The Semantic Characterization of Logic
|
|
- Ἁνανίας Μέλιοι
- 6 χρόνια πριν
- Προβολές:
Transcript
1 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 1 of 38 5 The Semantic Characterization of Logic 1. Introduction The Semantic Characterization of Logics Semantically Characterizing Other Standard Logical Notions Validity etc. Revisited The Mother of All Logical Notions Atomic Assignments Locality Valuation-Completeness and Super-Valuations Elementary Classes and Valuation Spaces Exercises Definitions General Theorems Theorems Pertaining to CSL Counterexamples Answers to Selected Exercises Definitions in Primitive Notation General Theorems Theorems Pertaining to CSL Official Definitions for Purposes of Doing Proofs of Theorems: Supporting Lemmas Theorems of Set Theory...38
2 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 2 of Introduction We have now examined Classical Sentential Logic (CSL). As we are well aware, CSL is not all there is to logic. At the very least, CSL has nothing to say about a large number of very important logical concepts, including quantification, identity, descriptions, etc. Second, it has nothing to say about non-truth functional connectives, such as the subjunctive conditional and the multitude of modal operators. Third, it does not speak directly about all truth-functional connectives, but only the privileged five. Finally, CSL is not universally accepted as the correct sentential logic. In opposition to CSL are a host of "deviant" logics that have been proposed as alternatives to CSL. These include multi-valued logic, supervaluational logic, intuitionistic logic, relevance logic, quantum logic, fuzzy logic, to name the most prominent examples. Given that the subject of logic is not monolithic, it is useful to distinguish between Logic and logic. The former refers to a scholarly discipline the "science of reasoning"; the latter refers to an abstract kind, and can be sensibly pluralized to form logics. This leads to the following slogan. Logic studies logics. Here, we can read this aloud as: logic with a capital-l studies logics with a little-l. Once we have the general term logics, we must ask the following question. We propose that, what is a logic? at a minimum, a logic specifies a class of valid argument forms. This means that a logic L can be (minimally) characterized as a structure (L,A), where L is a formal language over which L is written, and A is a set of argument forms in L namely those argument forms deemed valid by L. [Henceforth, we use the script letter L as a schematic name for logics, and we use ordinary L as a schematic name for formal languages.] We already know what a formal language is. So what is it to be an argument (form) in a (formal) language L? This is defined officially as follows. Df Let L be a formal language, and let S be the sentences (sentence forms; formulas) of L. Then an argument (form) in L is, by definition, any (ordered) pair (Γ/α) such that Γ is a subset of S, and α is an element of S.
3 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 3 of 38 Notice that we use the forward slash symbol / to delineate the items of the ordered pair. This particular choice is made in order to remind us that, in canonical form, an argument consists of premises followed by the word therefore followed by the conclusion. Thus, the slash-symbol has two roles: formally, it is simply a punctuation mark; however, heuristically, it is short for therefore. Before continuing, it is important to realize our definition of argument deviates from ordinary usage in two ways. In ordinary usage, an argument has one or more premises, and has only finitely many premises. According to our official definition, for abstract purposes, an argument can have any number of premises, including zero-many and infinitely-many 2. The Semantic Characterization of Logics So far, we have said that a logic L specifies a class of L-valid argument forms. We haven t said how this is accomplished. We do have a model of this process, however Classical Sentential Logic. Recall that CSL is characterized in two steps. First, one specifies the formal language L over which CSL is written to be the "standard" sentential language (ZOL) based on the five standard SL connectives. Second, one specifies the class V of CSL-admissible valuations, with respect to which all the usual logical notions are defined. A valuation is deemed CSL-admissible if and only if it complies with the truth-functional interpretation of the five standard SL connectives. This serves as a general model for the semantic specification of a logic. A logic L is semantically specified by a pair (L,V), where L is a formal language, and V is a set of valuations on L. Recall the definition of valuation on formal language L. Df Let L be a formal language, and let S be the set of sentences (formulas) of L. Then a valuation on L is, by definition, any function from S into {T,F}. In other words, a valuation on L assigns a truth-value, T or F, to every sentence of L. Once we have the class V of admissible valuations, we are in a position to define argumentvalidity, as follows. Df Let L be a logic semantically specified by (L,V). Let (Γ/α) be an argument in L. Then (Γ/α) is L-valid = df υ{υ V. γ(γ Γ υ(γ)=t) υ(α)=t} An alternative account of validity employs an intermediate notion of refutation.
4 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 4 of 38 Df Let L be a formula language, and let υ be a valuation on L. Let (Γ/α) be an argument in L. Then υ refutes (Γ/α) = df γ{γ Γ υ(γ)=t} & υ(α)=f In other words, a valuation refutes an argument if and only if it makes every premise true but makes the conclusion false. This definition allows us to prove the following theorem (exercise). Th Let L be a logic semantically specified by (L,V). Let (Γ/α) be an argument in L. Then (Γ/α) is L-valid υ{υ V & υ refutes (Γ/α)} 3. Semantically Characterizing Other Standard Logical Notions In addition to the central concept of logic argument validity other logical notions can be defined (even in intro logic!), including tautology, contradiction, consistency, logical implication, and logical equivalence. Each of these can be given a general definition in the context of logical semantics; some of them are given different names. In the following, we suppose that logic L is semantically specified by (L,V). Also, Γ is a subset of formulas of L, and α is a formula of L. (1) α is L-valid = df υ V, υ(α)=t (2) α is L-contra-valid = df υ V, υ(α)=f (3) α is L-contingent = df α is neither L-valid nor L-contra-valid (4) α L-entails β = df υ V{υ(α)=T υ(β)=t} (5) α and β are L-equivalent = df υ V{υ(α)=T υ(β)=t} (6) Γ is L-consistent = df υ V, γ Γ, υ(γ)=t (7) Γ is L-inconsistent = df Γ is not L-consistent
5 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 5 of Validity etc. Revisited In the present section, we formulate a number of logical notions in terms of a set V of admissible valuations. As usual, it is understood that a valuation on language L is a function that assigns exactly one truth-value, T or F, to every sentence in L. We assume also, of course, that T F. The relevant formal semantic notions are presented in a series of definitions. We begin with matters of terminology. In what follows, we presuppose a formal language L, with sentences S, and we presuppose a set V of admissible valuations. All definitions are relative to L and V. (D) Let α be a formula (i.e., α S), let Γ be a subset of formulas (i.e., Γ S), and let W be a subset of valuations (i.e., W V). (1) υ < α = df υ(α)=t [υ verifies α] (2) υ < Γ = df γ Γ, υ<γ [υ verifies Γ] (3) W < Γ = df w W, w<γ [W verifies Γ] (4) υ α = df υ(α)=f. [υ falsifies α] (5) υ Γ = df γ Γ, υ γ [υ falsifies Γ] (6) W Γ = df w W, w Γ [W falsifies Γ] Having introduced the basic terminology, we next define a variety of logical concepts, including validity and entailment, all defined relative to a set V of admissible valuations. (D) Let α, β be formulas, and let Γ, be subsets of formulas. (1) α is valid = df V < α (2) α is contra-valid = df V α (3) Γ is falsifiable = df υ V, υ Γ (4) Γ is unfalsifiable = df υ V, υ Γ (5) Γ is verifiable = df υ V, υ<γ (6) Γ is unverifiable = df υ V, υ<γ (7) α entails β = df υ V{υ<α υ<β} (8) Γ entails α = df υ V{υ<Γ υ<α} (9) α and β are equivalent = df υ V{υ<α υ<β} (10) Γ and are equivalent = df υ V{υ<Γ υ< } Note: entails here is short for semantically entails with respect to V ; the adverbs are omitted in this context. When the omission is troublesome, we will dutifully restore the modifiers. In order to symbolize some of these predicates, we use a single symbol, the double turnstile, ambiguously. As shown later, this ambiguity is harmless; indeed, it is fruitful. (1) α = df α is valid (2) α = df α is contra-valid (3) Γ = df Γ is unfalsifiable (4) Γ = df Γ is unverifiable (5) α β = df α entails β (6) Γ α = df Γ entails α (7) α β = df α and β are equivalent (8) Γ = df Γ and are equivalent
6 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 6 of 38 The notions of validity and contra-validity correspond to the customary logical notions of logical truth and logical falsehood. The notions of unfalsifiability and unverifiability are generalizations of validity and contra-validity, respectively. Specifically, to say that a set Γ of sentences is "valid" is to say that the sentences of Γ cannot all be made false. Similarly, to say that Γ is "contra-valid" is to say that the sentences of Γ cannot all be made true. Notice that a formula α is valid (resp., contra-valid) iff the singleton {α} is unfalsifiable (resp., unverifiable). In addition to the notions of validity and contra-validity, as well as their generalizations, there are two notions of entailment binary entailment, and ordinary entailment. Ordinary entailment corresponds to the notion of argument validity. Γ entails α (Γ/α) is valid Finally, there are two notions of logical equivalence, one pertaining to individual formulas, the other pertaining to sets of formulas. Note carefully that is a meta-linguistic two-place predicate, that should not be confused with the symbol employed by some logic authors (but currently no one outside philosophy!) as the object language connective for if and only if. We will never use in this unfortunate manner. Similarly, is a meta-linguistic two-place predicate, borrowed from set theory, and used to mean properly includes. Again, should not be confused with the symbol employed by some logic authors (but currently no one outside philosophy!) as the object language symbol for if then. We will never use in this unfortunate manner. 5. The Mother of All Logical Notions As used in the previous section, then symbol is used ambiguously; specifically, it represents two different two-place predicates, and four different one-place predicates. It was suggested that this is a harmless, indeed useful, ambiguity. In the present section, we examine a general abstract concept of entails [symbolized by ] from which all the usual logical notions can be derived. The following is the official definition, understood relative to V. Γ = df υ V{υ<Γ & υ } In other words, set Γ entails set if and only if no admissible valuation verifies Γ and falsifies. As we see in a later chapter, the symmetry of this notion of entailment plays a crucial role in the general completeness theorem for abstract logics. At the moment, however, we can use this symmetrical entailment to define all previous logical notions. This is the content of the following theorems, whose proofs are left as exercises. (1) α {α} (2) α {α} (3) Γ Γ (4) Γ Γ (5) α β {α} {β} (6) Γ α Γ {α} Note: in the above theorems, on the left-hand side, the turnstile is used ambiguously, but on the right-hand side, the turnstile refers exclusively to the symmetric entailment relation. The convention seems clear enough: a single formula can stand in place of its singleton, and the null expression can stand in place of the empty set.
7 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 7 of Atomic Assignments Df Let L be a formal language, and let A be the set of atomic formulas of L. Then (1) an atomic assignment on L is any function from A into {T,F}. (2) a finite atomic assignment on L is any function from A into {T,F}, where A is a finite subset of A Notice that every valuation on L gives rise to an associated atomic assignment, defined in the obvious manner. (T) Let υ be a valuation on L. Then there is a unique atomic assignment α υ on L, satisfying the following. for any atomic formula α, α υ (α) = υ(α) In other words, the atomic assignment function α υ is simply the restriction of the valuation function υ to the atomic formulas of L. Notice that α υ and υ are not identical, since their respective domains are different assuming of course that L has at least one non-atomic formula. Every valuation gives rise to an atomic assignment. Does every atomic assignment give rise to a valuation? In this connection, we propose the following definitions. Df Let L be a language with formulas S and atomic formulas A. Let V be a class of valuations on L. Let α be an atomic assignment [resp., finite atomic assignment] on L. Then α is V-consistent if and only if α can be extended to a valuation in V. In other words: α is V-consistent = df υ V α dom(α)[α(α)=υ(α)] Here, dom(α) is the domain of function α. V is said to be atomically-free if and only if every finite atomic assignment is V- consistent. In other words, to say that V is atomically-free is to say that every finite atomic assignment gives rise to at least one valuation in V. It is, of course, a fundamental assumption of elementary SL that every finite atomic assignment gives rise to at least one valuation no assignment of truth-values to finitely-many atomic formulas is logically prohibited. This is related to a central feature of logics formality which we discuss in greater detail later. For the moment, however, suppose logic L is specified by (L,V). Suppose there is a finite atomic assignment α on L that is not V-consistent. There are a number of ways this could happen, but let us simply suppose α(p)=t and α(q)=f. Since α cannot be extended to a valuation in V, it follows that the argument form (P/Q) is L-valid. This is a highly undesirable result,
8 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 8 of 38 because it entails that we have an L-valid argument form that has no internal structure in virtue of which it is valid. So far, we have discussed whether every atomic assignment can be extended to at least one valuation. Another interesting question is whether every atomic assignment can be extended to at most one valuation. In this connection, we propose the following definition. Df Let L be a language with formulas S and atomic formulas A. Let V be a class of valuations on L. Then V is said to be atomically determined if and only if: v 1 v 2 V{ α A[v 1 (α)=v 2 (α)] v 1 =v 2 } Observe that, given that v 1 and v 2 are valuations on L, the sentence v 1 =v 2 amounts to the following. α S[v 1 (α)=v 2 (α)] So, if a semantics is atomically determined, then if two valuations agree on all atomic formulas, then they agree on all formulas, and are therefore identical. Combining atomic-freedom and atomic-determination yields the following notion. Df Let L be a language with formulas S and atomic formulas A. Let V be a class of valuations on L. Then V is said to be atomistic if and only if V is both atomicallyfree and atomically determined. Given the definition of atomistic, we have the following immediate theorem. (T) Let L be a language and let V be a class of valuations on L. Suppose V is atomically determined. Then every atomic assignment on L gives rise to a unique valuation on L. The following is not automatic, but it is the sort of result we should expect. (T) Let L be a ZOL. Suppose V is truth-functional. Then V is atomistic. A remaining question, in this regard, is whether truth-functionality and atomicity are equivalent. They are not. (T) Not every atomistic semantics is truth-functional. In order to see this, we offer the following example.
9 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 9 of 38 (Ex) Let L be a prefix-formatted ZOL specified by the usual CSL-connectives, plus a one-place connective. Define V so that υ V iff υ satisfies the usual truth-functional conditions, plus the following condition pertaining to the extra connective. υ( α) = T if w(α)=t for every w V = F otherwise To see that this is not truth-functional, we simply note that υ( α)=f for every atomic formula; no atomic formula is an SL-tautology. There is, of course, a valuation υ such υ(p)=t and υ(q)=f. This means that, insofar as is truth-functional, its truth-function is given by: [ T=F; F=F]. So, if is truth-functional, then υ( α)= υ(α)=f, for every formula α. On the other hand, υ( DpNp) = T [notice that DpNp ( P P) is an SL-tautology]. On the other hand, this semantics is atomistic. This is because all valuations are truth-functional with respect to the standard CSL-connectives, and all valuations agree on all formulas whose main connective is. This is the basic idea; a formal proof requires induction. 7. Locality As we have seen, an atomic assignment is the abstract counterpart of a line in the guide table for a truth-table. Of course, in intro logic, we never assign truth-values to all atomic formulas [why bother?]. Rather, in doing truth-tables, we only assign truth-values to those atomic formulas that are involved in the specific argument under consideration. If we insist on evaluating all atomic formulas, we can simply say that every atomic formula not explicitly mentioned is assigned T (or F, as we wish; it doesn t matter). This simplification is based on the very plausible assumption that what truth-values we assign to all other atomic formulas is completely irrelevant to the computation of the truth-values of the formulas involved. This is certainly a feature of intro logic, and indeed of all truth-functional logics, but it is not built into the concept of valuation. Noting this assumption, we propose the following definition. Df Let L be a language with formulas S and atomic formulas A. Let V be a class of valuations on L. Then V is said to be local if and only if: v 1 v 2 V α S[ β{β A & β α. v 1 (α)=v 2 (α)} v 1 (α)=v 2 (α)] This says that, if two valuations agree on all the atomic subformulas of a formula, then they agree on the formula. Here, we use the symbol as the subformula predicate. It is defined inductively as follows, for general ZOL s written in prefix notation. α α α β & β γ. α γ if χ is a 1-place connective, then α χα if χ is a 2-place connective, then α,β χαβ if χ is a 3-place connective, then α,β,γ χαβγ etc. that s all!
10 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 10 of 38 If we define formulas to be strings of characters, as is customary, then we might define subformula simply to be a sub-string which is a formula. The sub-string predicate is defined using the string concatenation operation as follows. σ 1 σ 2 = df σ 3 σ 4 [σ 2 = σ 3 +σ 1 +σ 4 ] [Note: this definition assumes that our theory of strings includes a null-string ; then every string is a substring of itself.] [[Defining sub-formula to be a special kind of sub-string works for ZOL s. However, for more complicated languages, including quantified languages, the notion of sub-formula can be construed in a more subtle manner. For example, one can construe subformulas so that xfx has infinitely many immediate subformulas Fa, Fb, Fc, etc.]] Let us consider an extremely simple example. Consider a formal language L with just two formulas, p and p ; so the language L is both minuscule and odd. Next, define V so that it contains exactly three valuations, depicted in the following table. p p v 1 T T v 2 T F v 3 F F Notice first that this semantics is not atomistic v 1 and v 2 agree on the sole atomic formula p, but do not agree on all formulas; in particular, they do not agree on the "molecular" formula p. Notice also that this semantics is not local either v 1 and v 2 agree on all the atomic sub-formulas of p, but do not agree on p. The previous language is not a ZOL; it s way too small! The example can be corrected as follows. Consider a ZOL L with just one connective,, a one-place connective. Next, define V so that it contains exactly three valuations, depicted in the following schematic table. p* p* p* p* v 1 T T F F v 2 T F F F v 3 F F F F Here, p* stands for p followed by some number of sharps; in other words, p* is an arbitrary atomic formula of L. Notice that this semantics is neither atomistic nor local. One might naturally wonder whether locality and atomicity are equivalent. The answer is conveyed in the following theorem. (T) Every atomistic semantics is local, but not every local semantics is atomistic. Proof???
11 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 11 of Valuation-Completeness and Super-Valuations We now consider an interesting question. Once logic L is semantically specified by a set V of valuations, is there any room for extra valuations? In order to make this idea more precise, we propose the following definitions. D1. Let L be a logic semantically specified by (L,V). Let υ be any valuation on L. Then υ is said to be L-consistent [also, V-consistent] if and only if υ does not refute any L-valid [Vvalid] argument. D2. Let L be a logic semantically characterized by (L,V). Then V is said to be complete if and only if V contains every L-consistent [V-consistent] valuation. Here is how these ideas work. We start with a logic L characterized by a set V of L-admissible valuations; in particular, V generates the set of L-valid [V-valid] arguments. This set in turn generates a set of L-consistent [V-consistent] valuations. Obviously, every valuation in V is V-consistent (exercise). The question is whether every V-consistent valuation is in V. If it is, then V is complete; otherwise, it is incomplete. 1. Example 1 First, we consider a "degenerate" example. Define valuation v 0 as follows. v 0 (α) = T, for every sentence α in S This is a kooky valuation, to be sure, but notice that v 0 is L-consistent for any logic L. This is because v 0 refutes no argument whatsoever, because v 0 does not falsify any formula. 2. Example 2 Next, we consider a non-degenerate example. In particular, consider classical sentential logic (CSL), and the valuation v 1 defined as follows. v 1 (α) = T if every CSL-valuation verifies α; v 1 (α)=f, otherwise. First, v 1 is not CSL-admissible, because v 1 (P)=v 1 ( P)=F, and no CSL-admissible valuation has this property. Although υ is not an official CSL valuation, it is nevertheless CSL-consistent. To see this, we argue as follows. Suppose v 1 is not CSL-consistent. Then v 1 refutes at least one CSL-valid argument, call it (Γ/α). Then v 1 verifies every element of Γ, but falsifies α. Let γ be an element of Γ. Then v 1 (γ)=t, so by the definition of v 1, every CSL-valuation verifies α; in other words, α is CSL-valid it is a logical truth, a tautology. Thus, every element of Γ is CSL-valid. At this point, we can prove the following general lemma (exercise). L1 Γ α & γ(γ Γ γ). α In other words, if an argument is valid, and every premise is a logical truth, then its conclusion is also a logical truth. Applying this general result to CSL, we conclude that α is CSL-valid, so every CSL-valuation verifies α, so v 1 (α)=t. This contradicts our earlier assumption that υ falsifies α.
12 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 12 of 38 What we have shown is that the standard set of CSL-admissible valuations is not complete. There are at least two valuations (counting the degenerate one) that can be added without changing the logic, at least so far as argument validity is concerned. 3. Super-Valuations Are there other valuations that are CSL-consistent but not CSL-admissible? As it turns out, there are infinitely-many such valuations. This is in fact a special case of a more general theorem. In this connection, we offer the following definition. D3. Let L be a logic characterized by (L,V). Let W be any subset of V. Define v w as follows. v W (α) = T if w{w W w(α)=t} = F otherwise Terminology: following van Fraassen, we call v W the super-valuation associated with, or determined by, W. D4. Let V be a set of valuations on language L, and let υ be a valuation on L. Then υ is said to be a super-valuation over V if and only if there is a W V such that υ = v W. Example 1: Example 2: Example 3: if W=, then obtain Example 1 of the previous subsection. if W=V, then we obtain Example 2 of the previous subsection. if W={υ}, then v W = υ. This means that, technically speaking, every ordinary valuation is also a supervaluation. 4. General Theorems The following theorems sum up the important facts about supervaluations and completeness. T1. Let L be a logic characterized by V. Let W be any subset of V, and let v W be the super-valuation determined by W. Then v W is L-consistent. In other words, every super-valuation over V is V-consistent. T2. Let L be a logic characterized by V. Let υ be a valuation that is L-consistent. Then there is a subset W of V, and associated super-valuation v W, such that υ = v W. In other words, every V-consistent valuation is a super-valuation over V. T3. A logic (L,V) is complete if and only if every super-valuation over V is an element of V (if other words, V contains all its super-valuations).
13 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 13 of Elementary Classes and Valuation Spaces Associated with every formula φ, there is a subset of valuations that verify φ. This prompts the following official definition. (d) V(φ) = df {υ: υ<φ} = df {υ: υ(φ)=t} V(φ) is called the elementary class associated with φ; evidently, V(φ) is the set that consists precisely of those valuations in V that verify φ. This concept can be extended to sets in the obvious manner, as follows. (d) V(Γ) = df {υ: υ<γ} Once we have the basic notion, we can define the general notion of elementary class as follows. (D) (D) A subset W of valuations is said to be an elementary class iff there exists a formula φ such that W = V(φ). The valuation space associated with language L and semantics V is, by definition, the ordered pair (V,E), where E is the set of all elementary classes; in other words, E = {V(φ): φ S}. Notice that, although every elementary class is a subset of V, not every subset of V is an elementary class. For example, if V is infinite, then P (V) is uncountable. On the other hand, the number of elementary classes is no larger than the number of formulas, which is denumerable. By way of concluding this section, we note that the notions of elementary class and valuation space may be used to formulate the various formal semantic notions. We state the basic theorems, leaving the proofs as exercises. We begin with a theorem describing the relation between V(φ) and V(Γ). (1) V(Γ) = {V(γ): γ Γ} (2) α V(α) = V (3) α V(α) = (4) Γ {V(γ): γ Γ} = V (5) Γ V(Γ) = (6) α β V(α) V(β) (7) Γ α V(Γ) V(α) (8) Γ V(Γ) {V(δ): δ } (9) α β V(α)=V(β) (10) Γ V(Γ) = V( ) In this regard, the following are relevant set-theoretic facts about "big" intersection and union. (1) a {V(γ): γ Γ} γ{γ Γ a V(γ)} (2) a {V(γ): γ Γ} γ{γ Γ & a V(γ)}
14 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 14 of Exercises 1. Definitions Presupposing a formal language L and a set V of admissible valuations on L, define the following in primitive notation. Note 1: For these purposes, set-theoretic notation, including function application notation, is considered part of the primitive vocabulary. Note 2: There is nothing special about the exact form of the definition. The definiens can be any primitive formula that is logically equivalent to the "official" definition. If there is a particular formulation that seems memorable to you, then use it. 1. α is valid α 2. α is contra-valid α 3. Γ is unfalsifiable Γ 4. Γ is unverifiable Γ 5. α entails β α β 6. Γ entails α Γ α 7. Γ entails Γ 8. α and β are equivalent α β 9. Γ and are equivalent Γ
15 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 15 of General Theorems In the following a logic L semantically specified by (L,V) is assumed. It is also assumed that α, β, etc. are formulas of L, and Γ,, etc. are sets of formulas of L. Note 1: There are three different notions of semantic entailment employed here: binary, ordinary, and symmetric entailment. Similarly, the double turnstile is used in seven different ways (see Part 1 above). As usual, the context determines which one is meant. Note 2: You may use sortal variables and constants υ (etc.) for valuations in V, α (etc.) for formulas of L, and Γ (etc.) for sets of formulas of L. 1. Γ Γ 2. α Γ Γ α 3. Γ & γ{γ Γ Σ γ}. Σ 4. Γ & Γ Γ &. Γ 5. Γ α & Γ {α} β. Γ β if Γ entails α, and Γ {α} entails β, then Γ entails β 6. Γ α Γ {α} Γ entails α iff Γ entails {α} 7. α β {α} {β} α entails β iff {α} entails {β} 8. α α α is valid iff entails α 9. α {α} α is contra-valid iff {α} entails 10. Γ Γ Γ is unfalsifiable iff entails Γ 11. Γ Γ Γ is unverifiable iff Γ entails 12. α β {α} {β} 13. α β. α β & β α 14. Γ. α{γ α α} 15. Γ. δ{δ Γ δ} & γ{γ Γ γ}
16 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 16 of Theorems Pertaining to CSL In the following, assume that the set of admissible valuations is given by the standard semantics for CSL. Note: in the proposed formalization, the symbols and are used in three different ways, as names of object language symbols, as names of the associated truth-functions, and as the metalanguage connectives. The writer and reader of such proofs must be alert to context in reading these symbols. 1. Γ α Γ { α} Γ entails α iff Γ { α} is unverifiable 2. α β α β α entails β iff α β is valid 3. Γ {α} β Γ α β Γ {α} entails β iff Γ entails α β 4. Γ {α} Γ { α} Γ {α} entails iff Γ entails { α} 5. Γ {α} Γ { α} Γ entails {α} iff Γ { α} entails 6. {α β, α} β 7. {α β, β} α 8. α α β 9. β α β 10. {α, α} 11. {α, α} 12. α β [{α β, β} α] 13. α β [{α β, α} β] 4. Counterexamples Give a counterexample to the following: 1. Γ δ{δ & Γ δ} 2. Γ. Γ & Γ
17 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 17 of Answers to Selected Exercises 1. Definitions in Primitive Notation 1. α = df υ{υ V υ(α)=t} 2. α = df υ{υ V υ(α)=f} 3. Γ = df υ{υ V γ{γ Γ & υ(γ)=t}} 4. Γ = df υ{υ V & γ{γ Γ υ(γ)=t}} 5. α β = df υ{υ V. υ(α)=t υ(β)=t} 6. Γ α = df υ{υ V. γ{γ Γ υ(γ)=t} υ(α)=t} 7. Γ = df υ{υ V & γ{γ Γ υ(γ)=t} & δ{δ υ(δ)=f}} 8. α β = df υ{υ V. υ(α)=υ(β)} 9. Γ = df υ[υ V. δ{δ υ(δ)=t} γ{γ Γ υ(γ)=t}] 2. General Theorems Note: In what follows, many variables and constants are used sortally, as follows. υ, w : valuations in V α, β, γ : formulas in S Γ, : sets of formulas in S This means that we are presupposing the following shorthand. υ : υ{υ V } υ : υ{υ V & } α : α{α S } α : α{α S & } Γ : Γ{Γ S } Γ : Γ{Γ S & } See later sections for axioms, definitions, and subordinate lemmas.
18 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 18 of 38 #1: #2: #3: (1) : Γ Γ CD (2) Γ As (3) : Γ Def Γ (4) : υ{υ<γ & υ } ID (5) υ{υ<γ & υ } As (6) : 16,17,SL (7) w<γ & w } 5, O (8) x{x Γ & x } 2,ST (short for Set Theory ) (9) a Γ & a 8, O (10) x{x Γ w<x} 7,Def υ<γ (11) x{x Γ w x} 7,Def υ Γ (12) w<a 9a,10,QL (13) w a 9b,11,QL (14) w(a)=t 12,Def < (15) w(a)=f 13,Def (16) T=F 14,15,IL (17) T F Axiom 0 (1) : α Γ Γ α CD (2) α Γ As (3) : Γ α Def Γ α (4) : υ{υ<γ υ<α} UCD (5) w<γ As (6) : w<α 2,7,QL (7) x{x Γ w<x} 5,Def υ<γ (1) : Γ & x{x Γ Σ x}. Σ CD (2) Γ & x{x Γ Σ x} As (3) : Σ Def Γ (4) : υ{υ<σ & υ } ID (5) υ{υ<σ & υ } As (6) : 12b,15,SL (7) w<σ & w 5, O (8) υ{υ<γ & υ } 2a,Def Γ (9) [w<γ] 7b,8,QL (10) x{x Γ w<x} 9,Def υ<γ ( ) (11) (γ Γ w<γ) 10, O (12) γ Γ & [w<γ] 11,SL (13) Σ γ 2b,12a,QL (14) υ{υ<σ υ<γ} 13, Def Γ α (15) w<γ 7a,14,QL
19 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 19 of 38 #4: #5: #6: (1) : Γ & Γ Γ &. Γ CD (2) Γ & Γ Γ & As (3) : Γ Def Γ (4) : υ{υ<γ & υ } ID (5) υ{υ<γ & υ } As (6) : 11,15,16,QL (7) w<γ & w 5, O (8) x{x Γ w<x} 7a,Def υ<γ (9) x{x Γ x Γ } 2b,Def (10) x{x Γ w<x} 8,9,QL (11) w<γ 10,Def υ<γ (12) x{x w x} 7a,Def υ Γ (13) x{x x } 2c,Def (14) x{x w x} 12,13,QL (15) w 14,Def υ Γ (16) υ{υ<γ & υ } 2, Def Γ (1) : Γ α & Γ {α} β. Γ β CD (2) Γ α & Γ {α} β As (3) : Γ β Def Γ α (4) : υ(υ<γ υ<β) UCD (5) w<γ As (6) : w<β DD (7) υ(υ<γ υ<α) 2a, Def Γ α (8) υ(υ<γ {α} υ<β) 2b, Def Γ α (9) w<α 5,7,QL (10) w < Γ {α} 5,9,Lemma 2 (11) w<β 8,10,QL (1) : Γ α Γ {α} D (2) : CD (3) Γ α As (4) : Γ {α} Def Γ (5) : υ(υ<γ & υ {α}) ID (6) υ(υ<γ & υ {α}) As (7) : 16,17,SL (8) w<γ & w {α} 6, O (9) υ{υ<γ υ<α} 3,Def Γ α (10) w<α 8a,9,QL (11) x{x {α} w x} 8b,Def υ Γ (12) α {α} ST (13) w α 11,12,QL (14) w(α)=t 10,Def < (15) w(α)=f 13,Def (16) T=F 14,15,IL (17) T F Axiom 0
20 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 20 of 38 #6a: #7: (1) : CD (2) Γ {α} As (3) : Γ α Def Γ α (4) : υ{υ<γ υ<α} UCD (5) w<γ As (6) : w<α 16,Def < (7) υ(υ<γ & υ {α}) 2, Def Γ (8) υ(υ<γ [υ {α}]) 7,QL (9) [w {α}] 5,8,QL (10) x{x {α} w x} 9,Def υ Γ ( ) (11) x{x {α} & [w x]} 10,QL (12) a {α} & [w a] 11, O (13) a=α 12a,ST (14) [w α] 12b,13,IL (15) w(α) F 14,Def ( ) (16) w(α)=t 15,Lemma 0 (1) : α β {α} {β} D (2) : CD (3) α β As (4) : {α} {β} Def Γ (5) : υ(υ<{α} & υ {β}) ID (6) υ(υ<{α} & υ {β}) As (7) : 19,10,SL (8) w<{α} & w {β} 6, O (9) x{x {α} w<x} 8a,Def υ<γ (10) α {α} ST (11) w<α 9,10,QL (12) x{x {β} w x} 8a,Def υ Γ (13) β {β} ST (14) w β 12,13,QL (15) w(β)=f 14, Def υ α (16) υ{υ<α υ<β} 3,Def α β (17) w<β 11,16,QL (18) w(β)=t 17,Def υ<α (19) T=F 15,18,IL (20) T F Axiom 0
21 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 21 of 38 #7b: #8: (1) : CD (2) {α} {β} As (3) : α β Def α β (4) : υ{υ<α υ<β} UCD (5) w<α As (6) : w<β (7) υ(υ<{α} & υ {β}) 2, Def Γ (8) υ(υ<{α} [υ {β}]) 7,QL (9) : w<{α} Def (10) : x{x {α} w<x} UCD (11) e {α} As (12) : w<e 5,13,IL (13) e=α 11,ST (14) [w {β}] 8,9,QL (15) x{x {β} w x} 14, Def w Γ ( ) (16) x{x {β} & [w x]} 15,QL (17) e {β} & [w e] 16, O (18) e=β 17a,ST (19) [w β] 17b,18,IL (20) [w(β)=f] 19, Def υ α ( ) (21) w(β)=t 20,Lemma 0 (1) : α α D (2) : CD (3) α As (4) : α Def Γ α (5) : υ(υ< υ<α) UCD (6) w< As (7) : w<α DD (8) υ[υ<α] 3,Def α (9) w<α 8,QL (10) : CD (11) α As (12) : α Def α (13) : υ[υ<α] UD (14) : w<α 15,16,QL (15) υ(υ< υ<α) 11,Def Γ α (16) w< Lemma 5
22 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 22 of 38 #9: (1) : α {α} D (2) : CD (3) α As (4) : {α} Def Γ (5) : υ(υ<{α} δ{δ & υ<δ}) UCD (6) w<{α} As (7) : δ{δ & w<δ} 15,16,SL (8) υ[υ α] 3, Def α (9) υ[υ(α)=f] 8, Def (10) w(α)=f 9,QL (11) x{x {α} υ<x} 6, Def < (12) α {α} ST (13) w<α 11,12,QL (14) w(α)=t 13, Def < (15) T=F 10,14,IL (16) T F Axiom 0 (17) : CD (18) {α} As (19) : α Def α (20) : υ[υ<α] D (21) w<α As (22) : 27a,28,QL (23) w<{α} 21,Lemma 6 (24) υ{υ<{α} & υ } 18,Def Γ (25) [w ] 21,24,QL (26) x{x w x} 25, Def υ Γ ( ) (27) a & [w a] 26, O (28) x[x ] ST
23 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 23 of 38 #10: (1) : Γ Γ D (2) : CD (3) Γ As (4) : Γ Def Γ (5) : υ{υ< & υ Γ} D (6) w< & w Γ As (7) : 6b,8,QL (8) υ[υ Γ] 3, Def Γ (9) : CD (10) Γ As (11) : Γ Def Γ (12) : υ[υ Γ] D (13) w Γ As (14) : 21b,22,SL (15) x(x Γ w x) 13, Def υ Γ (16) υ{υ< & υ Γ} 10, Def Γ (17) w< Lemma 5 (18) [w Γ] 16,17,QL (19) x{x Γ w x} 18, Def υ Γ ( ) (20) x{x Γ & [w x]} 19,QL (21) a Γ & [w a] 26, O (22) w a 15,21a,QL
24 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 24 of 38 11: #12: #13: (1) : Γ Γ D (2) : CD (3) Γ As (4) : Γ Def Γ (5) : υ{υ<γ x(x & υ<x)} UCD (6) w<γ As (7) : x(x & υ<x) ID (8) υ[υ<γ] 2, Def Γ (9) [w<γ] 7,QL (10) 5,8 (11) : CD (12) Γ As (13) : Γ Def Γ (14) : υ[υ<γ] ID (15) υ[υ<γ] As (16) : 22,23,SL (17) w<γ 15, O (18) υ{υ<γ & υ } 12, Def Γ (19) [w ] 17,18,QL (20) x{x w x} 19,Def υ Γ (21) x(x & [w x]) 20,QL (22) x[x ] 21,QL (23) x[x ] ST (1) : α β {α} {β} D (2) : CD (3) α β As (4) : {α} {β} Def Γ (5) : υ(υ<{α} υ<{β}) UD (6) : w<{α} w<{β} 8, Lemma 6,SL (7) υ{υ<α υ<β} 3, Def α β (8) w<α w<β 7,QL (1) : α β. α β & β α D (2) : CD (3) α β As (4) υ{υ<α υ<β} 3,Def α β (5) : α β & β α &D (6) : α β Def α β (7) : υ{υ<α υ<β} 4,QL (8) : β α Def α β (9) : υ{υ<β υ<α} 4,QL (10) : CD (11) α β & β α As (12) υ{υ<α υ<β} 11a,Def α β (13) υ{υ<β υ<α} 11b,Def α β (14) : α β Def α β (15) : υ{υ<α υ<β} 12,13,QL
25 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 25 of 38 #14: (1) : Γ. x{γ x x} D (2) : CD (3) Γ As (4) υ{υ<γ υ< } 3, Def Γ (5) : x{γ x x} UD (6) : Γ α α D (7) : CD (8) Γ α As (9) υ{υ<γ υ<α} 8,Def Γ α (10) : α Def Γ α (11) : υ{υ< υ<α} UCD (12) w< As (13) : υ<α 9,14,QL (14) w<γ 4,11,QL (15) : CD (16) 8-14 mutatis mutandis #14b: (1) : CD (2) x{γ x x} As (3) : Γ Def Γ (4) : υ{υ<γ υ< } UD (5) : w<γ w< D (6) : CD (7) w<γ As (8) x{x Γ w<x} 7,Def υ<γ (9) : w< Def υ<γ (10) : x{x w<x} UCD (11) δ As (12) : w<δ 8,14,QL (13) δ 11,Th#2,QL (14) Γ δ 2,13,QL (15) : (16) 7-14 mutatis mutandis
26 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 26 of 38 #15: (1) : Γ. x{x Γ x} & x{x Γ x} D (2) : CD (3) Γ As (4) υ{υ<γ υ< } 3,Def Γ (5) : x{x Γ x} & x{x Γ x} &D (6) : x{x Γ x} UCD (7) δ As (8) : Γ δ Def Γ α (9) : υ{υ<γ υ<δ} UCD (10) w<γ As (11) : w<δ 12,13,QL (12) w< 4,10,QL (13) x{x w<x} 12, Def υ<γ (14) : γ{γ Γ γ} CD (15) 6-13 mutatis mutandis #15b: (1) : CD (2) x{x Γ x} & x{x Γ x} As (3) : Γ Def Γ (4) : υ{υ<γ υ< } UBD (5) : CD (6) w<γ As (7) : w< Def υ<γ (8) : x{x w<x} UCD (9) δ As (10) : w<δ 6,12,QL (11) Γ δ 2a,9,QL (12) υ{υ<γ υ<δ} 11, Def Γ α (13) : CD (14) 6-12, mutatis mutandis (2b/2a in line 11)
27 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 27 of Theorems Pertaining to CSL #1: #1b: (1) : Γ α Γ { α} D (2) : CD (3) Γ α As (4) : Γ { α} Def Γ (5) : υ[υ < Γ { α}] ID (6) υ[υ < Γ { α}] As (7) : 19,20,SL (8) w < Γ { α} 6, O (9) x(x Γ { α} w<x)) 8, Def < (10) υ(υ<γ υ<α) 3, Def Γ α (11) w<γ 8, Lemma 3, ST (12) w<α 10,11,QL (13) w(α)=t 10, Def < (14) α Γ { α} ST (15) w< α 9,14,QL (16) w( α)=t 15, Def < (17) w( α) = w(α) Def CSL-val (18) T = T 13,16,17,IL (19) T=F 18, Def (20) T F Axiom 0 (1) : CD (2) Γ { α} CD (3) : Γ α Def Γ α (4) : υ(υ<γ υ<α) UCD (5) w<γ As (6) : w<α 11,12-16,17-25,SC (7) υ[υ < Γ { α}] 2,Def Γ (8) [w < Γ { α}] 7,QL (9) x(x Γ { α} w<x) 8, Def υ<γ ( ) (10) a Γ { α} & [w<a] 9, O (11) a Γ a { α} 10a,Def (12) case 1: a Γ As (13) x(x Γ w<x) 5, Def < (14) w<a 12,13,QL (15) 10b,14,SL (16) w<α 15,SL (17) case 2: a { α} As (18) a = α 17, ST (19) [w< α] 10b,17,IL (20) w( α) T Def < ( ) (21) w( α)=f 20, Lemma 0 (22) w( α) = w(α) Def CSL-val (23) w(α) = F 21,22,IL (24) w(α) = T 23, Def (25) w<α 24, Def <
28 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 28 of 38 #2: #2b: (1) : α β α β D (2) : CD (3) α β As (4) : α β Def α (5) : υ[υ < α β] UD (6) : w < α β Def < (7) : w(α β) = T ID (8) w(α β) T As (9) w(α β)=f 8, Lemma 0 (10) w(α β) = w(α) w(β) Def CSL-val (11) w(α) w(β) = F 9,10,IL (12) w(α)=t & w(β)=f 11, Def (13) υ(υ<α υ<β) 3, Def α β (14) w<α 12a, Def < (15) w<β 13,14,QL (16) w(β)=t 15, Def < (17) T=F 12b,16,IL (18) T F Axiom 0 (1) : CD (2) α β As (3) : α β Def α β (4) : υ(υ<α υ<β) UCD (5) w<α As (6) : w<β Def < (7) : w(β)=t ID (8) w(β) T As (9) : 18,19,SL (10) w(β)=f 8,Lemma 0 (11) υ[υ < α β] 2, Def α (12) w < α β 11,QL (13) w(α β) = T 12, Def < (14) w(α β) = w(α) w(β) Def CSL-val (15) w(α) w(β) = T 13,14,IL (16) w(α)=f 10,15, Def (17) w(α)=t 5, Def < (18) T=F 31,32,IL (19) T F Axiom 0
29 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 29 of 38 #3: (1) : Γ {α} β Γ α β D (2) : CD (3) : Γ {α} β Γ α β CD (4) Γ {α} β As (5) : Γ α β Def Γ α (6) : υ(υ<γ υ < α β) UCD (7) w<γ As (8) : w < α β Def < (9) : w(α β)=t ID (10) w(α β) T As (11) : 23,24-31,SC (12) w(α β)=f 10, Lemma 0 (13) w(α β) = w(α) w(β) Def CSL-val (14) w(α) w(β) = F 12,13,IL (15) w(α)=t & w(β)=f 14, Def (16) w<α 15a, Def < (17) w(β) T 15b, Lemma 1 (18) [w<β] 17, Def < (19) υ(υ < Γ {α} υ<β) 4, Def Γ α (20) [w < Γ {α}] 18,19,QL (21) x(x Γ {α} w<x) 20, Def < ( ) (22) a Γ {α} & [w<a] 21, O (23) a Γ a {α} 22a,ST (24) case 1: a Γ As (25) x(x Γ w<x) 7, Def < (26) w<a 24,25,QL (27) 22b,26 (28) case 2: a {α} As (29) a=α 28, Def {} (30) [w<α] 22b,29,IL (31) 16,30
30 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 30 of 38 #3b: #4: (1) : CD (2) Γ α β As (3) : Γ {α} β Def Γ α (4) : υ(υ < Γ {α} υ<β) UCD (5) w < Γ {α} As (6) : w<β DD (7) υ(υ<γ υ < α β) 2, Def Γ α (8) w<γ 5, Lemma 3,ST (9) w < α β 7,8,QL (10) w(α β) = T 9, Def < (11) x(x Γ {α} w<x) 5, Def < (12) α Γ {α} ST (13) w<α 11,12,SL (14) w(α)=t 13, Def < (15) w(α β) = w(α) w(β) Def CSL-val (16) T = T w(β) 10,14,15,IL (17) w(β)=t 16, Def ² (18) w<β 17, Def < (1) : Γ {α} Γ { α} D (2) : CD (3) Γ {α} As (4) : Γ { α} Def Γ (5) : υ[υ<γ & υ { α}] D (6) w<γ & w { α} As (7) : 18,20,SL (8) x{x { α} w x} 6b,Def υ Γ (9) α { α} ST (10) w α 8,9,QL (11) w( α)=f 10,Def υ α (12) w( α) = w(α) Def CSL-valuation (13) w(α) = F 11,12,IL (14) w(α) = T 13,Def (15) w<α 14, Def < (16) w<γ {α} 6a,15,Lemma 2 (17) υ{υ<γ {α} & υ } 3, Def Γ (18) [w ] 16,17,QL (19) { α} ST (20) w 6b,19,Lemma 4
31 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 31 of 38 #4b: #5: #6: (1) : CD (2) Γ { α} As (3) : Γ {α} Def Γ (4) : υ{υ<γ {α}& υ } D (5) w<γ {α}& w As (6) : 15,16-31,SC (7) x{x Γ {α} w<x} 5a, Def υ<γ (8) x(x Γ x Γ {α}) ST (9) x(x Γ w<x) 7,8,QL (10) w<γ 9,Def υ<γ (11) υ(υ<γ & υ { α}) 2, Def Γ (12) [w { α}] 10,11,QL (13) x(x { α} w x) 12, Def w Γ ( ) (14) e { α} & [w e] 13, O (15) e e = α 14a, ST (16) c1: e As (17) x{x w x} 5b,Def υ (18) w e 16,17,QL (19) 14b,18,SL (20) c2: e = α As (21) [w α] 14b,20,IL (22) w( α) F 21, Def υ α ( ) (23) w( α) = w(α) Def CSL-valuation (24) w(α) F 22,23,IL (25) w(α) = T 24,Lemma 0 (26) w(α) = F 25,Def (27) α Γ {α} ST (28) w<α 7,27,QL (29) w(α)=t 28,Def υ<α (30) T=F 26,29,IL (31) 30,Axiom 0 (32) Γ {α} Γ { α} Very similar to #4. (1) : {α β, α} β Def Γ α (2) : υ(υ<{α β, α} υ<β) UCD (3) w<{α β, α} As (4) : w<β 13, Def < (5) x(x {α β, α} w<x) 3, Def υ<γ (6) α β, α {α β, α} ST (7) w<α β 5,6a,QL (8) w<α 5,6b,QL (9) w(α β)=t 7,Def < (10) w(α)=t 8,Def < (11) w(α β)=w(α) w(β) Def CSL-val (12) T = T w(β) 9,10,11,IL (13) w(β)=t 12, Def
32 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 32 of 38 #7: #8: #9: (1) : {α β, β} α Def Γ α (2) : υ(υ<{α β, β} υ< α) UCD (3) w<{α β, β} As (4) : w< α 19,Def < (5) x(x {α β, β} w<x) 3,Def υ<γ (6) α β, β {α β, β} ST (7) w<α β 5,6a,QL (8) w< β 5,6b,QL (9) w(α β)=t 7,Def < (10) w( β)=t 8,Def < (11) w( β) = w(β) Def CSL-val (12) w(β) = T 10,11,IL (13) w(β)=f 12,Def (14) w(α β)=w(α) w(β) Def CSL-valuation (15) T = w(α) F 9,13,14,IL (16) w(α)=f 15, Def (17) w( α) = w(α) Def CSL-val (18) w( α) = F 16,17,IL (19) w( α) = T 18, Def (1) : α α β Def α β (2) : υ{υ< α υ<α β} UCD (3) w< α As (4) : w<α β Def < (5) : w(α β)=t Def CSL-val (6) : w(α) w(β) = T 11,12,IL (7) w( α)=t 3, Def < (8) w( α) = w(α) Def CSL-val (9) w(α)=t 7,8,IL (10) w(α)=f 9,Def (11) w(α) w(β) = F w(β) 10,IL (12) F w(β) = T Def (1) β α β (2) : β α β Def α β (3) : υ{υ<β υ<α β} UCD (4) w<β As (5) : w<α β Def < (6) : w(α β)=t Def CSL-val (7) : w(α) w(β) = T 9,10,IL (8) w(β)=t 3, Def < (9) w(α) w(β) = w(α) T 10,IL (10) w(α) T = T Def
33 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 33 of 38 #10: #11: #12: (1) : {α, α} Def Γ (2) : υ x{x {α, α} υ<x} D (3) x{x {α, α} w<x} As (4) : 13,Axiom 0 (5) α, α {α, α} ST (6) w<α 3,5a,QL (7) w< α 3,5b,QL (8) w(α)=t 6,Def < (9) w( α)=t 7,Def < (10) w( α) = w(α) Def CSL-val (11) w(α) = T 9,10,IL (12) w(α)=f 11,Def (13) T=F 8,12,IL (1) : {α, α} Def Γ (2) : υ x{x {α, α} υ x} D (3) x{x {α, α} w x} As (4) : 13,Axiom 0,SL (5) α, α {α, α} ST (6) w α 3,5a,QL (7) w α 3,5b,QL (8) w(α)=f 6,Def < (9) w( α)=f 7,Def < (10) w( α) = w(α) Def CSL-val (11) w(α) = F 9,10,IL (12) w(α)=t 11,Def (13) T=F 8,12,IL (1) : α β [{α β, β} α] 2,QL (2) : [{P Q, Q} P] ID (3) {P Q, Q} P As (4) : 18,Axiom 0,SL (5) υ{υ<{p Q, Q} υ<p} 2,Def Γ α (6) υ{υ(p)=f & υ(q)=t} Big Lemma (7) w(p)=f & w(q)=t 6, O (8) w(p Q) = w(p) w(q) Def CSL-val (9) w(p Q) = F T 7,8,IL (10) w(p Q) = T 9,Def (11) w<p Q 10, Def < (12) w<q 7b,Def < (13) x{x {P Q, Q}. x=p Q x=q} ST (14) x{x {P Q, Q} w<x} 11,12,13,QL (15) w<{p Q, Q} 14,Def υ<γ (16) w<p 5,15,QL (17) w(p)=t 16,Def < (18) T=F 7,17,IL
34 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 34 of 38 #13: (1) α β [{α β, α} β] 2,QL (2) : [{P Q, P} Q] ID (3) {P Q, P} Q As (4) : 25,Axiom 0,SL (5) υ{υ<{p Q, P} υ< Q} 2,Def Γ α (6) υ{υ(p)=f & υ(q)=t} Big Lemma (7) w(p)=f & w(q)=t 6, O (8) w(p Q) = w(p) w(q) Def CSL-val (9) w(p Q) = F T 7,8,IL (10) w(p Q) = T 9,Def (11) w<p Q 10, Def < (12) w<q 7b,Def < (13) w( P) = w(p) Def CSL-val (14) w( P) = F 7a,13,IL (15) w( P) = T 14,Def (16) w< P 15,Def < (17) x{x {P Q, P}. x=p Q x = P} ST (18) x{x {P Q, P} w<x} 11,16,17,IL (19) w<{p Q, P} 18,Def υ<γ (20) w< Q 5,19,QL (21) w( Q)=T 20, Def < (22) w( Q) = w(q) Def CSL-val (23) w(q) = T 21,22,IL (24) w(q) = F 23,Def (25) T=F 7b,24,IL
35 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 35 of Official Definitions for Purposes of Doing Proofs of Theorems: (1) υ<α = df υ(α)=t (2) υ<γ = df x{x Γ υ<x} (3) υ α = df υ(α)=f (4) υ Γ = df x{x Γ υ x} (5) Γ α = df υ(υ<γ υ<α) (6) Γ = df υ(υ<γ & υ ) (7) α = df υ[υ<α] (8) α = df υ[υ α] (9) Γ = df υ[υ Γ] (10) Γ = df υ[υ<γ] (11) α β = df υ V{υ<α υ<β} (12) Γ = df υ V{υ<Γ υ< } (13) Def T = df F F = df T (14) Def T T = df T T F = df F F T = df T F F = df T (15) Def CSL-val υ is a CSL-valuation = df α[υ( α) = υ(α)] & αβ[υ(α β) = υ(α) υ(β)] &
36 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 36 of Supporting Lemmas Axiom 0: T F This is taken for granted in formal semantics. Logically speaking, it is an axiom (primitive thesis, fundamental postulate) of formal semantics. Lemma 0: (26) : υ(α)=t υ(α)=f (27) υ is a function from S into {T,F} Def of valuation on L (28) x(x S υ(x) {T,F}) 2, Def function from A to B (29) α S sortal assumption (30) υ(α) {T,F} 3,4,QL (31) υ(α)=t υ(α)=f 5, Def {} Lemma 1: υ(α)=t υ(α) F υ(α)=f υ(α) T Both are immediate corollaries to Axiom 0. Lemma 2: (1) : υ<γ & υ<α. υ<γ {α} CD (2) υ<γ & υ<α As (3) : υ < Γ {α} Def < (4) : x(x Γ {α} υ<x) UCD (5) a Γ {α} As (6) : υ<a SC (7) a Γ a {α} 5, Def (8) case 1: a Γ As (9) x(x Γ υ<x) 2a, Def < (10) υ<a 8,9,QL (11) case 2: a {α} As (12) a = α 11, Def {} (13) υ<a 2b,12,IL Lemma 3: (1) : Γ. υ< υ<γ CD2 (2) Γ As (3) υ< As (4) : υ<γ Def < (5) : x(x Γ υ<x) DD (6) x(x Γ x ) 2, Def (7) x(x υ<x) 3, Def < (8) x(x Γ υ<x) 6,7,QL
37 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 37 of 38 Lemma 4: (1) : Γ. υ υ Γ CD2 (2) Γ As (3) υ As (4) : υ Γ Def (5) : x(x Γ υ x) DD (6) x(x Γ x ) 2, Def (7) x(x υ x) 3, Def (8) x(x Γ υ x) 6,7,QL Lemma 5: (1) : υ< Def υ<γ (2) : x{x υ<x} 3,QL (3) x[x ] ST Lemma 6: (1) : w<{α} w<α D (2) : CD (3) w<{α} As (4) : w<α 5,6,QL (5) x{x {α} w<x} 3, Def υ<γ (6) α {α} ST (7) : CD (8) w<α As (9) : w<{α} Def υ<γ (10) : x{x {α} w<x} UCD (11) e {α} As (12) : w<e 8,13,IL (13) e=α 11,ST Big Lemma: In CSL, the (syntactically) atomic formulas are also semantically atomic. In other words, any assignment of truth values to any subset of atomic formulas can be extended to an admissible valuation. Proof: by induction!
38 Hardegree, Metalogic, Semantic Characterization of Logic page 38 of Theorems of Set Theory #1: #2: (1) : a Γ {a} Def (2) : a Γ a {a} DD (3) a=a IL (4) a {a} 3, Def {} (5) a Γ a {a} 4,SL (1) : a {a} DD (2) a=a IL (3) a {a} 2, Def {} (1) : a {a,b} DD (2) a=a IL (3) a=a a=b 2,SL (4) a {a,b} 2, Def {} #3: #4: #4: #5: #6: (1) : Γ Γ Def (2) : x(x Γ x Γ ) UCD (3) a Γ As (4) : a Γ Def (5) : a Γ a DD (6) a Γ a 3,SL (1) : x[x ] ID (2) x[x ] As (3) : 5,6,SL (4) a 2, O (5) a a 3, Def (6) a=a IL e Γ. e Γ e e Γ {α}. e Γ e=α Γ x{x Γ & x }
Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set
Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set May 6, 2008 Abstract A set of first-order formulas, whatever the cardinality of the set of symbols, is equivalent to an independent
2 Composition. Invertible Mappings
Arkansas Tech University MATH 4033: Elementary Modern Algebra Dr. Marcel B. Finan Composition. Invertible Mappings In this section we discuss two procedures for creating new mappings from old ones, namely,
Completeness Theorem for System AS1
11 The Completeness Theorem for System AS1 1. Introduction...2 2. Previous Definitions...2 3. Deductive Consistency...2 4. Maximal Consistent Sets...5 5. Lindenbaum s Lemma...6 6. Every Maximal Consistent
Lecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic
Lecture 2 Soundness and completeness of propositional logic February 9, 2004 1 Overview Review of natural deduction. Soundness and completeness. Semantics of propositional formulas. Soundness proof. Completeness
Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit
Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit Ting Zhang Stanford May 11, 2001 Stanford, 5/11/2001 1 Outline Ordinal Classification Ordinal Addition Ordinal Multiplication Ordinal
EE512: Error Control Coding
EE512: Error Control Coding Solution for Assignment on Finite Fields February 16, 2007 1. (a) Addition and Multiplication tables for GF (5) and GF (7) are shown in Tables 1 and 2. + 0 1 2 3 4 0 0 1 2 3
Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers
Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers There are two kinds of number.. Ordinal numbers (0th), st, 2nd, 3rd, 4th, 5th,..., ω, ω +,... ω2, ω2+,... ω 2... answers to the question What position is... in a sequence? What
3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β
3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS Page Theorem cos(αβ cos α cos β -sin α cos(α-β cos α cos β sin α NOTE: cos(αβ cos α cos β cos(α-β cos α -cos β Proof of cos(α-β cos α cos β sin α Let s use a unit circle
C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions
C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions Paul Liu November 15, 2007 Note that these are sample solutions only; in many cases there were many acceptable answers. 1 Reynolds Problem 10.1 1.1 Normal-order
derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates
derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates swapnizzle 03-03- :5:43 We begin by recognizing the familiar conversion from rectangular to spherical coordinates (note that φ is used
ω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 ω ω + 1 ω + 2 ω + 3 ω + 4 ω2 ω2 + 1 ω2 + 2 ω2 + 3 ω3 ω3 + 1 ω3 + 2 ω4 ω4 + 1 ω5 ω 2 ω 2 + 1 ω 2 + 2 ω 2 + ω ω 2 + ω + 1 ω 2 + ω2 ω 2 2 ω 2 2 + 1 ω 2 2 + ω ω 2 3 ω 3 ω 3 + 1 ω 3 + ω ω 3 +
4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1)
84 CHAPTER 4. STATIONARY TS MODELS 4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(,) This section is an introduction to a wide class of models ARMA(p,q) which we will consider in more detail later in this
CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS
CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS Shiah-Sen Wang The graphs are prepared by Chien-Lun Lai Based on : Precalculus: Mathematics for Calculus by J. Stuwart, L. Redin & S. Watson, 6th edition, 01, Brooks/Cole Chapter
A Conception of Inductive Logic: Example
A Conception of Inductive Logic: Example Patrick Maher Department of Philosophy, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign This paper presents a simple example of inductive logic done according to the
ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC = DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION #2. h 0 h h 0 h h 0 ( ) g k = g 0 + g 1 + g g 2009 =?
Teko Classes IITJEE/AIEEE Maths by SUHAAG SIR, Bhopal, Ph (0755) 3 00 000 www.tekoclasses.com ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION # Question Type A.Single Correct Type Q. (A) Sol least
Section 8.3 Trigonometric Equations
99 Section 8. Trigonometric Equations Objective 1: Solve Equations Involving One Trigonometric Function. In this section and the next, we will exple how to solving equations involving trigonometric functions.
A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation
International Mathematical Forum, 5, 2010, no. 67, 3301-3307 A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy Equivalence Relation D. K. Basnet Dept. of Mathematics, Assam University Silchar-788011, Assam, India dkbasnet@rediffmail.com
Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016
Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016 Silvio Capobianco Exercise 1.7 Let H(n) = J(n + 1) J(n). Equation (1.8) tells us that H(2n) = 2, and H(2n+1) = J(2n+2) J(2n+1) = (2J(n+1) 1) (2J(n)+1)
Example Sheet 3 Solutions
Example Sheet 3 Solutions. i Regular Sturm-Liouville. ii Singular Sturm-Liouville mixed boundary conditions. iii Not Sturm-Liouville ODE is not in Sturm-Liouville form. iv Regular Sturm-Liouville note
Homework 3 Solutions
Homework 3 Solutions Igor Yanovsky (Math 151A TA) Problem 1: Compute the absolute error and relative error in approximations of p by p. (Use calculator!) a) p π, p 22/7; b) p π, p 3.141. Solution: For
Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs
Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs Who? Nichole Schimanski When? July 27, 2011 Graphs A graph, G, consists of a vertex set, V (G), and an edge set, E(G). V (G) is any finite set E(G) is
Homomorphism in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Automata
International Journal of Fuzzy Mathematics Systems. ISSN 2248-9940 Volume 3, Number 1 (2013), pp. 39-45 Research India Publications http://www.ripublication.com/ijfms.htm Homomorphism in Intuitionistic
Finite Field Problems: Solutions
Finite Field Problems: Solutions 1. Let f = x 2 +1 Z 11 [x] and let F = Z 11 [x]/(f), a field. Let Solution: F =11 2 = 121, so F = 121 1 = 120. The possible orders are the divisors of 120. Solution: The
Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets
Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets S K Mala #1, Dr. MM Shanmugapriya *2 1 PhD Scholar in Mathematics, Karpagam University, Coimbatore, Tamilnadu- 641021 Assistant Professor of Mathematics,
Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3
Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3 1 State vector space and the dual space Space of wavefunctions The space of wavefunctions is the set of all
Problem Set 3: Solutions
CMPSCI 69GG Applied Information Theory Fall 006 Problem Set 3: Solutions. [Cover and Thomas 7.] a Define the following notation, C I p xx; Y max X; Y C I p xx; Ỹ max I X; Ỹ We would like to show that C
Phys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required)
Phys460.nb 81 ψ n (t) is still the (same) eigenstate of H But for tdependent H. The answer is NO. 5.5.5. Solution for the tdependent Schrodinger s equation If we assume that at time t 0, the electron starts
About these lecture notes. Simply Typed λ-calculus. Types
About these lecture notes Simply Typed λ-calculus Akim Demaille akim@lrde.epita.fr EPITA École Pour l Informatique et les Techniques Avancées Many of these slides are largely inspired from Andrew D. Ker
Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval
Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential Equations Let a (t), a 2 (t),..., a nn (t), b (t), b 2 (t),..., b n (t) be continuous functions on the interval I. The system of n first-order differential equations
CHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS
CHAPTER 5 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS EXERCISE 104 Page 8 1. Find the positive root of the equation x + 3x 5 = 0, correct to 3 significant figures, using the method of bisection. Let f(x) =
MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS
MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS FUMIE NAKAOKA AND NOBUYUKI ODA Received 20 December 2005; Revised 28 May 2006; Accepted 6 August 2006 Some properties of minimal closed sets and maximal closed
Math221: HW# 1 solutions
Math: HW# solutions Andy Royston October, 5 7.5.7, 3 rd Ed. We have a n = b n = a = fxdx = xdx =, x cos nxdx = x sin nx n sin nxdx n = cos nx n = n n, x sin nxdx = x cos nx n + cos nxdx n cos n = + sin
Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests
Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests Shirsendu Mukherjee Department of Statistics, Asutosh College, Kolkata, India. shirsendu st@yahoo.co.in So far we have treated the testing of one-sided
Math 6 SL Probability Distributions Practice Test Mark Scheme
Math 6 SL Probability Distributions Practice Test Mark Scheme. (a) Note: Award A for vertical line to right of mean, A for shading to right of their vertical line. AA N (b) evidence of recognizing symmetry
Solutions to Exercise Sheet 5
Solutions to Eercise Sheet 5 jacques@ucsd.edu. Let X and Y be random variables with joint pdf f(, y) = 3y( + y) where and y. Determine each of the following probabilities. Solutions. a. P (X ). b. P (X
Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics
Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics Nov 1, 01 In this lecture we examine root systems from an axiomatic point of view. 1 Reflections If v R n, then it determines a hyperplane, denoted P v, through the
Reminders: linear functions
Reminders: linear functions Let U and V be vector spaces over the same field F. Definition A function f : U V is linear if for every u 1, u 2 U, f (u 1 + u 2 ) = f (u 1 ) + f (u 2 ), and for every u U
6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes
122 CHAPTER 6. ARMA MODELS 6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes The purpose of forecasting is to predict future values of a TS based on the data collected to the present. In this section we will discuss a linear
The Simply Typed Lambda Calculus
Type Inference Instead of writing type annotations, can we use an algorithm to infer what the type annotations should be? That depends on the type system. For simple type systems the answer is yes, and
Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests
Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests Side-Note: So far we have seen a few approaches for creating tests such as Neyman-Pearson Lemma ( most powerful tests of H 0 : θ = θ 0 vs H 1 :
HOMEWORK 4 = G. In order to plot the stress versus the stretch we define a normalized stretch:
HOMEWORK 4 Problem a For the fast loading case, we want to derive the relationship between P zz and λ z. We know that the nominal stress is expressed as: P zz = ψ λ z where λ z = λ λ z. Therefore, applying
Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in
Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in : tail in X, head in A nowhere-zero Γ-flow is a Γ-circulation such that
The challenges of non-stable predicates
The challenges of non-stable predicates Consider a non-stable predicate Φ encoding, say, a safety property. We want to determine whether Φ holds for our program. The challenges of non-stable predicates
Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5. Luca Alberucci, University of Berne. Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008
Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5 Luca Alberucci, University of Berne Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008 Introduction Koz: Axiomatisation for the modal µ-calculus over K Axioms: All classical
ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER
ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER Abstract. We define ordinal arithmetic and show laws of Left- Monotonicity, Associativity, Distributivity, some minor related properties and the Cantor Normal Form.
Section 7.6 Double and Half Angle Formulas
09 Section 7. Double and Half Angle Fmulas To derive the double-angles fmulas, we will use the sum of two angles fmulas that we developed in the last section. We will let α θ and β θ: cos(θ) cos(θ + θ)
Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees
Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees Thomas F. Kent Andrea Sorbi Università degli Studi di Siena Italia July 18, 2007 Goal: Introduce a form of Σ 0 2-permitting for the enumeration degrees. Till now,
Abstract Storage Devices
Abstract Storage Devices Robert König Ueli Maurer Stefano Tessaro SOFSEM 2009 January 27, 2009 Outline 1. Motivation: Storage Devices 2. Abstract Storage Devices (ASD s) 3. Reducibility 4. Factoring ASD
Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2
International Journal of Algebra, Vol. 8, 24, no. 5, 239-246 HIKARI Ltd, www.m-hikari.com http://dx.doi.org/.2988/ija.24.422 Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2 Ligong An and
Matrices and Determinants
Matrices and Determinants SUBJECTIVE PROBLEMS: Q 1. For what value of k do the following system of equations possess a non-trivial (i.e., not all zero) solution over the set of rationals Q? x + ky + 3z
Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequality for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x, y, z X.
Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequalit for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x,, z X. Prove that d(x, z) d(, z) d(x, ). (ii): Reverse triangle inequalit for norms:
PARTIAL NOTES for 6.1 Trigonometric Identities
PARTIAL NOTES for 6.1 Trigonometric Identities tanθ = sinθ cosθ cotθ = cosθ sinθ BASIC IDENTITIES cscθ = 1 sinθ secθ = 1 cosθ cotθ = 1 tanθ PYTHAGOREAN IDENTITIES sin θ + cos θ =1 tan θ +1= sec θ 1 + cot
Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor
Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor Given f L 1 T 1 ), we consider the partial sums of the Fourier series of f: N 1) S N fθ) = ˆfk)e ikθ. k= N A calculation gives the Dirichlet formula
Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II
Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II October 18, 2012 1 Review First let us recall the situation. Let g be a simple algebra, with maximal toral subalgebra h (which we are calling a CSA, or Cartan Subalgebra).
k A = [k, k]( )[a 1, a 2 ] = [ka 1,ka 2 ] 4For the division of two intervals of confidence in R +
Chapter 3. Fuzzy Arithmetic 3- Fuzzy arithmetic: ~Addition(+) and subtraction (-): Let A = [a and B = [b, b in R If x [a and y [b, b than x+y [a +b +b Symbolically,we write A(+)B = [a (+)[b, b = [a +b
Strukturalna poprawność argumentu.
Strukturalna poprawność argumentu. Marcin Selinger Uniwersytet Wrocławski Katedra Logiki i Metodologii Nauk marcisel@uni.wroc.pl Table of contents: 1. Definition of argument and further notions. 2. Operations
ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II
ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II 2014/2015: Semester II Tutorial 7 1. Let X be a sample from a population P and consider testing hypotheses H 0 : P = P 0 versus H 1 : P = P 1, where P j is a known
Fourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics
Fourier Series MATH 211, Calculus II J. Robert Buchanan Department of Mathematics Spring 2018 Introduction Not all functions can be represented by Taylor series. f (k) (c) A Taylor series f (x) = (x c)
Συντακτικές λειτουργίες
2 Συντακτικές λειτουργίες (Syntactic functions) A. Πτώσεις και συντακτικές λειτουργίες (Cases and syntactic functions) The subject can be identified by asking ποιος (who) or τι (what) the sentence is about.
Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations. ------------------ ----------------------------- -----------------
Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations. 1. Sin ( ) = a) b) c) d) Ans b. Solution : Method 1. Ans a: 17 > 1 a) is rejected. w.k.t Sin ( sin ) = d is rejected. If sin
Formal Semantics. 1 Type Logic
Formal Semantics Principle of Compositionality The meaning of a sentence is determined by the meanings of its parts and the way they are put together. 1 Type Logic Types (a measure on expressions) The
Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates
Kiryl Tsishchanka Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates In this section we develop the formula for the area of a region whose boundary is given by a polar equation. We need to use the formula for the
Example of the Baum-Welch Algorithm
Example of the Baum-Welch Algorithm Larry Moss Q520, Spring 2008 1 Our corpus c We start with a very simple corpus. We take the set Y of unanalyzed words to be {ABBA, BAB}, and c to be given by c(abba)
forms This gives Remark 1. How to remember the above formulas: Substituting these into the equation we obtain with
Week 03: C lassification of S econd- Order L inear Equations In last week s lectures we have illustrated how to obtain the general solutions of first order PDEs using the method of characteristics. We
Partial Differential Equations in Biology The boundary element method. March 26, 2013
The boundary element method March 26, 203 Introduction and notation The problem: u = f in D R d u = ϕ in Γ D u n = g on Γ N, where D = Γ D Γ N, Γ D Γ N = (possibly, Γ D = [Neumann problem] or Γ N = [Dirichlet
Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval
Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential Equations Let a (t), a 2 (t),..., a nn (t), b (t), b 2 (t),..., b n (t) be continuous functions on the interval I. The system of n first-order differential equations
Practice Exam 2. Conceptual Questions. 1. State a Basic identity and then verify it. (a) Identity: Solution: One identity is csc(θ) = 1
Conceptual Questions. State a Basic identity and then verify it. a) Identity: Solution: One identity is cscθ) = sinθ) Practice Exam b) Verification: Solution: Given the point of intersection x, y) of the
Απόκριση σε Μοναδιαία Ωστική Δύναμη (Unit Impulse) Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο. Απόστολος Σ.
Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο The time integral of a force is referred to as impulse, is determined by and is obtained from: Newton s 2 nd Law of motion states that the action
5. Choice under Uncertainty
5. Choice under Uncertainty Daisuke Oyama Microeconomics I May 23, 2018 Formulations von Neumann-Morgenstern (1944/1947) X: Set of prizes Π: Set of probability distributions on X : Preference relation
Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates
Kiryl Tsishchanka Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates In this section we develop the formula for the area of a region whose boundary is given by a polar equation. We need to use the formula for the
Jesse Maassen and Mark Lundstrom Purdue University November 25, 2013
Notes on Average Scattering imes and Hall Factors Jesse Maassen and Mar Lundstrom Purdue University November 5, 13 I. Introduction 1 II. Solution of the BE 1 III. Exercises: Woring out average scattering
ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 19/5/2007
Οδηγίες: Να απαντηθούν όλες οι ερωτήσεις. Αν κάπου κάνετε κάποιες υποθέσεις να αναφερθούν στη σχετική ερώτηση. Όλα τα αρχεία που αναφέρονται στα προβλήματα βρίσκονται στον ίδιο φάκελο με το εκτελέσιμο
SCITECH Volume 13, Issue 2 RESEARCH ORGANISATION Published online: March 29, 2018
Journal of rogressive Research in Mathematics(JRM) ISSN: 2395-028 SCITECH Volume 3, Issue 2 RESEARCH ORGANISATION ublished online: March 29, 208 Journal of rogressive Research in Mathematics www.scitecresearch.com/journals
6.1. Dirac Equation. Hamiltonian. Dirac Eq.
6.1. Dirac Equation Ref: M.Kaku, Quantum Field Theory, Oxford Univ Press (1993) η μν = η μν = diag(1, -1, -1, -1) p 0 = p 0 p = p i = -p i p μ p μ = p 0 p 0 + p i p i = E c 2 - p 2 = (m c) 2 H = c p 2
Μηχανική Μάθηση Hypothesis Testing
ΕΛΛΗΝΙΚΗ ΔΗΜΟΚΡΑΤΙΑ ΠΑΝΕΠΙΣΤΗΜΙΟ ΚΡΗΤΗΣ Μηχανική Μάθηση Hypothesis Testing Γιώργος Μπορμπουδάκης Τμήμα Επιστήμης Υπολογιστών Procedure 1. Form the null (H 0 ) and alternative (H 1 ) hypothesis 2. Consider
Econ 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1
Eon : Fall 8 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 Email questions or omments to Dan Fetter Problem. Let X be a salar with density f(x, θ) (θx + θ) [ x ] with θ. (a) Find the most powerful level α test
1. Introduction and Preliminaries.
Faculty of Sciences and Mathematics, University of Niš, Serbia Available at: http://www.pmf.ni.ac.yu/filomat Filomat 22:1 (2008), 97 106 ON δ SETS IN γ SPACES V. Renuka Devi and D. Sivaraj Abstract We
LTL to Buchi. Overview. Buchi Model Checking LTL Translating LTL into Buchi. Ralf Huuck. Buchi Automata. Example
Overview LTL to Buchi Buchi Model Checking LTL Translating LTL into Buchi Ralf Huuck Buchi Automata Example Automaton which accepts infinite traces δ A Buchi automaton is 5-tuple Σ, Q, Q 0,δ, F Σ is a
Second Order Partial Differential Equations
Chapter 7 Second Order Partial Differential Equations 7.1 Introduction A second order linear PDE in two independent variables (x, y Ω can be written as A(x, y u x + B(x, y u xy + C(x, y u u u + D(x, y
SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS
Sahand Communications in Mathematical Analysis (SCMA) Vol. 3 No. 1 (2016), 21-27 http://scma.maragheh.ac.ir SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS BAYAZ DARABY 1 AND JAVAD JAFARI 2 Abstract. In the mathematical
Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude
Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude Jan Behrens 2012-12-31 In this paper we shall provide a method to approximate distances between two points on earth
F-TF Sum and Difference angle
F-TF Sum and Difference angle formulas Alignments to Content Standards: F-TF.C.9 Task In this task, you will show how all of the sum and difference angle formulas can be derived from a single formula when
ΠΤΥΧΙΑΚΗ ΕΡΓΑΣΙΑ ΒΑΛΕΝΤΙΝΑ ΠΑΠΑΔΟΠΟΥΛΟΥ Α.Μ.: 09/061. Υπεύθυνος Καθηγητής: Σάββας Μακρίδης
Α.Τ.Ε.Ι. ΙΟΝΙΩΝ ΝΗΣΩΝ ΠΑΡΑΡΤΗΜΑ ΑΡΓΟΣΤΟΛΙΟΥ ΤΜΗΜΑ ΔΗΜΟΣΙΩΝ ΣΧΕΣΕΩΝ ΚΑΙ ΕΠΙΚΟΙΝΩΝΙΑΣ ΠΤΥΧΙΑΚΗ ΕΡΓΑΣΙΑ «Η διαμόρφωση επικοινωνιακής στρατηγικής (και των τακτικών ενεργειών) για την ενδυνάμωση της εταιρικής
5.4 The Poisson Distribution.
The worst thing you can do about a situation is nothing. Sr. O Shea Jackson 5.4 The Poisson Distribution. Description of the Poisson Distribution Discrete probability distribution. The random variable
Potential Dividers. 46 minutes. 46 marks. Page 1 of 11
Potential Dividers 46 minutes 46 marks Page 1 of 11 Q1. In the circuit shown in the figure below, the battery, of negligible internal resistance, has an emf of 30 V. The pd across the lamp is 6.0 V and
Solution Series 9. i=1 x i and i=1 x i.
Lecturer: Prof. Dr. Mete SONER Coordinator: Yilin WANG Solution Series 9 Q1. Let α, β >, the p.d.f. of a beta distribution with parameters α and β is { Γ(α+β) Γ(α)Γ(β) f(x α, β) xα 1 (1 x) β 1 for < x
Second Order RLC Filters
ECEN 60 Circuits/Electronics Spring 007-0-07 P. Mathys Second Order RLC Filters RLC Lowpass Filter A passive RLC lowpass filter (LPF) circuit is shown in the following schematic. R L C v O (t) Using phasor
Mean bond enthalpy Standard enthalpy of formation Bond N H N N N N H O O O
Q1. (a) Explain the meaning of the terms mean bond enthalpy and standard enthalpy of formation. Mean bond enthalpy... Standard enthalpy of formation... (5) (b) Some mean bond enthalpies are given below.
TMA4115 Matematikk 3
TMA4115 Matematikk 3 Andrew Stacey Norges Teknisk-Naturvitenskapelige Universitet Trondheim Spring 2010 Lecture 12: Mathematics Marvellous Matrices Andrew Stacey Norges Teknisk-Naturvitenskapelige Universitet
DIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANSFORMATION SEMIGROUPS
GANIT J. Bangladesh Math. oc. IN 606-694) 0) -7 DIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANFORMATION EMIGROUP ubrata Majumdar, * Kalyan Kumar Dey and Mohd. Altab Hossain Department of Mathematics University
Models for Probabilistic Programs with an Adversary
Models for Probabilistic Programs with an Adversary Robert Rand, Steve Zdancewic University of Pennsylvania Probabilistic Programming Semantics 2016 Interactive Proofs 2/47 Interactive Proofs 2/47 Interactive
Strain gauge and rosettes
Strain gauge and rosettes Introduction A strain gauge is a device which is used to measure strain (deformation) on an object subjected to forces. Strain can be measured using various types of devices classified
Section 9.2 Polar Equations and Graphs
180 Section 9. Polar Equations and Graphs In this section, we will be graphing polar equations on a polar grid. In the first few examples, we will write the polar equation in rectangular form to help identify
SOLVING CUBICS AND QUARTICS BY RADICALS
SOLVING CUBICS AND QUARTICS BY RADICALS The purpose of this handout is to record the classical formulas expressing the roots of degree three and degree four polynomials in terms of radicals. We begin with
Overview. Transition Semantics. Configurations and the transition relation. Executions and computation
Overview Transition Semantics Configurations and the transition relation Executions and computation Inference rules for small-step structural operational semantics for the simple imperative language Transition
On a four-dimensional hyperbolic manifold with finite volume
BULETINUL ACADEMIEI DE ŞTIINŢE A REPUBLICII MOLDOVA. MATEMATICA Numbers 2(72) 3(73), 2013, Pages 80 89 ISSN 1024 7696 On a four-dimensional hyperbolic manifold with finite volume I.S.Gutsul Abstract. In
Srednicki Chapter 55
Srednicki Chapter 55 QFT Problems & Solutions A. George August 3, 03 Srednicki 55.. Use equations 55.3-55.0 and A i, A j ] = Π i, Π j ] = 0 (at equal times) to verify equations 55.-55.3. This is our third
λρ-calculus 1. each λ-variable is a λρ-term, called an atom or atomic term; 2. if M and N are λρ-term then (MN) is a λρ-term called an application;
λρ-calculus Yuichi Komori komori@math.s.chiba-u.ac.jp Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Sciences, Chiba University Arato Cho aratoc@g.math.s.chiba-u.ac.jp Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Sciences,
SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM
SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM Solutions to Question 1 a) The cumulative distribution function of T conditional on N n is Pr (T t N n) Pr (max (X 1,..., X N ) t N n) Pr (max