Strukturalna poprawność argumentu.

Σχετικά έγγραφα
Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit

Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set

Example Sheet 3 Solutions

The challenges of non-stable predicates

EE512: Error Control Coding

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 6/5/2006

Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3

MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS

Reminders: linear functions

Lecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic

Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations

2. Let H 1 and H 2 be Hilbert spaces and let T : H 1 H 2 be a bounded linear operator. Prove that [T (H 1 )] = N (T ). (6p)

ω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω

A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation

Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests

ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER

2 Composition. Invertible Mappings

Finite Field Problems: Solutions

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 19/5/2007

k A = [k, k]( )[a 1, a 2 ] = [ka 1,ka 2 ] 4For the division of two intervals of confidence in R +

A Bonus-Malus System as a Markov Set-Chain. Małgorzata Niemiec Warsaw School of Economics Institute of Econometrics

Phys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required)

C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions

Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers

Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 24/3/2007

Matrices and Determinants

Πρόβλημα 1: Αναζήτηση Ελάχιστης/Μέγιστης Τιμής

Partial Differential Equations in Biology The boundary element method. March 26, 2013

Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs

Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets

F A S C I C U L I M A T H E M A T I C I

DESIGN OF MACHINERY SOLUTION MANUAL h in h 4 0.

Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in

The Simply Typed Lambda Calculus

CHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS

Homework 3 Solutions

A Conception of Inductive Logic: Example

SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM

SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM

6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes

Αλγόριθμοι και πολυπλοκότητα NP-Completeness (2)

ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II

Section 8.3 Trigonometric Equations

Main source: "Discrete-time systems and computer control" by Α. ΣΚΟΔΡΑΣ ΨΗΦΙΑΚΟΣ ΕΛΕΓΧΟΣ ΔΙΑΛΕΞΗ 4 ΔΙΑΦΑΝΕΙΑ 1

SCITECH Volume 13, Issue 2 RESEARCH ORGANISATION Published online: March 29, 2018

5. Choice under Uncertainty

PARTIAL NOTES for 6.1 Trigonometric Identities

Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2

Overview. Transition Semantics. Configurations and the transition relation. Executions and computation

Section 8.2 Graphs of Polar Equations

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

ΠΑΝΕΠΙΣΤΗΜΙΟ ΚΥΠΡΟΥ ΤΜΗΜΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ. ΕΠΛ342: Βάσεις Δεδομένων. Χειμερινό Εξάμηνο Φροντιστήριο 10 ΛΥΣΕΙΣ. Επερωτήσεις SQL

If we restrict the domain of y = sin x to [ π, π ], the restrict function. y = sin x, π 2 x π 2

12. Radon-Nikodym Theorem

Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor

Some new generalized topologies via hereditary classes. Key Words:hereditary generalized topological space, A κ(h,µ)-sets, κµ -topology.

The ε-pseudospectrum of a Matrix

If we restrict the domain of y = sin x to [ π 2, π 2

Homomorphism in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Automata

Homework 8 Model Solution Section

Fourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics

Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests

Math 6 SL Probability Distributions Practice Test Mark Scheme

Econ 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1

Homomorphism of Intuitionistic Fuzzy Groups

Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016

SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES G11LMA Linear Mathematics Examination Solutions

DIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANSFORMATION SEMIGROUPS

Generating Set of the Complete Semigroups of Binary Relations

Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics

Practice Exam 2. Conceptual Questions. 1. State a Basic identity and then verify it. (a) Identity: Solution: One identity is csc(θ) = 1

Pg The perimeter is P = 3x The area of a triangle is. where b is the base, h is the height. In our case b = x, then the area is

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

Second Order Partial Differential Equations

ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC = DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION #2. h 0 h h 0 h h 0 ( ) g k = g 0 + g 1 + g g 2009 =?

Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5. Luca Alberucci, University of Berne. Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008

LTL to Buchi. Overview. Buchi Model Checking LTL Translating LTL into Buchi. Ralf Huuck. Buchi Automata. Example

Depth versus Rigidity in the Design of International Trade Agreements. Leslie Johns

SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS

Démographie spatiale/spatial Demography

Mean-Variance Analysis

Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude

3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β

Instruction Execution Times

AME SAMPLE REPORT James R. Cole, Ph.D. Neuropsychology

2. THEORY OF EQUATIONS. PREVIOUS EAMCET Bits.

Mean bond enthalpy Standard enthalpy of formation Bond N H N N N N H O O O

( y) Partial Differential Equations

Physical DB Design. B-Trees Index files can become quite large for large main files Indices on index files are possible.

Lecture 21: Properties and robustness of LSE

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

Block Ciphers Modes. Ramki Thurimella

derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

Solution Series 9. i=1 x i and i=1 x i.

Section 9.2 Polar Equations and Graphs

Trigonometric Formula Sheet

Συντακτικές λειτουργίες

4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1)

Transcript:

Strukturalna poprawność argumentu. Marcin Selinger Uniwersytet Wrocławski Katedra Logiki i Metodologii Nauk marcisel@uni.wroc.pl

Table of contents: 1. Definition of argument and further notions. 2. Operations on arguments. 3. Structural correctness of arguments.

1. Definition of argument and further notions. References: [1973] S. N. Thomas (second edition, 1986), Practical reasoning in natural language. [2001] K. Szymanek, Sztuka argumentacji. Słownik terminologiczny. [2003] K. Szymanek, K. A. Wieczorek, A. Wójcik, Sztuka argumentacji. Ćwiczenia w badaniu argumentów. [2006] M. Tokarz, Argumentacja, perswazja, manipulacja.

Argument = konkluzja + przesłanki. Przesłanki mogą wspierać konkluzję: 1 2 1 2 1 2 3 4 łącznie (zespołowo, szeregowo) rozłącznie (rozdzielnie, równolegle) w sposób mieszany Czasami przesłanki wspierają inne przesłanki: 1 2 3 7 4 5 6 8 9

Let S be a set of sentences of a given language. A1, A2,..., An A > be a finite sequence of nonempty, finite relations defined on the set P fin (S) S. Let A = < Thus A m 1 2 2 = { < 1, >, <, >,..., < m, m P P P > } m m m m i m i m for m n A. Def. 1. A is an argument iff the following conditions hold: (i) 1 2 i 1 = 1 =... = 1 (i.e. for m = 1); (ii) j i k j k m m P m 1 for 2 m n A.

Assume that A = < Def. 2. Def. 3. Further definitions. The final conclusion of A is the sentence: 1 A1, A2,..., A 2 i 1 1 = 1 =... = 1 > is an argument. A sentence is a premise of A iff it is an element of a set belonging to the domain of some of relations: A1, A2,..., A n A n A.

Examples 1 2 <{<{ 1 }, >, <{ 2 }, >}> 1 2 convergent argument <{<{ 1, 2 }, >}> 1 2 3 4 linked argument <{<{ 1, 2, 3 }, >, <{ 4 }, >}>

1 2 3 7 4 5 6 8 9 <{<{ 9 }, >}, {<{ 4, 5, 6 }, 9 >, <{ 8 }, 9 >}, {<{ 1 }, 5 >, <{ 2 }, 5 >, <{ 3 }, 5 >}, <{ 7 }, 8 >}>.

A = < A, A 2,..., A 1 > n A Def. 4. The final argument of A is the one-element sequence <A 1 >. Def. 5. The m-th level of A is the relation A m (for m n A ). Def. 6. An argument <{<P, β >}> is an atomic argument of A iff there exists m n A such that <P, β > A m.

Def. 7. An argument is direct iff it consists of one level only. Def. 8. A sentence is an intermediate conclusion of A iff it belongs to the counterdomain of some of its levels, which are higher then 1. Def. 9. A sentence is a first premise of A iff it belongs to an element of the domain of A n A. or it belongs to an element of the domain of A m (for m < n A ), but it does not belong to the counterdomain of A m + 1.

Examples 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 3 2 final argument level of argument atomic argument direct argument intermediate conclusion first premise 9 1 <{<{ 9 }, >}, {<{ 4, 5, 6 }, 9 >, <{ 8 }, 9 >}, {<{ 1 }, 5 >, <{ 2 }, 5 >, <{ 3 }, 5 >}, <{ 7 }, 8 >}>.

1 1 1 = 2 3 2 3 <{<{ 2, 3 }, >}, {<{ 1 }, 2 >, <{ 1 }, 3 >}>

1 1 1 1 2 2 6 2 2 3 6 3 3 1 3 = 6 4 7 4 7 4 6 4 7 5 5 5 7 5

Def. 10 The domain of A is the set of all the premises of A. Def. 11 The counterdomain of A is the set of all the conclusions of A. i.e. the set of intermediate conclusions {final colclusion} Def. 12 The range of A is the sum of the domain and counterdomain of A.

Example 1 2 3 7 3 Domain: { 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9 } 4 5 6 8 2 Counterdomain: {, 5, 8, 9 } 9 1 Range: {, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9 } <{<{ 9 }, >}, {<{ 4, 5, 6 }, 9 >, <{ 8 }, 9 >}, {<{ 1 }, 5 >, <{ 2 }, 5 >, <{ 3 }, 5 >}, <{ 7 }, 8 >}>.

Def. 13 A sentence δ directly supports a sentence δ in A iff there exists an atomic argument of A, such thatδ belongs to its domain, and δ belongs to its counterdomain. Def. 14 A sentenceδ n indirectly supports a sentenceδ 1 in A iff there exists a sequence of sentences <δ 1, δ 2, δ n >, where n 3, such that each of its elements (except for δ 1 ) directly supports (in A) the preceding element. Def. 15 A sentenceδsupports a sentenceδ in A iff δ directly or indirectly supportsδ in A.

Def. 16 An argument is circular iff its range contains a sentence, which supports itself (in this argument). 1 2 3 1 2 3 4 5 6 4 5 6 1 9 9 circular non-circular

Assume that A = < A1, A2,..., A > and B = < B1, B2,..., B > are arguments. Def. 17 (B A) B is a subargument of A iff the following conditions hold: (i) n B n A ; (ii) k n A n B +1 ( B1 Ak, B2 Ak + 1,..., Bn Ak + n 1 ). Def. 18 (B A) B is an internal subargument of A iff the following conditions hold: (i) n B < n A ; (ii) k n A n B +1 (k > 1 and B A n A B B n B, B2 k+ 1,..., Bn Ak + n 1 ). 1 k A B B

Example 2 1 2 3 7 4 5 6 4 5 6 8 9 9 Remark 1: A A, for all A. Remark 2: "B A" doesn t mean "B A and B A".

2. Operations on arguments. Addition. Maximal subarguments. Subtraction.

Addition of arguments "conclusional" "premisal" 1 2 + = 1 2 1 2 + = 1 2 1 Assume that A = < A1, A2,..., An A >, B = < B1, B2,..., Bn B > and C = < C1, C 2,..., C > are arguments. n C Assume that 1 m n A.

Def. 19 A + m B = C iff either the final conclusion of B is not contained in the counterdomain of A m and A = C. or the final conclusion of B is contained in the counterdomain of A m and the following condisions hold: (i) n C = max {n A, m + n B 1}; (ii) C i = A i, if 1 i < m (for m 2) or i > m + n B ; (iii) C i = A i B i-m+1, if m i n A ; (iv) C i = B i-m+1, if n A < i n C. Def. 20 A + B = ( ((A + na B) + na-1 B) + na-2 ) + 1 B

γ β + 1 = γ β + 2 = γ β

Def. 21 A + m B = C iff either the final conclusion of B is not contained in any element of the domain of A m and A = C or the final conclusion of B is contained in some element of the domain of A m and the following condisions hold: (i) n C = max {n A, m + n B }; (ii) C i = A i, if 1 i m (for m 2) or i > m + n B ; (iii) C i = A i B i-m, if m < i n A ; (iv) C i = B i-m, if n A < i n C. Def. 22 A + B = ( ((A + na B) + na-1 B) + na-2 ) + 1 B

Remark 1: Let m > 1. Then A + m B = A + m-1 B iff the final conclusion of B is contained in the counterdomain of A m or the final conclusion of B is not contained in any element of the domain of A m-1. (i.e. the above equation holds iff the final conclusion of B is not any of the first premises on the level m-1 of A) Remark 2: The operations of addition are neither commutative nor associative, but if A, B (and C) have identical final conclusions, then the following equations hold: A + 1 B = B + 1 A; (A + 1 B) + 1 C = A + 1 (B + 1 C).

Def. 23 A + B = (A + B) + 1 B Remark 1: If the final conclusion of B is not in the range of A, then: A + B = A. Remark 2: If A is not circular, then A + A = A.

Maximal subarguments determined by a conclusion determined by an atomic argument 1 2 3 7 1 2 3 7 4 5 6 8 4 5 6 8 conclusion: 9 9 9 atomic argument: <{<{ 4, 5, 6 }, 9 >}>

Assume that A = < A1, A2,..., A n A > and B = <B 1 > are arguments. Assume that B is an atomic argument in A, where B 1 A m for the level number m n A. Def. 24 C = max(a, B, m) iff C is the longest (e.i. containing the largest number of levels) of the arguments C* = < C* 1, C* 2,..., C* n >, such that satisfy C* the following conditions: (i) n C* n A m + 1; (ii) C* 1 = B 1 ; (iii) if n C* 2, then for every 2 i n C* : C* i = {<P, δ*> A i+m-1 : δ* is contained in some element of the domain of C* i-1 }.

Assume that A = < A1, A2,..., A n A > is an argument. Assume thatδ is an element of the counterdomain of A m for the level number m n A. Def. 25 C = max(a, δ, m) iff C is the longest of the arguments C* = < C, C*,..., * >, * nc* 1 2 C such that satisfy the following conditions: (i) n C* n A m + 1; (ii) C* 1 = {<P, δ*> A m : δ* =δ}; (iii) if n C* 2, then for every 2 i n C* : C* i = {<P, δ*> A i+m-1 : δ* is contained in some element of the domain of C* i-1 }.

Remark 1: If B is the final argument of A, then max(a, B, 1) = A. Ifδis the final conclusion in A, then max(a, δ, 1) = A. Remark 2: If {B 1, B 2,, B k } is the set of all atomic arguments of the m-th level of A, which have the same conclusionδ, then: max(a,δ, m) = max(a, B 1, m) + 1 max(a, B 2, m) + 1 + 1 max(a, B k, m).

Subtraction of arguments 1 2 3 7 1 2 3 7 = 4 5 6 8 4 5 6 8 9 9 9

Assume that A = < A1, A2,..., An A > is an argument, and that B = <B 1 > is an atomic (non-final) argument in A (B 1 A m for m n A ). Assume that C = < C1, C2,..., C > = max(a, B, m). Def. 26 A m B = D iff (i) m 1 n D n A ; (ii) if m 2, then D i = A i, for every i < m; (iii) if n A = n C + m 1, then: n D = max{j < n A : A j C j-m+1 }; D i = A i C i-m+1, for every m i n D ; (iv) if n A > n C + m 1, then: n D = n A ; D i = A i C i-m+1, for every m i n C + m 1; D i = A i, for every n C + m 1 < i n D. n C

3. Structural correctness of arguments. For a structurally correct argument A = < n A > it is necessary that the following conditions hold: (1) For every argument B: if B A, then (the counterdomain of B) (the domain of B) = = {the final conclusion of B}. (2) (The domain of A) (the counterdomain of A) = = (the set of all the first premises of A). A1, A2,..., A (3) For every sentence δ: if there are i, j n A, such that the counterdomains of A i and A j containδ, then max(a, δ, i) = max(a, δ, j). An open problem: Are these conditions sufficient?

Remark 1: The condition (1) doesn t hold iff A is circular. Remark 2: The condition (2) doesn t hold iff there is a sentence in the domain of A, which is one of the first premises and a conclusion (final or intermediate) at the same time. Remark 3: The condition (3) doesn t hold iff there is a sentence in the domain of A, which is supported by different subarguments, when it appears on different levels. Remark 4: If the condition (1) doesn t hold, then at least one of the conditions: (2) or (3) doesn t hold either. The converse implication is not true.

Example 1 2 3 6 6 8 4 γ 6 7 7 9 10 11 γ 5 5 β γ β 12 4 3 13 14 15 2 16 1

1 4 γ 2 3 γ 5 6 5 β γ 13 14 16 12 15 4 3 2 1

1 2 3 6 4 γ 6 7 γ 5 5 β γ 12 4 3 13 14 15 2 16 1

1 2 3 6 4 γ 6 7 γ 5 5 β γ 12 4 3 13 14 15 8 2 16 9 10 11 1

1 7 1 4 2 3 6 1 4 2 3 γ 6 7 4 2 3 γ 5 5 β γ 12 4 3 13 14 15 8 2 16 9 10 11 1

- Dziękuję za uwagę.