurrence by τ, such that that occurrence is free in ψ, hence free in θ. By the inductive hypothesis, σ = τ (θ θ ). Since ψ is χ θ, a tautology gives the desired result. E3.12 Prove that the hypothesis of Theorem 3.25 is necessary. Consider the formula v 0 v 1 (v 0 < v 1 ) v 1 (v 1 < v 1 ). This formula is not universally valid; it fails to hold in (ω, <), for example. E3.13 Prove Proposition Proof. By definition, v i ϕ is v i ϕ. Now ϕ ϕ by a tautology. Hence using generalization and (L2) we get v i ϕ v i ϕ. Hence another tautology yields v i ϕ v i ϕ, i.e., v i ϕ v i ϕ. E3.14 Prove Proposition Proof. v i ϕ is the formula v i ϕ, so a simple tautology gives the result. E3.15 Prove Proposition Proof. By Theorem 3.25 we have v i ϕ Subf v i σ ( ϕ). Since clearly Subfv i σ ( ϕ) is the same as Subf v i σ ϕ, a tautology gives Subfv i σ ϕ v iϕ. E3.16 Prove Proposition By Corollary 3.26 and Corollary E3.17 Prove Proposition Proof. ϕ v i ϕ. Now use a tautology. E3.18 Prove Proposition Assume ϕ ψ. By a tautology, ϕ ψ. Hence by generalization and (L2), v i ϕ v i ψ. Similarly, v i ψ v i ϕ. The exercise follows by a tautology. E3.19 Prove Proposition 3.42 Assume ϕ ψ. By a tautology, ϕ ψ. Hence by exercise E3.18, v i ϕ v i ψ. Now a tautology gives the desired result. E3.20 Prove that v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ) v 0 (v 0 = v 1 v 0 = v 2 ). 10

11 v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ) v 0 = v 1 ; Cor twice, taut. (1) v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ) v 0 = v 2 ; Thm (2) v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ) v 0 = v 2 ; (2), Cor. 3.26, taut. (3) v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ) v 0 = v 1 v 0 = v 2 ; (1), (3), taut. (4) v 0 v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ) v 0 (v 0 = v 1 v 0 = v 2 ); (4), (L2), taut. (5) v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ) v 0 (v 0 = v 1 v 0 = v 2 ). (5), Prop. 3.27, taut. E3.21 Prove that v 0 ( v 0 = v 1 v 0 = v 2 ) v 0 v 1 ( v 0 = v 1 ). v 0 (v 0 = v 1 v 0 = v 2 ) v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ); E3.20, taut. (1) v 0 (v 0 = v 1 v 0 = v 2 ) v 0 (v 0 = v 1 v 0 = v 2 ); Prop (2) (v 0 = v 1 v 0 = v 2 ) ( (v 0 = v 1 ) (v 0 = v 2 )); taut. (3) v 0 (v 0 = v 1 v 0 = v 2 ) v 0 ( (v 0 = v 1 ) (v 0 = v 2 )); (3), Prop (4) v 0 (v 0 = v 1 v 0 = v 2 ) v 0 ( (v 0 = v 1 ) (v 0 = v 2 )); (2), (4), taut. (5) v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ) v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ); Prop (6) v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ) v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ); (6), Prop (7) v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ) v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ); Prop (8) v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ) v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ) (7), (8), taut. (9) v 0 ( v 0 = v 1 v 0 = v 2 ) v 0 v 1 ( v 0 = v 1 ). (1), (5), (9), taut. Solutions to exercises in Chapter 4 E4.1 Suppose that Γ ϕ ψ, Γ ϕ ψ, and Γ ϕ ϕ. Prove that Γ is inconsistent. The formula ( ϕ ϕ) ϕ is a tautology. Hence by Lemma 3.3, Γ ( ϕ ϕ) ϕ. Since also Γ ϕ ϕ, it follows that Γ ϕ. Hence Γ ψ and Γ ψ. Hence by Lemma 4.1, Γ is inconsistent. E4.2 Let L be a language with just one non-logical constant, a binary relation symbol R. Let Γ consist of all sentences of the form v 1 v 0 [Rv 0 v 1 ϕ] with ϕ a formula with only v 0 free. Show that Γ is inconsistent. Hint: take ϕ to be Rv 0 v 0. By Theorem 3.25 we have (1) Γ v 0 [Rv 0 v 1 Rv 0 v 0 ] [Rv 1 v 1 Rv 1 v 1 ]. Now [Rv 1 v 1 Rv 1 v 1 ] (v 0 = v 0 ) is a tautology, so from (1) we obtain Γ v 0 [Rv 0 v 1 Rv 0 v 0 ] (v 0 = v 0 ); 11

12 then generalization gives Then by Proposition 3.37 we get Γ v 1 [ v 0 [Rv 0 v 1 Rv 0 v 0 ] (v 0 = v 0 )]. Γ v 1 v 0 [Rv 0 v 1 Rv 0 v 0 ] (v 0 = v 0 ). But the hypothesis here is a member of Γ, so we get Γ (v 0 = v 0 ). Hence by Lemma 4.1, Γ is inconsistent. Alternate proof (due to a couple of students). Suppose that Γ is consistent. By the completeness theorem let A be a model of Γ. Taking ϕ to be Rv 0 v 0, we get A = v 1 v 0 [Rv 0 v 1 Rv 0 v 0 ]. Let a : ω A be any assignment. Then by Proposition 2.8(iv) there is a b A such that A = v 0 [Rv 0 v 1 Rv 0 v 0 ][a 1 b ]. By the definition of satisfaction of, it follows that for any c A we have A = [Rv 0 v 1 Rv 0 v 0 ][a 0 c b 1 ]. Hence (c, b) RA iff (c, b) / R A, contradiction. E4.3 Show that the first-order deduction theorem fails if the condition that ϕ is a sentence is omitted. Hint: take Γ =, let ϕ be the formula v 0 = v 1, and let ψ be the formula v 0 = v 2. {v 0 = v 1 } v 0 = v 1 {v 0 = v 1 } v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ) {v 0 = v 1 } v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ) v 0 = v 2 by Theorem 3.25 {v 0 = v 1 } v 0 = v 2. On the other hand, let A be the structure with universe ω and define a = 0, 0, 1, 1,.... Clearly A = [v 0 = v 1 v 0 = v 2 ][a]. Hence v 0 = v 1 v 0 = v 2 by Theorem 3.2. E4.4 In the language for A def = (ω, S, 0, +, ), let τ be the term v 0 + v 1 v 2 and ν the term v 0 + v 2. Let a be the sequence 0, 1, 2,.... Let ρ be obtained from τ by replacing the occurrence of v 1 by ν. (a) Describe ρ as a sequence of integers. (b) What is ρ A (a)? (c) What is ν A (a)? (d) Describe the sequence a 1 as a sequence of integers. ν A (a) (e) Verify that ρ A (a) = τ A (a 1 ) (cf. Lemma 4.4.) ν A (a) (a) ρ is v 0 + (v 0 + v 2 ) v 2 ; as a sequence of integers it is 7, 5, 9, 7, 5, 15, 15. (b) ρ A (a) = 0 + (0 + 2) 2 = 4. (c) ν A (a) = = 2. (d) a 1 = 0, 2, 2, 3,.... ν A (a) (e) ρ A (a) = 4, as above; τ A (a 1 ) = = 4. ν A (a) 12

13 E4.5 In the language for A def = (ω, S, 0, +, ), let ϕ be the formula v 0 (v 0 v 1 = v 1 ), let ν be the formula v 1 + v 1, and let a = 1, 0, 1, 0,.... (a) Describe Subf v 1 ν ϕ as a sequence of integers (b) What is ν A (a)? (c) Describe a 1 ν A (a) (d) Determine whether A = Subf v 1 ν (e) Determine whether A = ϕ[a 1 ν A (a) as a sequence of integers. ϕ[a] or not. ] or not. (a) Subf v 1 ν ϕ is v 0 (v 0 (v 1 + v 1 ) = v 1 + v 1 ; as a sequence of integers it is 4, 5, 3, 9, 5, 7, 10, 10, 7, 10, 10. (b) ν A (a) = (v 1 + v 1 ) A ( 1, 0, 1, 0,... ) = = 0. (c) a 1 = 1, 0, 1, 0,.... ν A (a) (d) A = Subf v 1 ν ϕ[a] iff A = [ v 0(v 0 (v 1 +v 1 ) = v 1 +v 1 ][ 1, 0, 1, 0,... ] iff for all a ω, a (0 + 0) = 0 + 0; this is true. (e) A = ϕ[a 1 ] iff A = [ v 0(v 0 v 1 = v 1 ][ 1, 0, 1, 0,... ] iff for all a ω, a 0 = 0; ν A (a) this is true. E4.6 Show that the condition in Lemma 4.6 that no free occurrence of v i in ϕ is within a subformula of the form v k µ with v k a variable occurring in ν is necessary for the conclusion of the lemma. In the language for A = (ω, S, 0, +, ), let ϕ be the formula v 1 [Sv 1 = v 0 ], ν = v 1, and a = 1, 1,.... Note that the condition on v 0 fails. Now Subf v 0 v 1 ϕ is the formula v 1 [Sv 1 = v 1 ], and there is no a ω such that Sa = a, and hence A = Subf v 0 v 1 ϕ[a]. Also, ν A (a) = v1 A (a) = a 1 = 1, and hence a 0 = 1, 1,.... Since S0 = 1, it follows that ν A (a) A = ϕ[a 0 ν A (a) ]. E4.7 Let A be an L -structure, with L arbitrary. Define Γ = {ϕ : ϕ is a sentence and A = ϕ[a] for some a : ω A}. Prove that Γ is complete and consistent. Note by Lemma 4.4 that A = ϕ[a] for some a : ω A iff A = ϕ[a] for every a : ω A. Let ϕ be any sentence. Take any a : ω A. If A = ϕ[a], then ϕ Γ and hence Γ ϕ. Suppose that A = ϕ[a]. Then A = ϕ[a], hence ϕ Γ, hence Γ ϕ. This shows that Γ is complete. Suppose that Γ is not consistent. Then Γ (v 0 = v 0 ) by Lemma 4.1. Then Γ = (v 0 = v 0 ) by Theorem 3.2. Since A is a model of Γ, it is also a model of (v 0 = v 0 ), contradiction. E4.8 Call a set Γ strongly complete iff for every formula ϕ, Γ ϕ or Γ ϕ. Prove that if Γ is strongly complete, then Γ v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ). Assume that Γ is strongly complete. Then Γ v 0 = v 1 or Γ (v 0 = v 1 ). If Γ v 0 = v 1, then by generalization, Γ v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ). Suppose that Γ (v 0 = v 1 ). Then by 13

14 generalization, Γ v 0 (v 0 = v 1 ). By Theorem 3.25, Γ v 0 (v 0 = v 1 ) (v 1 = v 1 ). Hence Γ (v 1 = v 1 ). But also Γ v 1 = v 1 by Proposition 3.4, so Γ is inconsistent by Lemma 4.1, and hence again Γ v 0 v 1 (v 0 = v 1 ). E4.9 Prove that if Γ is rich, then for every term σ with no variables occurring in σ there is an individual constant c such that Γ σ = c. By richness we have Γ v 0 (v 0 = σ) c = σ for some individual constant c. Then using (L4) it follows that Γ c = σ. E4.10 Prove that if Γ is rich, then for every sentence ϕ there is a sentence ψ with no quantifiers in it such that Γ ϕ ψ. We proceed by induction on the number m of symbols,, in ϕ. (More exactly, by the number of the integers 1,2,4 that occur in the sequence ϕ.) If m = 0, then ϕ is atomic and we can take ψ = ϕ. Assume the result for m and suppose that ϕ has m + 1 integers 1,2,4 in it. Then there are three possibilities. First, ϕ = ϕ. Let ψ be a quantifier-free sentence such that Γ ϕ ψ. Then Γ ϕ ψ. Second, ϕ = (ϕ ϕ ). Choose quantifier-free sentences ψ and ψ such that Γ ϕ ψ and Γ ϕ ψ. Then Γ ϕ (ψ ψ ). Third, ϕ = v i ϕ. By richness, let c be an individual constant such that Γ v i ϕ Subf v i c ϕ. Then by Theorem 3.31 we get (1) Γ v i ϕ Subf v i c ϕ. Now Subf v i c ϕ has only m integers 1,2,4 in it, so by the inductive hypothesis there is a sentence ψ with no quantifiers in it such that Γ Subf v i c ϕ ψ and hence (2) Γ Subf v i c ϕ ψ. From (1) and (2) and a tautology we get Γ v i ϕ ψ. Then by Proposition 3.31, Γ v i ϕ ψ, finishing the inductive proof. E4.11 Describe sentences in a language for ordering which say that < is a linear ordering and there are infinitely many elements. Prove that the resulting set Γ of sentences is not complete. Let Γ consist of the following sentences: v 0 (v 0 < v 0 ); v 0 v 1 v 2 [v 0 < v 1 v 1 < v 2 v 0 < v 2 ]; v 0 v 1 [v 0 < v 1 v 0 = v 1 v 1 < v 0 ]; (v i = v j ) for every positive integer n. i<j<n The following sentence ϕ holds in (Q, <) but not in (ω, <): v 0 v 1 [v 0 < v 1 v 2 (v 0 < v 2 v 2 < v 1 )]. Since ϕ does not hold in (ω, <), we have Γ ϕ, by Theorem 4.2. But since ϕ holds in (Q, <), we also have Γ ϕ by Theorem 4.2. So Γ is not complete. 14

15 E4.12 Prove that if a sentence ϕ holds in every infinite model of a set Γ of sentences, then there is an m ω such that it holds in every model of Γ with at least m elements. Suppose that ϕ holds in every infinite model of a set Γ of sentences, but for every m ω there is a model M of Γ with at least m elements such that ϕ does not hold in M. Let be the following set: Γ (v i = v j ) : n a positive integer { ϕ}. i<j<n Our hypothesis implies that every finite subset of has a model; for if m is the maximum of all n such that the above big conjunction is in, then the hypothesis yields a model of. By the compactness theorem we get a model N of. Thus N is an infinite model of Γ in which ϕ does not hold, contradiction. E4.13 Let L be the language of ordering. Prove that there is no set Γ of sentences whose models are exactly the well-ordering structures. Suppose there is such a set. Let us expand the language L to a new one L by adding an infinite sequence c m, m ω, of individual constants. Then consider the following set Θ of sentences: all members of Γ, plus all sentences c m+1 < c m for m ω. Clearly every finite subset of Θ has a model, so let A = (A, <, a i ) i<ω be a model of Θ itself. (Here a i is the 0-ary function, i.e., element of A, corresponding to c i.) Then a 0 > a 1 > ; so {a i : i ω} is a nonempty subset of A with no least element, contradiction. E4.14 Suppose that Γ is a set of sentences, and ϕ is a sentence. Prove that if Γ = ϕ, then = ϕ for some finite Γ. We prove the contrapositive: Suppose that for every finite subset of Γ, = ϕ. Thus every finite subset of Γ { ϕ} has a model, so Γ { ϕ} has a model, proving that Γ = ϕ. E4.15 Suppose that f is a function mapping a set M into a set N. Let R = {(a, b) : a, b M and f(a) = f(b)}. Prove that R is an equivalence relation on M. If a M, then f(a) = f(a), so (a, a) R. Thus R is reflexive on M. Suppose that (a, b) R. Then f(a) = f(b), so f(b) = f(a) and hence (b, a) R. Thus R is symmetric. Suppose that (a, b) R and (b, c) R. Then f(a) = f(b) and f(b) = f(c), so f(a) = f(c) and hence (a, c) R. E4.16 Suppose that R is an equivalence relation on a set M. Prove that there is a function f mapping M into some set N such that R = {(a, b) : a, b M and f(a) = f(b)}. Let N be the collection of all equivalence classes under R. For each a M let f(a) = [a] R. Then (a, b) R iff a, b M and [a] R = [b] R iff a, b M and f(a) = f(b). E4.17 Let Γ be a set of sentences in a first-order language, and let be the collection of all sentences holding in every model of Γ. Prove that = {ϕ : ϕ is a sentence and Γ ϕ}. For, suppose that ϕ. To prove that Γ ϕ we use the compactness theorem, proving that Γ = ϕ. Let A be any model of Γ. Since ϕ, it follows that A is a model of Γ, as desired. 15

16 For, suppose that ϕ is a sentence and Γ ϕ. Then by the easy direction of the completeness theorem, Γ = ϕ. That is, every model of Γ is a model of ϕ. Hence ϕ. Solutions, Chapter 6 E6.1 Prove that if f : A B and C i : i I is a system of subsets of A, then f [ i I C ] i = i I f[c i]. [ ] x f C i i I iff x rng ( f i I C i ) iff y i I C i [f(y) = x] iff i I y C i [f(y) = x] iff i I[x rng(f C i )] iff i I[x f[c i ]] iff x i I f[c i ]. E6.2 Prove that if f : A B and C, D A, then f[c D] f[c] f[d]. Give an example showing that equality does not hold in general. Take any x f[c D]. Choose y C D such that x = f(y). Since y C, we have x f[c]. Similarly, x f[d]. So x f[c] f[d]. Since x is arbitrary, this shows that f[c D] f[c] f[d]. For the required example, let dmn(f) = {a, b} with a b and with f(a) = a = f(b). Let C = {a} and D = {b}. Then C D =, so f[c D] =, while f[c] = {a} = f[d] and hence f[c] f[d] = {a}. So f[c D] f[c] f[d]. E6.3 Given f : A B and C, D A, compare f[c\d] and f[c]\f[d]: prove the inclusions (if any) which hold, and give counterexamples for the inclusions that fail to hold. We claim that f[c]\f[d] f[c\d]. For, suppose that x f[c]\f[d]. Choose c C such that x = f(c). Since x / f[d], we have c / D. So c C\D and hence x f[c\d], proving the claim. The other inclusion does not hold. For, take the same f, C, D as for exercise E6.2. Then C\D = {a} and so f[c\d]. But f[c] = {a} = f[d], so f[c]\f[d] =. E6.4 Prove that if f : A B and C i : i I is a system of subsets of B, then f [ 1 i I C ] i = i I f 1 [C i ]. For any b B we have b f 1 [ i I C i ] iff f(b) i I C i iff i I[f(b) C i ] 16

17 iff i I[b f 1 [C i ]] iff b i I f 1 [C i ]. E6.5 Prove that if f : A B and C i : i I is a system of subsets of B, then f [ 1 i I C ] i = i I f 1 [C i ]. For any a, a f 1 [ i I C i ] iff f(a) i I C i iff i I[f(a) C i ] iff i I[a f 1 [C i ]] iff a i I f 1 [C i ]. E6.6 Prove that if f : A B and C, D B, then f 1 [C\D] = f 1 [C]\f 1 [D]. For any a, a f 1 [C\D] iff f(a) C\D E6.7 Prove that if f : A B and C A, then iff iff iff f(a) C and f(a) / D a f 1 [C] and a / f 1 [D] a f 1 [C]\f 1 [D]. {b B : f 1 [{b}] C} = B\f[A\C]. First suppose that b is in the left side; but suppose also, aiming for a contradiction, that b f[a\c]. Say b = f(a), with a A\C. Then a f 1 [{b}], so a C, contradiction. Second, suppose that b is in the right side. Take any a f 1 [{b}]. Then f(a) = b, and it follows that a C, as desired. E6.8 For any sets A, B define A B = (A\B) (B\A); this is called the symmetric difference of A and B. Prove that if A, B, C are given sets, then A (B C) = (A B) C. Let D = A B C, A = D\A, B = D\B, and C = D\C. Then A B = (A B ) (B A ); (A B) = ((A B ) (B A )) = (A B ) (B A ) = (A B) (B A) = (A B ) (A B). 17

18 These equations hold for any sets A, B. Now A (B C) = (A (B C) ) ((B C) A = (A ((B C ) (B C))) (((B C ) (C B )) A ) = (A B C ) (A B C) (A B C ) (A B C). This holds for any sets A, B, C. Hence (A B) C = C (A B) = (C A B ) (C A B) (C A B ) (C A B) = A (B C). E6.9 For any set A let Id A = { x, x : x A}. Justify this definition on the basis of the axioms. Id A = {y A A : x A[y = x, x ]}. E6.10 Suppose that f : A B. Prove that f is surjective iff there is a g : B A such that f g = Id B. Note: the axiom of choice might be needed. : given b B, we have b = (f g)(b) = f(g(b)); so f is surjective. : Assume that f is surjective. Let A = {{(b, a) : a A, f(a) = b} : b B}. Each member of A is nonempty; for let x A. Choose b B such that x = {(b, a) : a A, f(a) = b}. Choose a A such that f(a) = b. So (b, a) x. The members of A are pairwise disjoint: suppose x, y A with x y. Choose b, c so that x = {(b, a) : a A, f(a) = b} and y = {(b, a) : a A, f(a) = c}. If u x y, then there exist a, a A such that u = (b, a), f(a) = b, and also (u = (c, a ), f(a ) = c. So by Theorem 6.3, b = c. But then x = y, contradiction. Now by the axiom of choice, let C have exactly one element in common with each member of A. Then define g = {(b, a) C : a A, f(a) = b}. Now g is a function. For, suppose that (b, a), (b, a ) g. Let x = {(b, a ) : a A, f(a ) = b}. Then (b, a), (b, a ) C x, so (b, a) = (b, a ). Hence a = a. Clearly g B A. Next, dmn(g) = B, for suppose that b B. Choose x C {(b, a ) : a A, f(a ) = b}; say x = (b, a) with a A, f(a) = b. Then x g and so b dmn(g). Thus g : B A. Take any b B, and let g(b) = a. So (b, a) g and hence f(a) = b. So f g = Id B. 18

19 E6.11 Let A be a nonempty set. Suppose that f : A B. Prove that f is injective iff there is a g : B A such that g f = Id A. First suppose that f is injective. Fix a A, and let g = f 1 {(b, a) : b B\rng(f)}. Then g is a function. In fact, suppose that (b, c), (b, d) g. If both are in f 1, then (c, b(, (d, b) f, so f(c) = b = f(d) and hence c = d since f is injective. If (b, c) f 1 and b B\rng(f), the (c, b) f, so b rng(f), contradiction. If (b, c), (b, d) / f 1, then c = d = a. Clearly then g : B A. For any a A we have (a, f(a)) f, hence (f(a), a) f 1 g, and so g(f(a)) = a. Second, suppose that g : B A and g f = Id A. Suppose that f(a) = f(a ). Then a = (g f)(a) = g(f(a)) = g(f(a )) = (g f)(a ) = a. E6.12 Suppose that f : A B. Prove that f is a bijection iff there is a g : B A such that f g = Id B and g f = Id A. Prove this without using the axiom of choice. : Assume that f is a bijection. By E6.11 there is a g : B A such that g f = Id A. We claim that f g = Id B. Since f is a bijection, the relation f 1 is also a bijection. Now for any b B, (f g)(b) = f(g(b)) = f(g(f(f 1 (b)))) = f((g f)(f 1 (b))) = f(f 1 (b)) = b. So f g = Id B, as desired. : Assume that g is as indicated. Then f is injective, since f(a) = f(b) implies that a = g(f(a)) = g(f(a )) = a. And f is surjective, since for a given b B we have f(g(b)) = b. E6.13 For any sets R, S define R S = {(x, z) : y((x, y) R (y, z) S)}. Justify this definition on the basis of the axioms. R S = {(x, z) dmn(r) rng(s) : y((x, y) R (y, z) S)}. E6.14 Suppose that f, g : A A. Prove that is a function. (A A)\[((A A)\f) ((A A)\g)] Suppose that (x, y), (x, z) are in the indicated set, with y z. By symmetry say f(x) y. Then (x, y) [(A A)\f], so it follows that (y, z) g, as otherwise (x, z) [((A A)\f) ((A A)\g)]. Hence (y, y) / g, so (x, y) [((A A)\f) ((A A)\g)], contradiction. 19

20 E6.15 Suppose that f : A B is a surjection, g : A C, and x, y A[f(x) = f(y) g(x) = g(y)]. Prove that there is a function h : B C such that h f = g. Define h as a set of ordered pairs. Let h = {(f(a), g(a)) : a A}. Then h is a function, for suppose that (x, y), (x, z) h. Choose a, a A so that x = f(a), y = g(a), x = f(a ), and y = g(a ). Thus f(a) = f(a ), so g(a) = g(a ), as desired. Since f is a surjection it is clear that dmn(h) = B. Clearly rng(h) C. So h : B C. If a A, then (f(a), b(a)) h, hence h(f(a)) = g(a). This shows that h f = g. E6.16 The statement A A B B(A B) implies that A B is slightly wrong. Fix it, and prove the result. If A has a nonempty member and B is empty, the implication does not hold. Add the hypothesis B. Suppose that a A and B B; we want to show that a B. Choose A A such that a A. Since A B, we have a B. E6.17 Suppose that A A B B(A B). Prove that A B. Suppose that a A ; we want to show that a B. Choose A A such that a A. Then choose B B such that A B. Then a B. Hence a B. E6.18 The statement A A B B(B A) implies that B A. is slightly wrong. Fix it, and prove the result. If A is empty and B is nonempty, the statement is false. Fix it by adding the hypothesis that A is nonempty. Suppose that b B and A A ; we want to show that b A. Choose B B such that B A. Now b B since b B, so b A. Solutions, exercises in Chapter 7 E7.1 Prove that if x is an ordinal, then x is transitive and (x, {(y, z) x x : y z}) is a well-ordered set. By definition, x is transitive. Let R = {(y, z) x x : y z}). Obviously R is a relation. By definition, R x x. R is irreflexive on x by Theorem 7.5. R is transitive since x is transitive. R is linear on x by Theorem 7.7. The final well-ordering property follows from Theorem E7.2 Assume that x is transitive and (x, {(y, z) x x : y z}) is a well-ordered set. Prove that for all y, z x, either y = z or y z or z y. This is obvious. E7.3 Assume that x is transitve and for all y, z x, either y = z or y z or z y. Prove that for all y, if y x and y is transitive, then y x. Hint: apply the foundation axiom to x\y. 20

21 Assume the hypothesis, and suppose that y x and y is transitive. Choose z x\y such that z (x\y) =. If u y, then u x since y x. So u, z x, so by hypothesis we have u z, u = z, or z u. Now u z since z / y and u y. And z / u, since z u would imply, because y is transitive and u y, that z y, which is not true. Hence u z. This is true for any u y. So y z. Clearly also z y, so y = z x. E7.4 Assume that x is transitive and for all y, if y x and y is transitive, then y x. Show that x is an ordinal. Hint: let y = {z x : z is an ordinal}, and get a contradiction from the assumption that y x. Assume the hypothesis. Let y = {z x : z is an ordinal}. So y x. Suppose that y x. Now y is transitive, for assume that z y. Thus z x and z is an ordinal. Suppose that w z. Then w x since x is transitive, and w is an ordinal since z is an ordinal. So w y. Thus, indeed, y is transitive. So by assumption y x. Now y is a transitive set of transitive sets, so y is an ordinal. It follows that y y, contradiction. This proves that x = y. So x is a transitive set of transitive sets, and hence x is an ordinal. E7.5 Show that if x is an ordinal, then the following two conditions hold: (i) For all y x, either y {y} = x or y {y} x. (ii) For all y x, either y = x or y x. Assume that x is an ordinal. Then (i) holds by Proposition Now suppose that y x. If z y, choose w y such that z w. Then also w x, so z x since x is transitive. This shows that y x. By Proposition 7.3, y is an ordinal. Hence by Proposition 7.8, y x. E7.6 Assume the two conditions of exercise E7.5. Show that x is an ordinal. Hint: Show that there is an ordinal α not in x. Taking such an ordinal α, show that there is a least β α {α} such that β / x. Work with such a β to show that x is an ordinal. By Theorem 7.6 there is an ordinal α not in x. Then by Theorem 7.13 there is a least β α {α} such that β / x. Now we have two possibilities: Case 1. β = β. Now β x, so by (ii) second clause, since β = β / x we have x = β, hence x is an ordinal, as desired. Case 2. β = ( β) + 1. Thus β is an ordinal smaller than β, so it is in x. By (i), since β = β + 1 / x we have x = ( β) + 1, hence x is an ordinal. Solutions, exercises in Chapter 8 E8.1 Give an example of A,R such that R is not well-founded on A and is not set-like on A. We take On and R, where R = {(α, β) : α > β}. As shown after 8.2, R is not set-like on On. It is also not well-founded on On, since ω is a nonempty set of ordinals, but if m ω then (m + 1, m) R, so that ω does not have an R-minimal element. E8.2 Give an example of A,R such that R is not well-founded on A but is set-like on A. Give one example with R and A are proper classes, and one example where they are sets. 21

22 Both are sets: let A = ω and R = {(m, n) : m, n ω and m > n. Then ω does not have an R-minimal element, since for any m ω we have (m + 1, m) R. Both are proper classes: let A = On and let R = {(m, n) : m, n ω and m > n} {(α, β) : α < β}. E8.3 Give an example of A,R such that R is well-founded on A but is not set-like on A. Let A = V and R = {(a, ) : a V, a }. Thus pred AR ( ) = V, so R is not set-like on V. Now let X be a nonempty set. If X = { }, then X and a X[(a, ) / R]. If X { }, take any a X\{ }. Then b X[(b, a) / R]. E8.4 Suppose that R is a class relation contained in A A, x A, and v pred AR (x). Prove by induction on n that if n ω\1, f is a function with domain n + 1, i < n[(f(i), f(i + 1)) R] and f(n) = v, then f(0) pred AR (x). Suppose that R is a class relation contained in A A, x A, and v pred AR (x). We take n = 1 in the condition to be proved. So, suppose that f is a function with domain 2 such that i < 1[(f(i), f(i + 1)) R] and f(1) = v. Thus (f(0), v) R, so f(0) pred AR (v). By Lemma 8.3(ii), f(0) pred AR (x). Now suppose that if n ω\1, f is a function with domain n + 1, i < n[(f(i), f(i + 1)) R] and f(n) = v, then f(0) pred AR (x). Suppose also now that f is a function with domain n + 2, i < n + 1[(f(i), f(i + 1)) R] and f(n + 1) = v. Define g with domain n + 1 by setting g(i) = f(i + 1) for all i < n + 1. Then i < n[(g(i), g(i + 1)) = (f(i + 1), f(i + 2)) R] and g(n) = f(n + 1) = v. Hence by the inductive assumption, f(1) = g(0) pred AR (x). We also have (f(0), f(1)) R, so by Lemma 8.3(ii), f(0) pred AR (x). E8.5 Suppose that R is a class relation contained in A A, (u, v) R, and (v, w) R. Show that (u, w) R. Assume that R is a class relation contained in A A, (u, v) R, and (v, w) R. Since (u, v) R, there exist n ω\1 and a function f with domain n + 1 such that i < n[(f(i), f(i + 1)) R, f(0) = u, and f(n) = v. From exercise E8.4 it follows that (u, w) R. E8.6 Give an example of a proper class X which has a proper class of -minimal elements. Let X = {{α} : α 2}. We claim that all elements of X are -minimal. Suppose that α, β 2 and {α} {β}. Then {α} = β, Since β 2 we have 0, 1 β, so 0 = α = 1, contradiction. E8.7 Give an example of a proper class relation R contained in A A for some proper class A, and a class function G mapping A V into V such that R is set-like on A but not well-founded on A and there is no class function F mapping A into V such that F(a) = G(a,F pred AR (a)) for all a A. Let A = On and R = {(m, n) : m, n ω and m > n} {(α, β) : ω α < β}. 22

23 Thus R is a proper class relation contained in A A. Clearly R is set-like on On but it is not well-founded on On. Define G : On V V by setting { {a(α + G(α, a) = 1)} if α ω and a is a function with domain {m ω : m > α}, otherwise. Suppose that F : A V is such that F(α) = G(α,F pred OnR (α)) for all α On. Let f = F ω. Choose b rng(f) such that b rng(f) =. Say b = f(m) with m ω. Now f(m) = F(m) = G(m,F pred OnR (m)) = G(m,F {n : n ω, n > m}) = {F(m + 1)} = {f(m + 1)}, so that f(m + 1) f(m) rng(f), contradiction. E8.8 Give an example of a proper class relation R contained in some A A for some proper class A and a class function G mapping A V into V such that R is set-like on A but not well-founded on A but still there is a class function F mapping A into V such that F(a) = G(a,F pred AR (a)) for all a A. Let A and R be as in exercise E8.7, but define G(α, a) = α for all α On and all a V. Then the function F : On V such that F(α) = α for all α On is as desired. Solutions to exercises in chapter 9 E9.1 Let (A, <) be a well order. Suppose that B A and b B a A[a < b a B]. Prove that there is an element a A such that B = {b A : b < a}. Let a be the least element of A\B. We claim that a is as desired. For, if b B, then it cannot happen that a b, since this would imply that a B; so b < a. And if b < a, then b B by the minimality of a. E9.2 Let (A, <) be a well order. Suppose that B A and b B a A[a < b a B]. Prove that (A, <) is not isomorphic to (B, <). Suppose that f is such an isomorphism from (A, <) onto (B, <). By exercise E9.1, let a A be such that B = {x A : x < a}. By Proposition 9.11, a f(a), contradicting the assumption that f maps into B. E9.3 Suppose that f is a one-one function mapping an ordinal α onto a set A. Define a relation which is a subset of A A such that (A, <) is a well-order and f is an isomorphism of (α, <) onto (A, ). Define = {(a, b) A A : f 1 (a) < f 1 (b)}. We check that (A, <) is a well-order. If a A and a a, then f 1 (a) < f a (a), contradiction. So is irreflexive. Suppose that a b c. Then f 1 (a) < f 1 (b) < f 1 (c), so f 1 (a) < f 1 (c) and hence a c. So is transitive. Now given a, b A, either f 1 (a) < f 1 (b) or f 1 (a) = f 1 (b) or f 1 (b) < f 1 (a), so a b or a = b or b a. Thus (A, ) is a linear order. Finally, suppose that X A. Then f 1 [X], so let ξ be the least element of f 1 [X]. Then f(ξ) X. Suppose that b X. Then f 1 (b) f 1 [X], so ξ f 1 (b). Hence 23

24 f(ξ) b. This shows that f(ξ) is the -least element of X. We have shown that (A, ) is a well-order. We are given that f is a bijection from α onto A. If ξ, η α and ξ < η, then f(ξ) f(η). If f(ξ) f(η), then ξ < η. Thus f is an isomorphism. E9.4 Prove that 1 + m = m + 1 for any m ω. (Ordinary) induction on m = 1 = using Theorem 9.21(vi). Assume that 1 + m = m + 1. Then 1 + (m + 1) = (1 + m) + 1 = (m + 1) + 1. E9.5 Prove that m + n = n + m for any m, n ω. With m fixed, induction on n. 0 + m = m = m + 0 using Theorem 9.21(vi). Assume that m + n = n + m. Then (n + 1) + m = n + (1 + m) = n + (m + 1) (by exercise E9.4) = (n + m) + 1 = (m + n) + 1 = m + (n + 1). E9.6 Prove that ω α iff 1 + α = α. First note that 1 + ω = m ω (1 + m) = m ω (m + 1) = ω, using Theorem 9.21(vi). : Assume that ω α. By Theorem 9.21(vii) let δ be such that ω + δ = α. Then 1 + α = 1 + (ω + δ) = (1 + ω) + δ = ω + δ = α. : It suffices to show that if m < ω then 1 + m m. This is true by Theorem 9.21(vi). E9.7 For any ordinals α, β let α β = (α {0}) (β {1}). We define a relation as follows. For any x, y α β, x y iff one of the following three conditions holds: (i) There are ξ, η < α such that x = (ξ, 0), y = (η, 0), and ξ < η. (ii) There are ξ, η < β such that x = (ξ, 1), y = (η, 1), and ξ < η. (ii) There are ξ < α and η < β such that x = (ξ, 0) and y = (η, 1). Prove that (α β, ) is a well order which is isomorphic to α + β. Clearly is a well-order. We show by transfinite induction on β, with α fixed, that (α β, ) is order isomorphic to α + β. For β = 0 we have α + β = α + 0 = α, while α β = α 0 = α {0}. Clearly ξ (ξ, 0) defines an order-isomorphism from α onto (α {0}, ). So our result holds for β = 0. Assume it for β, and suppose that f is an order-isomorphism from α + β onto (α β, ). Now the last element of α (β + 1) is (β, 1), and the last element of α + (β + 1) is α + β, so the function f {(α + β, (β, 1))} is an order-isomorphism from α + (β + 1) onto α (β + 1). Now assume that β is a limit ordinal, and for each γ < β, the ordinal α + γ is isomorphic to α γ. For each such γ let f γ be the unique isomorphism from α + γ onto 24

25 α γ. Note that if γ < δ < β, then f δ γ is an isomorphism from α +γ onto α γ; hence f δ γ = f γ. It follows that is an isomorphism from α + β onto α β, finishing the inductive proof. E9.8 Given ordinals α, β, we define the following relation on α β: γ<β (ξ, η) (ξ, η ) iff ((ξ, η) and (ξ, η ) are in α β and: f γ η < η, or (η = η and ξ < ξ ). We may say that this is the anti-dictionary or anti-lexicographic order. Show that the set α β under the anti-lexicographic order is a well order which is isomorphic to α β. We may assume that α 0. It is straightforward to check that is a well-order. Now we define, for any (ξ, η) α β, f(ξ, η) = α η + ξ. We claim that f is the desired order-isomorphism from α β onto α β. If (ξ, η) α β, then f(ξ, η) = α η + ξ < α η + α = α (η + 1) α β. Thus f maps into α β. To show that f is one-one, suppose that (ξ, η), (ξ, η ) α β and f(ξ, η) = f(ξ, η ). Then by Theorem 9.26, (ξ, η) = (ξ, η ). So f is one-one. To show that f maps onto α β, let γ < α β. Choose ξ and η so that γ = α η + ξ with ξ < α. Now η < β, as otherwise γ = α η + ξ α η α β. It follows that f(ξ, η) = α η + ξ = γ. so f is onto. Finally, we show that the order is preserved. Suppose that (ξ, η) (ξ, η ). Then one of these cases holds: Case 1. η < η. Then f(ξ, η) = α η + ξ < α η + α = α (η + 1) α η α η + ξ = f(ξ, η ), as desired. Case 2. η = η and ξ < ξ. Then f(ξ, η) < f(ξ, η ). Now it follows that f is the desired isomorphism. E9.9 Suppose that α and β are ordinals, with β 0. We define α β w = {f α β : {ξ < α : f(ξ) 0} is finite}. 25

26 For f, g α β w we write f g iff f g and f(ξ) < g(ξ) for the greatest ξ < α for which f(ξ) g(ξ). Prove that ( α β w, ) is a well-order which is order-isomorphic to the ordinal exponent β α. (A set X is finite iff there is a bijection from some natural number onto X.) If α = 0, then β α = 1, and α β w also has only one element, the empty function (= the emptyset). So, assume that α 0. If β = 1, then α β w has only one member, namely the function with domain α whose value is always 0. This is clearly order-isomorphic to 1, as desired. So, suppose that β > 1. Now we define a function f mapping β α into α β w. Let f(0) be the member of α β w which takes only the value 0. Now suppose that 0 < ε < β α. By Theorem 9.29 write ε = β γ(0) δ(0) + β γ(1) δ(1) + + β γ(m 1) δ(m 1), where ε γ(0) > γ(1) > > γ(m 1) and 0 < δ(i) < β for each i < m. Note that β γ(0) ε < β α, so γ(0) < α. Then we define, for any ζ < α, (f(ε))(ζ) = { 0 if ζ / {γ(0),..., γ(m 1)}, δ(i) if ζ = γ(i) with i < m. Clearly f(ε) α β w. To see that f maps onto α β w, suppose that x α β w. If x takes only the value 0, then f(0) = x. Suppose that x takes on some nonzero value. Let {ξ < α : x(ξ) 0} = {γ(0), γ(1),..., γ(m 1)}, where γ(0) > γ(1) > > γ(m 1). Let δ(i) = x(γ(i)) for each i < m, and let ε = β γ(0) δ(0) + β γ(1) δ(1) + + β γ(m 1) δ(m 1). Clearly then f(ε) = x. Now we complete the proof by showing that for any ε, θ < β α, ε < θ iff f(ε) < f(θ). This equivalence is clear if one of ε, θ is 0, so suppose that both are nonzero. Write ε = β γ(0) δ(0) + β γ(1) δ(1) + + β γ(m 1) δ(m 1), where α γ(0) > γ(1) > > γ(m 1) and 0 < δ(i) < β for each i < m, and θ = β γ (0) δ (0) + β γ (1) δ (1) + + β γ (n 1) δ (n 1), where α γ (0) > γ (1) > > γ (n 1) and 0 < δ (i) < β for each i < n. By symmetry we may suppose that m n. Note that N(β, m, γ, δ), k(β, m, γ, δ) = ε, N(β, n, γ, δ ), and k(β, n, γ, δ ) = θ. We now consider several possibilities. Case 1. ε = θ. Then clearly f(ε) = f(θ). Case 2. γ γ, δ δ, and m < n. Thus ε < θ. Also, γ (m) is the largest ξ < α such that (f(ε))(ξ) (f(θ))(ξ), and (f(ε))(ξ) = 0 < δ (m) = (f(θ))(γ (m)), so f(ε) < f(θ). 26

Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set

Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set May 6, 2008 Abstract A set of first-order formulas, whatever the cardinality of the set of symbols, is equivalent to an independent

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit

Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit Ting Zhang Stanford May 11, 2001 Stanford, 5/11/2001 1 Outline Ordinal Classification Ordinal Addition Ordinal Multiplication Ordinal

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

2 Composition. Invertible Mappings

2 Composition. Invertible Mappings Arkansas Tech University MATH 4033: Elementary Modern Algebra Dr. Marcel B. Finan Composition. Invertible Mappings In this section we discuss two procedures for creating new mappings from old ones, namely,

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers

Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers There are two kinds of number.. Ordinal numbers (0th), st, 2nd, 3rd, 4th, 5th,..., ω, ω +,... ω2, ω2+,... ω 2... answers to the question What position is... in a sequence? What

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions

C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions Paul Liu November 15, 2007 Note that these are sample solutions only; in many cases there were many acceptable answers. 1 Reynolds Problem 10.1 1.1 Normal-order

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

EE512: Error Control Coding

EE512: Error Control Coding EE512: Error Control Coding Solution for Assignment on Finite Fields February 16, 2007 1. (a) Addition and Multiplication tables for GF (5) and GF (7) are shown in Tables 1 and 2. + 0 1 2 3 4 0 0 1 2 3

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Lecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic

Lecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic Lecture 2 Soundness and completeness of propositional logic February 9, 2004 1 Overview Review of natural deduction. Soundness and completeness. Semantics of propositional formulas. Soundness proof. Completeness

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER

ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER Abstract. We define ordinal arithmetic and show laws of Left- Monotonicity, Associativity, Distributivity, some minor related properties and the Cantor Normal Form.

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Matrices and Determinants

Matrices and Determinants Matrices and Determinants SUBJECTIVE PROBLEMS: Q 1. For what value of k do the following system of equations possess a non-trivial (i.e., not all zero) solution over the set of rationals Q? x + ky + 3z

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation

A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation International Mathematical Forum, 5, 2010, no. 67, 3301-3307 A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy Equivalence Relation D. K. Basnet Dept. of Mathematics, Assam University Silchar-788011, Assam, India dkbasnet@rediffmail.com

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Thus X is nonempty by supposition. By (i), let x be a minimal element of X. Then let

Thus X is nonempty by supposition. By (i), let x be a minimal element of X. Then let 4. Ordinals July 26, 2011 In this chapter we introduce the ordinals, prove a general recursion theorem, and develop some elementary ordinal arithmetic. A set A is transitive iff x A y x(y A); in other

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in

Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in : tail in X, head in A nowhere-zero Γ-flow is a Γ-circulation such that

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor

Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor Given f L 1 T 1 ), we consider the partial sums of the Fourier series of f: N 1) S N fθ) = ˆfk)e ikθ. k= N A calculation gives the Dirichlet formula

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1)

4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1) 84 CHAPTER 4. STATIONARY TS MODELS 4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(,) This section is an introduction to a wide class of models ARMA(p,q) which we will consider in more detail later in this

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

CHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS

CHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS CHAPTER 5 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS EXERCISE 104 Page 8 1. Find the positive root of the equation x + 3x 5 = 0, correct to 3 significant figures, using the method of bisection. Let f(x) =

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Section 8.3 Trigonometric Equations

Section 8.3 Trigonometric Equations 99 Section 8. Trigonometric Equations Objective 1: Solve Equations Involving One Trigonometric Function. In this section and the next, we will exple how to solving equations involving trigonometric functions.

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016

Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016 Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016 Silvio Capobianco Exercise 1.7 Let H(n) = J(n + 1) J(n). Equation (1.8) tells us that H(2n) = 2, and H(2n+1) = J(2n+2) J(2n+1) = (2J(n+1) 1) (2J(n)+1)

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Chapter 2. Ordinals, well-founded relations.

Chapter 2. Ordinals, well-founded relations. Chapter 2. Ordinals, well-founded relations. 2.1. Well-founded Relations. We start with some definitions and rapidly reach the notion of a well-ordered set. Definition. For any X and any binary relation

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Homework 3 Solutions

Homework 3 Solutions Homework 3 Solutions Igor Yanovsky (Math 151A TA) Problem 1: Compute the absolute error and relative error in approximations of p by p. (Use calculator!) a) p π, p 22/7; b) p π, p 3.141. Solution: For

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

2. Let H 1 and H 2 be Hilbert spaces and let T : H 1 H 2 be a bounded linear operator. Prove that [T (H 1 )] = N (T ). (6p)

2. Let H 1 and H 2 be Hilbert spaces and let T : H 1 H 2 be a bounded linear operator. Prove that [T (H 1 )] = N (T ). (6p) Uppsala Universitet Matematiska Institutionen Andreas Strömbergsson Prov i matematik Funktionalanalys Kurs: F3B, F4Sy, NVP 2005-03-08 Skrivtid: 9 14 Tillåtna hjälpmedel: Manuella skrivdon, Kreyszigs bok

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs

Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs Who? Nichole Schimanski When? July 27, 2011 Graphs A graph, G, consists of a vertex set, V (G), and an edge set, E(G). V (G) is any finite set E(G) is

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequality for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x, y, z X.

Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequality for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x, y, z X. Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequalit for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x,, z X. Prove that d(x, z) d(, z) d(x, ). (ii): Reverse triangle inequalit for norms:

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II

ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II 2014/2015: Semester II Tutorial 7 1. Let X be a sample from a population P and consider testing hypotheses H 0 : P = P 0 versus H 1 : P = P 1, where P j is a known

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Example Sheet 3 Solutions

Example Sheet 3 Solutions Example Sheet 3 Solutions. i Regular Sturm-Liouville. ii Singular Sturm-Liouville mixed boundary conditions. iii Not Sturm-Liouville ODE is not in Sturm-Liouville form. iv Regular Sturm-Liouville note

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

A Conception of Inductive Logic: Example

A Conception of Inductive Logic: Example A Conception of Inductive Logic: Example Patrick Maher Department of Philosophy, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign This paper presents a simple example of inductive logic done according to the

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

ω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω

ω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 ω ω + 1 ω + 2 ω + 3 ω + 4 ω2 ω2 + 1 ω2 + 2 ω2 + 3 ω3 ω3 + 1 ω3 + 2 ω4 ω4 + 1 ω5 ω 2 ω 2 + 1 ω 2 + 2 ω 2 + ω ω 2 + ω + 1 ω 2 + ω2 ω 2 2 ω 2 2 + 1 ω 2 2 + ω ω 2 3 ω 3 ω 3 + 1 ω 3 + ω ω 3 +

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β

3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β 3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS Page Theorem cos(αβ cos α cos β -sin α cos(α-β cos α cos β sin α NOTE: cos(αβ cos α cos β cos(α-β cos α -cos β Proof of cos(α-β cos α cos β sin α Let s use a unit circle

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Reminders: linear functions

Reminders: linear functions Reminders: linear functions Let U and V be vector spaces over the same field F. Definition A function f : U V is linear if for every u 1, u 2 U, f (u 1 + u 2 ) = f (u 1 ) + f (u 2 ), and for every u U

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics

Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics Nov 1, 01 In this lecture we examine root systems from an axiomatic point of view. 1 Reflections If v R n, then it determines a hyperplane, denoted P v, through the

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

THE SECOND ISOMORPHISM THEOREM ON ORDERED SET UNDER ANTIORDERS. Daniel A. Romano

THE SECOND ISOMORPHISM THEOREM ON ORDERED SET UNDER ANTIORDERS. Daniel A. Romano 235 Kragujevac J. Math. 30 (2007) 235 242. THE SECOND ISOMORPHISM THEOREM ON ORDERED SET UNDER ANTIORDERS Daniel A. Romano Department of Mathematics and Informatics, Banja Luka University, Mladena Stojanovića

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Finite Field Problems: Solutions

Finite Field Problems: Solutions Finite Field Problems: Solutions 1. Let f = x 2 +1 Z 11 [x] and let F = Z 11 [x]/(f), a field. Let Solution: F =11 2 = 121, so F = 121 1 = 120. The possible orders are the divisors of 120. Solution: The

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Tridiagonal matrices. Gérard MEURANT. October, 2008

Tridiagonal matrices. Gérard MEURANT. October, 2008 Tridiagonal matrices Gérard MEURANT October, 2008 1 Similarity 2 Cholesy factorizations 3 Eigenvalues 4 Inverse Similarity Let α 1 ω 1 β 1 α 2 ω 2 T =......... β 2 α 1 ω 1 β 1 α and β i ω i, i = 1,...,

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates

derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates swapnizzle 03-03- :5:43 We begin by recognizing the familiar conversion from rectangular to spherical coordinates (note that φ is used

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations. ------------------ ----------------------------- -----------------

Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations. ------------------ ----------------------------- ----------------- Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations. 1. Sin ( ) = a) b) c) d) Ans b. Solution : Method 1. Ans a: 17 > 1 a) is rejected. w.k.t Sin ( sin ) = d is rejected. If sin

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Problem Set 3: Solutions

Problem Set 3: Solutions CMPSCI 69GG Applied Information Theory Fall 006 Problem Set 3: Solutions. [Cover and Thomas 7.] a Define the following notation, C I p xx; Y max X; Y C I p xx; Ỹ max I X; Ỹ We would like to show that C

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC = DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION #2. h 0 h h 0 h h 0 ( ) g k = g 0 + g 1 + g g 2009 =?

ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC = DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION #2. h 0 h h 0 h h 0 ( ) g k = g 0 + g 1 + g g 2009 =? Teko Classes IITJEE/AIEEE Maths by SUHAAG SIR, Bhopal, Ph (0755) 3 00 000 www.tekoclasses.com ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION # Question Type A.Single Correct Type Q. (A) Sol least

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

HOMEWORK 4 = G. In order to plot the stress versus the stretch we define a normalized stretch:

HOMEWORK 4 = G. In order to plot the stress versus the stretch we define a normalized stretch: HOMEWORK 4 Problem a For the fast loading case, we want to derive the relationship between P zz and λ z. We know that the nominal stress is expressed as: P zz = ψ λ z where λ z = λ λ z. Therefore, applying

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS

MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS FUMIE NAKAOKA AND NOBUYUKI ODA Received 20 December 2005; Revised 28 May 2006; Accepted 6 August 2006 Some properties of minimal closed sets and maximal closed

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential Equations Let a (t), a 2 (t),..., a nn (t), b (t), b 2 (t),..., b n (t) be continuous functions on the interval I. The system of n first-order differential equations

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Generating Set of the Complete Semigroups of Binary Relations

Generating Set of the Complete Semigroups of Binary Relations Applied Mathematics 06 7 98-07 Published Online January 06 in SciRes http://wwwscirporg/journal/am http://dxdoiorg/036/am067009 Generating Set of the Complete Semigroups of Binary Relations Yasha iasamidze

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3

Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3 Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3 1 State vector space and the dual space Space of wavefunctions The space of wavefunctions is the set of all

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests

Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests Side-Note: So far we have seen a few approaches for creating tests such as Neyman-Pearson Lemma ( most powerful tests of H 0 : θ = θ 0 vs H 1 :

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Phys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required)

Phys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required) Phys460.nb 81 ψ n (t) is still the (same) eigenstate of H But for tdependent H. The answer is NO. 5.5.5. Solution for the tdependent Schrodinger s equation If we assume that at time t 0, the electron starts

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5. Luca Alberucci, University of Berne. Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008

Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5. Luca Alberucci, University of Berne. Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008 Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5 Luca Alberucci, University of Berne Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008 Introduction Koz: Axiomatisation for the modal µ-calculus over K Axioms: All classical

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES G11LMA Linear Mathematics Examination Solutions

SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES G11LMA Linear Mathematics Examination Solutions SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES GLMA Linear Mathematics 00- Examination Solutions. (a) i. ( + 5i)( i) = (6 + 5) + (5 )i = + i. Real part is, imaginary part is. (b) ii. + 5i i ( + 5i)( + i) = ( i)( + i)

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Solutions to Exercise Sheet 5

Solutions to Exercise Sheet 5 Solutions to Eercise Sheet 5 jacques@ucsd.edu. Let X and Y be random variables with joint pdf f(, y) = 3y( + y) where and y. Determine each of the following probabilities. Solutions. a. P (X ). b. P (X

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

The challenges of non-stable predicates

The challenges of non-stable predicates The challenges of non-stable predicates Consider a non-stable predicate Φ encoding, say, a safety property. We want to determine whether Φ holds for our program. The challenges of non-stable predicates

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Second Order Partial Differential Equations

Second Order Partial Differential Equations Chapter 7 Second Order Partial Differential Equations 7.1 Introduction A second order linear PDE in two independent variables (x, y Ω can be written as A(x, y u x + B(x, y u xy + C(x, y u u u + D(x, y

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Cardinals. Y = n Y n. Define h: X Y by f(x) if x X n X n+1 and n is even h(x) = g

Cardinals. Y = n Y n. Define h: X Y by f(x) if x X n X n+1 and n is even h(x) = g Cardinals 1. Introduction to Cardinals We work in the base theory ZF. The definitions and many (but not all) of the basic theorems do not require AC; we will indicate explicitly when we are using choice.

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Partial Differential Equations in Biology The boundary element method. March 26, 2013

Partial Differential Equations in Biology The boundary element method. March 26, 2013 The boundary element method March 26, 203 Introduction and notation The problem: u = f in D R d u = ϕ in Γ D u n = g on Γ N, where D = Γ D Γ N, Γ D Γ N = (possibly, Γ D = [Neumann problem] or Γ N = [Dirichlet

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes

6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes 122 CHAPTER 6. ARMA MODELS 6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes The purpose of forecasting is to predict future values of a TS based on the data collected to the present. In this section we will discuss a linear

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Second Order RLC Filters

Second Order RLC Filters ECEN 60 Circuits/Electronics Spring 007-0-07 P. Mathys Second Order RLC Filters RLC Lowpass Filter A passive RLC lowpass filter (LPF) circuit is shown in the following schematic. R L C v O (t) Using phasor

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates Kiryl Tsishchanka Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates In this section we develop the formula for the area of a region whose boundary is given by a polar equation. We need to use the formula for the

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS

CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS Shiah-Sen Wang The graphs are prepared by Chien-Lun Lai Based on : Precalculus: Mathematics for Calculus by J. Stuwart, L. Redin & S. Watson, 6th edition, 01, Brooks/Cole Chapter

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Math221: HW# 1 solutions

Math221: HW# 1 solutions Math: HW# solutions Andy Royston October, 5 7.5.7, 3 rd Ed. We have a n = b n = a = fxdx = xdx =, x cos nxdx = x sin nx n sin nxdx n = cos nx n = n n, x sin nxdx = x cos nx n + cos nxdx n cos n = + sin

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

5. Choice under Uncertainty

5. Choice under Uncertainty 5. Choice under Uncertainty Daisuke Oyama Microeconomics I May 23, 2018 Formulations von Neumann-Morgenstern (1944/1947) X: Set of prizes Π: Set of probability distributions on X : Preference relation

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Lecture 21: Properties and robustness of LSE

Lecture 21: Properties and robustness of LSE Lecture 21: Properties and robustness of LSE BLUE: Robustness of LSE against normality We now study properties of l τ β and σ 2 under assumption A2, i.e., without the normality assumption on ε. From Theorem

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests

Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests Shirsendu Mukherjee Department of Statistics, Asutosh College, Kolkata, India. shirsendu st@yahoo.co.in So far we have treated the testing of one-sided

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

The Simply Typed Lambda Calculus

The Simply Typed Lambda Calculus Type Inference Instead of writing type annotations, can we use an algorithm to infer what the type annotations should be? That depends on the type system. For simple type systems the answer is yes, and

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Practice Exam 2. Conceptual Questions. 1. State a Basic identity and then verify it. (a) Identity: Solution: One identity is csc(θ) = 1

Practice Exam 2. Conceptual Questions. 1. State a Basic identity and then verify it. (a) Identity: Solution: One identity is csc(θ) = 1 Conceptual Questions. State a Basic identity and then verify it. a) Identity: Solution: One identity is cscθ) = sinθ) Practice Exam b) Verification: Solution: Given the point of intersection x, y) of the

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Section 7.6 Double and Half Angle Formulas

Section 7.6 Double and Half Angle Formulas 09 Section 7. Double and Half Angle Fmulas To derive the double-angles fmulas, we will use the sum of two angles fmulas that we developed in the last section. We will let α θ and β θ: cos(θ) cos(θ + θ)

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Quadratic Expressions

Quadratic Expressions Quadratic Expressions. The standard form of a quadratic equation is ax + bx + c = 0 where a, b, c R and a 0. The roots of ax + bx + c = 0 are b ± b a 4ac. 3. For the equation ax +bx+c = 0, sum of the roots

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II

Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II October 18, 2012 1 Review First let us recall the situation. Let g be a simple algebra, with maximal toral subalgebra h (which we are calling a CSA, or Cartan Subalgebra).

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates Kiryl Tsishchanka Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates In this section we develop the formula for the area of a region whose boundary is given by a polar equation. We need to use the formula for the

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Overview. Transition Semantics. Configurations and the transition relation. Executions and computation

Overview. Transition Semantics. Configurations and the transition relation. Executions and computation Overview Transition Semantics Configurations and the transition relation Executions and computation Inference rules for small-step structural operational semantics for the simple imperative language Transition

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Chap. 6 Pushdown Automata

Chap. 6 Pushdown Automata Chap. 6 Pushdown Automata 6.1 Definition of Pushdown Automata Example 6.1 L = {wcw R w (0+1) * } P c 0P0 1P1 1. Start at state q 0, push input symbol onto stack, and stay in q 0. 2. If input symbol is

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

( y) Partial Differential Equations

( y) Partial Differential Equations Partial Dierential Equations Linear P.D.Es. contains no owers roducts o the deendent variables / an o its derivatives can occasionall be solved. Consider eamle ( ) a (sometimes written as a ) we can integrate

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM

SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM Solutions to Question 1 a) The cumulative distribution function of T conditional on N n is Pr T t N n) Pr max X 1,..., X N ) t N n) Pr max

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

k A = [k, k]( )[a 1, a 2 ] = [ka 1,ka 2 ] 4For the division of two intervals of confidence in R +

k A = [k, k]( )[a 1, a 2 ] = [ka 1,ka 2 ] 4For the division of two intervals of confidence in R + Chapter 3. Fuzzy Arithmetic 3- Fuzzy arithmetic: ~Addition(+) and subtraction (-): Let A = [a and B = [b, b in R If x [a and y [b, b than x+y [a +b +b Symbolically,we write A(+)B = [a (+)[b, b = [a +b

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

forms This gives Remark 1. How to remember the above formulas: Substituting these into the equation we obtain with

forms This gives Remark 1. How to remember the above formulas: Substituting these into the equation we obtain with Week 03: C lassification of S econd- Order L inear Equations In last week s lectures we have illustrated how to obtain the general solutions of first order PDEs using the method of characteristics. We

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions.

On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions. On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions. Moti Gitik December 31, 2015 Abstract Every set of ordinals of cardinality κ in a Prikry extension with a measure over κ contains an old set of arbitrary

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Απόκριση σε Μοναδιαία Ωστική Δύναμη (Unit Impulse) Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο. Απόστολος Σ.

Απόκριση σε Μοναδιαία Ωστική Δύναμη (Unit Impulse) Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο. Απόστολος Σ. Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο The time integral of a force is referred to as impulse, is determined by and is obtained from: Newton s 2 nd Law of motion states that the action

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

de Rham Theorem May 10, 2016

de Rham Theorem May 10, 2016 de Rham Theorem May 10, 2016 Stokes formula and the integration morphism: Let M = σ Σ σ be a smooth triangulated manifold. Fact: Stokes formula σ ω = σ dω holds, e.g. for simplices. It can be used to define

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Solutions to Selected Homework Problems 1.26 Claim: α : S S which is 1-1 but not onto β : S S which is onto but not 1-1. y z = z y y, z S.

Solutions to Selected Homework Problems 1.26 Claim: α : S S which is 1-1 but not onto β : S S which is onto but not 1-1. y z = z y y, z S. Solutions to Selected Homework Problems 1.26 Claim: α : S S which is 1-1 but not onto β : S S which is onto but not 1-1. Proof. ( ) Since α is 1-1, β : S S such that β α = id S. Since β α = id S is onto,

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Homework 8 Model Solution Section

Homework 8 Model Solution Section MATH 004 Homework Solution Homework 8 Model Solution Section 14.5 14.6. 14.5. Use the Chain Rule to find dz where z cosx + 4y), x 5t 4, y 1 t. dz dx + dy y sinx + 4y)0t + 4) sinx + 4y) 1t ) 0t + 4t ) sinx

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 6/5/2006

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 6/5/2006 Οδηγίες: Να απαντηθούν όλες οι ερωτήσεις. Ολοι οι αριθμοί που αναφέρονται σε όλα τα ερωτήματα είναι μικρότεροι το 1000 εκτός αν ορίζεται διαφορετικά στη διατύπωση του προβλήματος. Διάρκεια: 3,5 ώρες Καλή

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Completeness Theorem for System AS1

Completeness Theorem for System AS1 11 The Completeness Theorem for System AS1 1. Introduction...2 2. Previous Definitions...2 3. Deductive Consistency...2 4. Maximal Consistent Sets...5 5. Lindenbaum s Lemma...6 6. Every Maximal Consistent

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Srednicki Chapter 55

Srednicki Chapter 55 Srednicki Chapter 55 QFT Problems & Solutions A. George August 3, 03 Srednicki 55.. Use equations 55.3-55.0 and A i, A j ] = Π i, Π j ] = 0 (at equal times) to verify equations 55.-55.3. This is our third

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines

New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines Michigan State University Oct 8-31, 016 Anhui University Definition If X = {x 1, x,, x N } S n 1 (unit sphere in R n ) and x i, x j = a

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude

Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude Jan Behrens 2012-12-31 In this paper we shall provide a method to approximate distances between two points on earth

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 19/5/2007

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 19/5/2007 Οδηγίες: Να απαντηθούν όλες οι ερωτήσεις. Αν κάπου κάνετε κάποιες υποθέσεις να αναφερθούν στη σχετική ερώτηση. Όλα τα αρχεία που αναφέρονται στα προβλήματα βρίσκονται στον ίδιο φάκελο με το εκτελέσιμο

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

w o = R 1 p. (1) R = p =. = 1

w o = R 1 p. (1) R = p =. = 1 Πανεπιστήµιο Κρήτης - Τµήµα Επιστήµης Υπολογιστών ΗΥ-570: Στατιστική Επεξεργασία Σήµατος 205 ιδάσκων : Α. Μουχτάρης Τριτη Σειρά Ασκήσεων Λύσεις Ασκηση 3. 5.2 (a) From the Wiener-Hopf equation we have:

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Exercises 10. Find a fundamental matrix of the given system of equations. Also find the fundamental matrix Φ(t) satisfying Φ(0) = I. 1.

Exercises 10. Find a fundamental matrix of the given system of equations. Also find the fundamental matrix Φ(t) satisfying Φ(0) = I. 1. Exercises 0 More exercises are available in Elementary Differential Equations. If you have a problem to solve any of them, feel free to come to office hour. Problem Find a fundamental matrix of the given

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

About these lecture notes. Simply Typed λ-calculus. Types

About these lecture notes. Simply Typed λ-calculus. Types About these lecture notes Simply Typed λ-calculus Akim Demaille akim@lrde.epita.fr EPITA École Pour l Informatique et les Techniques Avancées Many of these slides are largely inspired from Andrew D. Ker

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

SOLVING CUBICS AND QUARTICS BY RADICALS

SOLVING CUBICS AND QUARTICS BY RADICALS SOLVING CUBICS AND QUARTICS BY RADICALS The purpose of this handout is to record the classical formulas expressing the roots of degree three and degree four polynomials in terms of radicals. We begin with

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

1. Introduction and Preliminaries.

1. Introduction and Preliminaries. Faculty of Sciences and Mathematics, University of Niš, Serbia Available at: http://www.pmf.ni.ac.yu/filomat Filomat 22:1 (2008), 97 106 ON δ SETS IN γ SPACES V. Renuka Devi and D. Sivaraj Abstract We

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Section 9.2 Polar Equations and Graphs

Section 9.2 Polar Equations and Graphs 180 Section 9. Polar Equations and Graphs In this section, we will be graphing polar equations on a polar grid. In the first few examples, we will write the polar equation in rectangular form to help identify

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

F A S C I C U L I M A T H E M A T I C I

F A S C I C U L I M A T H E M A T I C I F A S C I C U L I M A T H E M A T I C I Nr 46 2011 C. Carpintero, N. Rajesh and E. Rosas ON A CLASS OF (γ, γ )-PREOPEN SETS IN A TOPOLOGICAL SPACE Abstract. In this paper we have introduced the concept

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Math 6 SL Probability Distributions Practice Test Mark Scheme

Math 6 SL Probability Distributions Practice Test Mark Scheme Math 6 SL Probability Distributions Practice Test Mark Scheme. (a) Note: Award A for vertical line to right of mean, A for shading to right of their vertical line. AA N (b) evidence of recognizing symmetry

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

dim(u) = n 1 and {v j } j i

dim(u) = n 1 and {v j } j i SOLUTIONS Math B4900 Homework 1 2/7/2018 Unless otherwise specified, U, V, and W denote vector spaces over a common field F ; ϕ and ψ denote linear transformations; A, B, and C denote bases; A, B, and

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2

Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2 International Journal of Algebra, Vol. 8, 24, no. 5, 239-246 HIKARI Ltd, www.m-hikari.com http://dx.doi.org/.2988/ija.24.422 Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2 Ligong An and

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

On a four-dimensional hyperbolic manifold with finite volume

On a four-dimensional hyperbolic manifold with finite volume BULETINUL ACADEMIEI DE ŞTIINŢE A REPUBLICII MOLDOVA. MATEMATICA Numbers 2(72) 3(73), 2013, Pages 80 89 ISSN 1024 7696 On a four-dimensional hyperbolic manifold with finite volume I.S.Gutsul Abstract. In

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

CHAPTER 48 APPLICATIONS OF MATRICES AND DETERMINANTS

CHAPTER 48 APPLICATIONS OF MATRICES AND DETERMINANTS CHAPTER 48 APPLICATIONS OF MATRICES AND DETERMINANTS EXERCISE 01 Page 545 1. Use matrices to solve: 3x + 4y x + 5y + 7 3x + 4y x + 5y 7 Hence, 3 4 x 0 5 y 7 The inverse of 3 4 5 is: 1 5 4 1 5 4 15 8 3

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Homomorphism in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Automata

Homomorphism in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Automata International Journal of Fuzzy Mathematics Systems. ISSN 2248-9940 Volume 3, Number 1 (2013), pp. 39-45 Research India Publications http://www.ripublication.com/ijfms.htm Homomorphism in Intuitionistic

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees

Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees Thomas F. Kent Andrea Sorbi Università degli Studi di Siena Italia July 18, 2007 Goal: Introduce a form of Σ 0 2-permitting for the enumeration degrees. Till now,

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Lecture 34 Bootstrap confidence intervals

Lecture 34 Bootstrap confidence intervals Lecture 34 Bootstrap confidence intervals Confidence Intervals θ: an unknown parameter of interest We want to find limits θ and θ such that Gt = P nˆθ θ t If G 1 1 α is known, then P θ θ = P θ θ = 1 α

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential Equations Let a (t), a 2 (t),..., a nn (t), b (t), b 2 (t),..., b n (t) be continuous functions on the interval I. The system of n first-order differential equations

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Fourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics

Fourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics Fourier Series MATH 211, Calculus II J. Robert Buchanan Department of Mathematics Spring 2018 Introduction Not all functions can be represented by Taylor series. f (k) (c) A Taylor series f (x) = (x c)

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Econ 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1

Econ 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8  questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1 Eon : Fall 8 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 Email questions or omments to Dan Fetter Problem. Let X be a salar with density f(x, θ) (θx + θ) [ x ] with θ. (a) Find the most powerful level α test

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Trigonometric Formula Sheet

Trigonometric Formula Sheet Trigonometric Formula Sheet Definition of the Trig Functions Right Triangle Definition Assume that: 0 < θ < or 0 < θ < 90 Unit Circle Definition Assume θ can be any angle. y x, y hypotenuse opposite θ

Διαβάστε περισσότερα