18 Completeness Theorem for Axiom System AS1+Q for CPL
|
|
- Ἀμιναδάβ Γλυκύς
- 6 χρόνια πριν
- Προβολές:
Transcript
1 18 Completeness Theorem for Axiom System AS1+Q for CPL 1. Introduction The Construction of the Sequence Γ 1, Γ 2, Informal Account and Justification of the Construction Every Γ i in Γ 1, Γ 2, is Consistent The Construction of Ω, and Proof that it is Consistent Proof that Ω is Maximal Consistent w.r.t. Closed Formulas The Substitution/Quantification Lemma About Ω Showing that Ω is Verifiable Aside on Induction on Complexity Proof that ω Verifies the Formulas in Ω Appendix Completeness for CQL Derivation System for CQL for Closed Formulas Completeness for Closed Argument Forms Universal Derivation is Admissible Negation-Universal Elimination is Admissible; Existential Elimination is Admissible...18
2 2 Hardegree, MetaLogic 1. Introduction As mentioned earlier, in proving the major theorem, we proceed in small steps. First, we prove that AS1+Q is complete for Classical Predicate Logic (CPL), then we prove that it is complete for Classical Quantifier Logic (CQL). After that, we consider an axiom system for Classical First-Order Logic, and show that it is complete for CFOL. In proving completeness of AS1+Q for CPL, we proceed in a manner fairly similar to, but not exactly like, our proof that AS1 is complete for CSL. (1) We prove that every (deductively) consistent set can be extended to a maximal consistent set. The CPL-construction is slightly different from the SL-construction. (2) We prove that the maximal consistent set constructed in the manner specified in Part 1 is verifiable (semantically consistent). (3) We employ the two negation theorems NT1 and NT2 to prove that every CPL-valid argument is AS1+Q-valid [meaning that its conclusion can be derived from its premises using the rules of AS1]. 2. The Construction of the Sequence ÆG 1, G 2, æ Let be the official language of CPL. Let ε 1, ε 2, be an enumeration of the closed formulas of. Let c 1, c 2, be an enumeration of the constants of. Suppose additionally that both enumerations are one-to-one, meaning that ε i = ε j only if i=j, and c i = c j only if i=j. Suppose that Γ is a consistent set of closed formulas of ; further suppose that Γ does not contain any constants (recall Simplification #3). The construction of Γ 1, Γ 2, goes as follows. (1) Γ 1 = Γ (2) if Γ n {ε n } then: Γ n+1 = Γ n {ε n } if then: Γ n {ε n } if ε n is not a universal formula [i.e., ε vφ, for any v, φ] then: Γ n+1 = Γ n { ε n } if then: ε n is a universal formula, ε = vφ (for some v, φ), and Γ n+1 = Γ n { vφ} { φ[c/v]} where c is the* first constant (relative to c 1, c 2, ) not occurring in Γ n.
3 18: Completeness Theorem 3 *By hypothesis, Γ contains no constants. Given the definition of Γ 1, Γ 2,, Γ n has finitely-many formulas not in Γ, and each formula has finitely-many symbols, so at most finitely-many constants appear in Γ n. It follows, by ST, that there is a first constant not in Γ n. Thus, the description the first constant not in Γ n is referentially proper. 3. Informal Account and Justification of the Construction As the reader can see, the construction of Γ 1, Γ 2, in Section 2 is very similar to the SLconstruction. The only difference is the extra formula φ[c/v] added in the third case. The intuition is fairly straightforward. Everytime one adds a formula to the expanding set, one adds a corroborating formula (also called a witness ). This maneuver corresponds to the natural deduction rule O. Recall how this rule is formulated. vφ φ[c/v] where c does not appear earlier in the derivation [i.e., c is new ] So what we are doing in adding the extra formula is applying the rule O. Notice that the constant c substituted for v in φ is specified to be the first constant not appearing in Γ n in other words, c is new. One might naturally ask why this extra step is required. Why don t we just construct Γ 1, Γ 2, and Ω [= {Γ 1, Γ 2, }] the same way we do in SL? Then the proof would exactly parallel the proof for SL. We show Γ is contained in Ω, and Ω is verifiable, so Γ is verifiable, then apply NT1 and NT2 to show completeness. The answer is that the particular construction we choose makes showing that Ω is verifiable easier to accomplish. As it turns out, some maximal consistent sets are easier to show verifiable than others. 4. Every G i in ÆG 1, G 2, æ is Consistent Having constructed Γ 1, Γ 2,, we next show every Γ n is consistent, which is accomplished by (simple, weak) math induction. (1) : n[γ n ] MI [n 1] Base Case: (2) : Γ 1 3,4,IL (3) Γ 1 = Γ Def Γ 1, Γ 2, (4) Γ by hypothesis Inductive Case: (5) : n{γ n Γ n+1 } UCD (6) Γ n As (7) : Γ n+1 SC Given the definition of Γ n+1 in terms of Γ n there are two cases to consider, the second of which divides into two cases. (8) c1: Γ n {ε n } As (9) Γ n+1 = Γ n {ε n } 8, Def Γ 1, Γ 2, (10) Γ n+1 6,9,IL
4 4 Hardegree, MetaLogic (11) c2: Γ n {ε n } As (12) c2.1: ε n is not a universal As (13) Γ n+1 = Γ n { ε n } 11, Def Γ 1, Γ 2, (14) Γ n { ε n } 11,earlier result about AS1 AS1+Q contains the full deductive apparatus of AS1, so results about AS1 can simply be transferred to AS1+Q. (15) Γ n+1 13,14,IL (16) c2.2: ε n is a universal As (17) ε n = vφ 16,def(is a universal), O (18) let c = the first constant not in Γ n see Section 2 for justification (19) Γ n+1 = Γ n { vφ} { φ[c/v]} 16,17,18,Def Γ 1, Γ 2, given 19, in order to show Γ n+1, the following suffices: (20) : Γ n { vφ} { φ[c/v]} ID (21) Γ n { vφ} { φ[c/v]} As (22) : 6,29,SL (23) Γ n ε n 11,NT1 (24) Γ n vφ 17,23,IL (25) Γ n { vφ} φ[c/v] 20,NT1 (26) Γ n φ[c/v] 24,25,GenTh( ) (27) c * Γ n 18, description logic (28) Γ n vφ 26,27,UDT (29) Γ n 24,28,earlier result about AS1 5. The Construction of W, and Proof that it is Consistent Next, given Γ 1, Γ 2,, as defined above, we define Ω as follows. Ω = {Γ 1, Γ 2, } The proof that Ω is consistent duplicates the result for AS1, which we summarize here. (1) : Ω DD (2) Ω = {Γ 1, Γ 2, } Def of Ω (3) n{γ i Γ n+1 } L03 (4) {Γ 1, Γ 2, } 3,L01,L02,QL (5) Ω 2,4,IL Subordinate Lemmas: L01: n[γ n ] proven above L02: n{γ n Γ n+1 } & n[γ n ]. {Γ 1, Γ 2, } This result, proven earlier about AS1, transfers to AS1+Q.
5 18: Completeness Theorem 5 L03: n{γ n Γ n+1 } This result, proven earlier about AS1, transfers to AS1+Q. 6. Proof that W is Maximal Consistent w.r.t. Closed Formulas Next, we prove that Ω is maximal consistent w.r.t. closed formulas, which may be defined as follows. MC[Ω] = df Ω & α{closed[α] {α Ω. Ω {α} }} We have already shown the first conjunct that Ω is consistent. The second conjunct is proven like the analogous result about AS1, which is reproduced here. (1) : α{closed[α] {α Ω. Ω {α} }} UCCD (2) closed[α] As (3) α Ω As (4) : Ω {α} DD (5) α Ω 3,L04,QL (6) Ω α 5,GenTh( ) (7) Ω {α} α 6,GenTh( ) (8) Ω {α} α GenTh( ) (9) Ω {α} 7,8, result about AS1
6 6 Hardegree, MetaLogic L04: " a{a W xor a W } (0) α{closed[α] {α Ω xor α Ω}} UCD (1) closed[α] As (2) : α Ω xor α Ω 3,16,Def(xor) (3) : α Ω or α Ω 5,10,SL (4) n[α = ε n ] 1, Def ε 1, ε 2, (5) α = ε n 5, O (6) : Γ n {ε n } α Ω CD (7) Γ n {ε n } As (8) : α Ω 5,10,IL (9) Γ n+1 = Γ n {ε n } 7, Def Γ 1, Γ 2, (10) ε n Ω 9,Def Ω,ST (11) : Γ n {ε n } α Ω CD (12) Γ n {ε n } As (13) : α Ω 5,15,IL (14) Γ n+1 = Γ n { ε n } 10, Def Γ 1, Γ 2, (15) ε n Ω 14,Def Ω,ST (16) : {α Ω & α Ω} ID (17) α Ω & α Ω As (18) : 21,22 (19) Ω α 17a, since Ω is MC, it is deductively closed (20) Ω α 17b, since Ω is MC, it is deductively closed (21) Ω 19,20,result about AS1 (22) Ω shown earlier 7. The Substitution/Quantification Lemma About W In the Chapter on Soundness, we proved the Substitution/Quantification Lemma, which is about admissible valuations in CFOL. In the present section, we prove an analogous lemma about the constructed set Ω. L05: " v W «" c{ [c/v] W } [ ] Suppose v Ω, and suppose c is a closed singular term. First, v [c/v] is an axiom of AS1+Q, so we have v [c/v], so we have Ω [c/v]. Next, by an earlier theorem, Ω is maximal consistent, which by yet another earlier theorem entails that it is closed under deductive consequence. It follows that [c/v] Ω.
7 18: Completeness Theorem 7 (1) : CD (2) c{ [c/v] Ω} As (3) : v Ω ID (4) v Ω As (5) : DD (6) n[ v = ε n ] Def ε 1, ε 2, (7) v = ε n 6, O (8) : Γ n { v } ID (9) Γ n { v } As (10) : 4,12,SL (11) Γ n {ε n } 7,9,IL (12) Γ n+1 = Γ n {ε n } 11,Def Γ 1, Γ 2, (13) Γ n+1 = Γ n { v } 7,12,IL (14) v Ω 13, Def Ω, ST (15) Γ n+1 = Γ n { v } { [c 0 /v]} (some c 0 ) 7,8,Def Γ 1, Γ 2, (16) [c 0 /v] Ω 15, Def Ω (17) [c 0 /v] Ω 2,QL (18) 16,17,L04 8. Showing that W is Verifiable Our next step is to show that our constructed set Ω is verifiable, which is to say there is a CFOLadmissible valuation that verifies every formula in Ω, and hence every formula in our original set Γ. We proceed as follows. First, we define the underlying domain of discourse (universe) U as follows. U = C N where and C = the set of constants of N = the set of proper nouns of In other words, U = the set of all the closed singular terms of Next, define an interpretation function I, and partial assignment function, as follows. (c) = c for every constant c I(n) = n for every proper noun n I( ) = { u 1,,u k : u 1 u k Ω} for every k-place predicate, for every k Now, one can routinely show that there is at least one admissible valuation that extends I and [exercise]. Let ω be one such valuation. In other words: ω is CFOL-admissible ω(c) = (c) for every constant c ω(n) = I(n) for every proper noun n ω( ) = I( ) for every k-place predicate, for every k What we wish to show is that ω verifies every formula in Ω. We in fact prove that ω verifies a formula if and only if it is in Ω.
8 8 Hardegree, MetaLogic 9. Aside on Induction on Complexity In doing the proof that ω verifies every formula in Ω, we will employing a deductive technique called induction on formula-complexity. First, the general notion of syntactic complexity may be defined as follows, where it is assumed that ε is a grammatically well-formed expression of. complexity(ε) = df the number of functor-occurrences in ε Note, in this connection, that we count quantifiers as two-place functors: vφ = v,φ. Subordinate to this is the notion of term-complexity, which is defined just for singular terms, and formula-complexity, which is defined just for formulas, as follows. term-complexity(τ) = df the number of function sign occurrences in τ formula-complexity(φ) = df the number of logical operator occurrences in φ Note, in this connection, that we count quantifier expressions (e.g., x, y ) as one-place logical operators. The following are examples. Expression Syntactic Term- Formula- Complexity Complexity Complexity a 0 0 f(a) 1 1 f(f(a)) 2 2 s(f(a), f(b)) 3 3 P[a] 1 0 P[f(a)] 2 0 P[f(f(a))] 3 0 Fx Gx 3 1 x(fx Gx) 4 2 x(fx Gx) 5 3 Now, every grammatical expression of a formal language has a complexity, so in order to show: ε [ε] [where ε is understood to be an expression of ] we need merely show: n ε{complexity(ε) = n [ε]} The latter can be shown either by weak induction or strong induction. Let us concentrate on strong induction, which is often more useful. Then the inductive case is officially written as follows. Assume: k{k<n ε{complexity(ε) = k [ε]}}
9 18: Completeness Theorem 9 Show: ε{complexity(ε) = n [ε]} The inductive case can be simplified if we introduce the notion simpler than, defined as follows. ε 1 < ε 2 = df complexity(ε 1 ) < complexity(ε 2 ) Specifically, appealing to some fairly obvious principles of arithmetic, we can instead write the inductive case as follows. Assume: Show: ε {ε < ε [ε ]} [ε] The general case may not be useful. It is often easier to do proofs about singular terms, or about formulas. That is where the notions of term-complexity and formula complexity arise. For example, in dealing with CPL, we can do many proofs using induction on formula-complexity. In that case, we can write the inductive case as follows, where φ ranges over formulas of. Assume: φ{φ < φ 0 [φ]} Show: [φ 0 ] 10. Proof that w Verifies the Formulas in W (a1) ω is CFOL-admissible As (a2) ω(c) = (c) for every constant c As (a3) ω(n) = I(n) for every proper noun n As (a4) ω( ) = I( ) for every k-place predicate, for every k As (a5) (c) = c for every constant c As (a6) I(n) = n for every proper noun n As (a7) I( ) = { u 1,,u k : u 1 u k Ω} for every k-place predicate, for every k As I( ) τ τ Ω alternate description (1) : φ{ω(φ) = T φ Ω} induction on complexity of φ (2) φ {φ < φ {ω(φ ) = T φ Ω}} IH (3) : ω(φ) = T φ Ω separation of cases (4) φ is atomic or molecular (i.e., not atomic) SL (5) c1: φ is atomic As (6) see below (7) c2: φ is molecular As (8) φ is a universal, or a negation, or a conditional 6, def CPL (9) c2.1: φ is a universal As (10) see below (11) c2.2: φ is a negation As (12) see below (13) c2.3: φ is a conditional As (14) see below
10 10 Hardegree, MetaLogic Subordinate Cases: Case 1: Case 2.1: Case 2.2: Case 2.3: (1) φ is atomic As (2) : ω(φ) = T φ Ω 3,4,IL (3) φ = τ 1,, τ k (some, τ 1,, τ k ) Def(atomic), O (4) : ω( τ 1,, τ k ) = T τ 1,, τ k Ω 5,8,9,SL (5) ω( τ 1,, τ k ) = T ω( ) ω(τ 1 ),, ω(τ k ) = T a1, def(val) (6) ω( ) = I( ) a4 (7) i k: ω(τ i ) = I(τ i ) = τ i a2,a3 (8) ω( ) ω(τ 1 ),, ω(τ k ) = T I( ) τ 1,, τ k = T 6,7,IL (9) I( ) τ 1,, τ k = T τ 1,, τ k Ω a7 (1) φ is a universal As (2) : ω(φ) = T φ Ω 3,4,IL (3) φ = x (some x, ) def(universal), O (4) : ω( x ) = T x Ω 6,8,9,SL (5) every element of U has a name according to ω (6) ω( x ) = T c{ω( [c/v]) = T} 5,SubQ (7) c{ [c/v] < x } (8) c{ω( [c/v]) = T [c/v] Ω} 7,IH,QL (9) x Ω c{ [c/v] Ω} SubQ for Ω (1) φ is a negation As (2) : ω(φ) = T φ Ω 3,4,IL (3) φ = β (some β) def(negation), O (4) : ω( β) = T β Ω 5,8,9,SL (5) ω( β) = T ω(β) = F def(val) (6) β is simpler than β obvious (7) ω(β) = T β Ω 6,IH (8) ω(β) = F β Ω 7,def(val),SL (9) β Ω β Ω L04 (1) φ is a conditional As (2) : ω(φ) = T φ Ω 3,4,IL (3) φ = α β (some α, β) def(conditional), O (4) : ω(α β) = T α β Ω 5,7,9,10,SL (5) ω(α β) = T. ω(α) = F or ω(β) = T def(val) (6) α is simpler than α β obvious (7) ω(α) = F α Ω 6,IH (8) β is simpler than α β obvious (9) ω(β) = T β Ω 8,IH (10) α β Ω. α Ω or β Ω earlier result about AS1
11 18: Completeness Theorem Appendix Completeness for CQL 1. Derivation System for CQL for Closed Formulas Rules of CSL (R1) (R2) (R3) (R4) / α (β α) / [α (β γ)] [(α β) (α γ)] / ( α β) (β α) α, α β / β New Rules (R5) / v [t/v] where t is closed (R6) / v where v is not free in (R7) / v( ) ( v v ) (R8) π( [c/v]) / v where π( [c/v]) are prior lines that prove [c/v] 2. Completeness for Closed Argument Forms Assume is a CQL without constants; assume + is augmented by a denumerable set C of constants, one of which is c 0. Assume Γ is a consistent set of closed formulas of ; assume σ 1, σ 2, is an enumeration of the closed formulas +. [[Constants play the same role here that they do in derivations they are ad hoc names of objects in the domain; they are like variables, except that they are not quantified.]] Construct Γ 1, Γ 2,, U 1, U 2,, and D 1, D 2, inductively as follows.
12 12 Hardegree, MetaLogic Base Cases: a) U 1 = P {c 0 } b) Γ 1 = Γ c) D 1 = Inductive Cases: c1: if at least one constant in σ n is already discarded [ c{c σ n & c D n }], then: a) D n+1 = D n b) U n+1 = U n c) Γ n+1 = Γ n c2: otherwise: c2.1: if every constant in σ n is already used [ c{c σ n c U n }], then: a) D n+1 = D n b) U n+1 = U n c) c2.1.1: if Γ n {σ n }, then: Γ n+1 = Γ n {σ n } c2.1.2: otherwise: Γ n+1 = Γ n { σ n } c2.2: if any constant c in σ n is not already used [i.e., c σ n & c U n ], then: c2.2.1: if α Γ n {α= vφ & σ n = φ[c/v]}, then: a) D n+1 = D n b) U n+1 = U n {c} c) Γ n+1 = Γ n {σ n } c2.2.2: otherwise: a) D n+1 = D n {c} b) U n+1 = U n c) Γ n+1 = Γ n
13 18: Completeness Theorem 13 Ω = {Γ 1, Γ 2, } U = {U 1, U 2, } υ(α) = T if α* Ω υ(α) = F if α* Ω υ(τ) = τ* if τ is a term υ(ώ) = { u 1,,u k, ώu 1 u k : u 1 u k Ω} if ώ is a k-place function sign υ( ) = { u 1,,u k : u 1 u k Ω} if is a k-place predicate ε* = df the result of replacing every free variable in ε by c 0. Show: n[γ n ]. Then by the compactness of derivations, Ω. Show: γ{γ Γ & c γ}. Γ { [c/v]} α Γ { v } α Show: υ( τ 1 τ k ) = [υ( )] υ(τ 1 ),,υ(τ k ) Show: υ(ώτ 1 τ k ) = [υ(ώ)] υ(τ 1 ),,υ(τ k ) Show: υ(α β) = υ(α) υ(β) Show: υ( α) = υ(α) Show: υ( x k ) = min{υ ( ): υ k υ} υ k υ = df i{i k υ (x i ) = υ(x i )}
14 14 Hardegree, MetaLogic Practice Proof: (1) : xfx Ω u{u U Fu Ω} D (2) : CD (3) xfx Ω As (4) : u{u U Fu Ω} UCD (5) c U As (6) : Fc Ω ID (7) Fc Ω As (8) : DD (9) Fc Ω 7,Lemma (10) 3,9,Earlier Theorem (11) : CD (12) c{c U Fc Ω} As (13) : xfx Ω ID (14) xfx Ω As (15) : DD (16) xfx Ω 13,Lemma (17) n{ xfx Γ n } 16,Def Ω,ST (18) xfx Γ n 17, O (19) finite[u n ] lemma (20) finite[d n ] lemma (21) k c{k>n & c U n D n & Fc = σ k } 19,20,lemma (22) k>n 21, &O (23) c U n D n 21, &O (24) Fc = σ k 21, &O (25) Fc Γ k+1 18,22,23,24,Def Γ i (26) c U k+1 18,22,23,24,Def U i (27) c U 26, Def U (28) Fc Ω 25, Def Ω (29) Fc Ω 12,28,QL (30) 28,29,Lemma
15 18: Completeness Theorem 15 Real Proof: (1) : v Ω u{u U [u/v] Ω} D (2) : CD (3) v As (4) : u{u U [u/v] Ω} UCD (5) c U As (6) : [c/v] Ω ID (7) [c/v] Ω As (8) : DD (9) [c/v] Ω 7,Lemma (10) 3,9,Earlier Theorem (11) : CD (12) u{u U [u/v] Ω} As (13) : v Ω ID (14) v Ω As (15) : DD (16) v Ω 13,Lemma (17) n{ v Γ n } 16,Def Ω,ST (18) v Γ n 17, O (19) finite[u n ] lemma (20) finite[d n ] lemma (21) k c{k>n & c U n D n & [c/v] = σ k } 19,20,lemma (22) k>n 21, &O (23) c U n D n 21, &O (24) [c/v] = σ k 21, &O (25) [c/v] Γ k+1 18,22,23,24,Def Γ i (26) c U k+1 18,22,23,24,Def U i (27) c U 26, Def U (28) [c/v] Ω 25, Def Ω (29) [c/v] Ω 12,28,QL (30) 28,29,Lemma
16 16 Hardegree, MetaLogic σ 1 k σ 2 = df i{i k σ 1 i = σ 2 i} σ[u/k] = df the result of substituting u for σ k For example, a,b,c, [d/2] = a,d,c,, and c,d,e, [a/3] = c,d,a,. υ V: I σ: υ = val(i,σ); in particular, υ( ) = I( ) υ(ώ) = I(ώ) υ(ρ) = I(ρ) υ(x k ) = σ k I n = the instantiations at n i.e., every formula obtained by instantiating every open formula in Γ n to constant c 0, plus every formula obtained by multiple applications of O to formulas in Γ n using singular terms in U n. v 1 v k { Γ n & v 1,,v k are free in. [c/v 1,,c/v k ] I n } v 1 v k τ 1 τ k { v 1 v k ¹ Γ n & τ 1,,τ k U n. [τ 1 /v 1,,τ k /v k ] I n } *We describe this by saying that σ n corroborates vφ.
17 18: Completeness Theorem Universal Derivation is Admissible UDP: $g{g G & c g} fi. G [c/v] fi G " v (1) γ{γ Γ & c γ} As (2) : Γ [c/v] Γ v 3, lemma (3) : n: d{dd [c/v]/γ/n Γ v } SMI (4) k<n: d{dd [c/v]/γ/k Γ v } As (5) : d{dd [c/v]/γ/n Γ v } UCD (6) δd [c/v]/γ/n As (7) : Γ v Def (8) δ n = [c/v] 6,Def Dα/Γ/n (9) Ax{ [c/v]} or [c/v] Γ or GEN{ [c/v]} or MP{ [c/v]} 6,8,Def Dα/Γ/n (10) c1: Ax{ [c/v]} As (11) [c/v] proves [c/v] 7,9,Def proves (12) [c/v], v DER v [c/v]/γ inspection (13) d{dder v /Γ 11,QL (14) Γ v 12, Def (15) c2: [c/v] Γ As (16) : v not free in ID (17) v is free in As (18) : (19) c [c/v] 16, Def [c/v] (20) 1,14,18,QL (21) = [c/v] 14, Def [c/v] (22) / v R6 15, Def R6 (23) / [c/v] v R6 20,21,IL (24) [c/v], [c/v] v, v DER v [c/v]/γ 22+R4+inspection (25) d{dder v /Γ 23,QL (26) Γ v 24, Def (27) c3: GEN{ [c/v]} As (28) δ δ: δ proves [c/v][c /v ] & [c/v]= v [c/v] 27,Def GEN [R8] (29) δ + v proves v (30) d{d proves v } 29,QL (31) v 30, Def (32) Γ v 21,G? (33) c4: MP{ [c/v]} As (34) j,k<n, γ: d j =γ [c/v] & d k =γ 33,Def MP[] (35) j<n & d j =γ [c/v] 34, &O (36) k<n & d k =γ 34, &O (37) : d i : i j D γ [c/v] / Γ/ j Def D/n [&D] (38) a: : len d i : i j = j ST (39) b: : last d i : i j =γ [c/v] (40) last d i : i j = d j ST (41) c: : d i : i j DΓ Def ddγ (42) : δ d i : i j : Ax[δ] or δ Γ or GEN[δ] or MP[δ] UCD (43) δ d i : i j As (44) : Ax[δ] or δ Γ {α} or GEN[δ] or MP[δ] (45) δ d 32,ST (46) : d i : i k D γ / Γ {α} / k Def D/n (47) similar to derivation of line 37 (48) Γ v{γ } IH (49) Γ v{γ} IH (50) Γ v
18 18 Hardegree, MetaLogic 4. Negation-Universal Elimination is Admissible; Existential Elimination is Admissible L1: G { a} b fi G { b} a (1) : Γ { α} β Γ { β} α CD (2) Γ { α} β As (3) : Γ { β} α CDT (4) : Γ β α 5,7,MPP (5) Γ α β 2,DT (6) ( α β) ( β α) lemma (7) Γ ( α β) ( β α) lemma NUEP: $g{g G & c g} & cˇa fi. G { [c/v]} a fi G { " v } a (1) γ{γ Γ & c γ} As (2) c α As (3) : Γ { [c/v]} α Γ { v } α CD (4) Γ { [c/v]} α As (5) : Γ { v } α DD (6) Γ { α} [c/v] 3,L1 (7) γ{γ Γ { α} & c γ} 1,2,ST (8) Γ { α} v 6,7,UDP (9) Γ { v } α 8,L1 Corollary: $g{g G & c g} fi. G { [c/v]} fi G { " v } (1) γ{γ Γ & c γ} As (2) : Γ { [c/v]} Γ { v } CD (3) Γ { [c/v]} As (4) : Γ { v } DD (5) α[γ { [c/v]} α] 3,Def (6) Γ { [c/v]} P 5,QL (7) Γ { [c/v]} P 5,QL (8) c P inspection (9) c P inspection (10) Γ { v } P 6,8,NUEP (11) Γ { v } P 7,9,NUEP (12) Γ { v } 10,11,Lemma? Corollary: " v ¹ G & $g{g G & c g} & G.fi G { [c/v]} (1) v ¹ Γ As (2) γ{γ Γ & c γ} As (3) Γ As (4) : Γ { [c/v]} CD (5) Γ { [c/v]} As (6) : 3,9,SL (7) Γ { v } 2,5,cor1 (8) Γ = Γ { v } 1,ST (9) Γ 7,8,IL
19 18: Completeness Theorem 19 L2: G {a} b fi G { a} b (1) : Γ {α} β Γ { α} β CD (2) Γ {α} β As (3) : Γ { α} β DD (4) α α lemma (5) Γ α α 4,G? (6) Γ { α} α G? (7) Γ { α} α α G? (8) Γ { α} α 6,7,MPP (9) Γ { α} {α} β 2,G? (10) Γ { α} β 8,9,G? EEP: $g{g G & c g} & cˇa fi. G { [c/v]} a fi G {$v } a (1) γ{γ Γ & c γ} As (2) c α As (3) : Γ { [c/v]} α Γ { v } α CD (4) Γ { [c/v]} α As (5) : Γ { v } α DD (6) Γ { [c/v]} α 4,L2 (7) Γ { α} [c/v] 6,L1 (8) γ{γ Γ { α} & c γ} 1,2,ST (9) Γ { α} v 7,8,UDP (10) Γ { v } α 9,L1 (11) Γ { v } α 10, Def v
Completeness Theorem for System AS1
11 The Completeness Theorem for System AS1 1. Introduction...2 2. Previous Definitions...2 3. Deductive Consistency...2 4. Maximal Consistent Sets...5 5. Lindenbaum s Lemma...6 6. Every Maximal Consistent
Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set
Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set May 6, 2008 Abstract A set of first-order formulas, whatever the cardinality of the set of symbols, is equivalent to an independent
Lecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic
Lecture 2 Soundness and completeness of propositional logic February 9, 2004 1 Overview Review of natural deduction. Soundness and completeness. Semantics of propositional formulas. Soundness proof. Completeness
C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions
C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions Paul Liu November 15, 2007 Note that these are sample solutions only; in many cases there were many acceptable answers. 1 Reynolds Problem 10.1 1.1 Normal-order
2 Composition. Invertible Mappings
Arkansas Tech University MATH 4033: Elementary Modern Algebra Dr. Marcel B. Finan Composition. Invertible Mappings In this section we discuss two procedures for creating new mappings from old ones, namely,
Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit
Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit Ting Zhang Stanford May 11, 2001 Stanford, 5/11/2001 1 Outline Ordinal Classification Ordinal Addition Ordinal Multiplication Ordinal
Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs
Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs Who? Nichole Schimanski When? July 27, 2011 Graphs A graph, G, consists of a vertex set, V (G), and an edge set, E(G). V (G) is any finite set E(G) is
EE512: Error Control Coding
EE512: Error Control Coding Solution for Assignment on Finite Fields February 16, 2007 1. (a) Addition and Multiplication tables for GF (5) and GF (7) are shown in Tables 1 and 2. + 0 1 2 3 4 0 0 1 2 3
Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in
Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in : tail in X, head in A nowhere-zero Γ-flow is a Γ-circulation such that
derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates
derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates swapnizzle 03-03- :5:43 We begin by recognizing the familiar conversion from rectangular to spherical coordinates (note that φ is used
Homework 3 Solutions
Homework 3 Solutions Igor Yanovsky (Math 151A TA) Problem 1: Compute the absolute error and relative error in approximations of p by p. (Use calculator!) a) p π, p 22/7; b) p π, p 3.141. Solution: For
Example Sheet 3 Solutions
Example Sheet 3 Solutions. i Regular Sturm-Liouville. ii Singular Sturm-Liouville mixed boundary conditions. iii Not Sturm-Liouville ODE is not in Sturm-Liouville form. iv Regular Sturm-Liouville note
Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor
Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor Given f L 1 T 1 ), we consider the partial sums of the Fourier series of f: N 1) S N fθ) = ˆfk)e ikθ. k= N A calculation gives the Dirichlet formula
Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers
Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers There are two kinds of number.. Ordinal numbers (0th), st, 2nd, 3rd, 4th, 5th,..., ω, ω +,... ω2, ω2+,... ω 2... answers to the question What position is... in a sequence? What
4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1)
84 CHAPTER 4. STATIONARY TS MODELS 4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(,) This section is an introduction to a wide class of models ARMA(p,q) which we will consider in more detail later in this
Matrices and Determinants
Matrices and Determinants SUBJECTIVE PROBLEMS: Q 1. For what value of k do the following system of equations possess a non-trivial (i.e., not all zero) solution over the set of rationals Q? x + ky + 3z
About these lecture notes. Simply Typed λ-calculus. Types
About these lecture notes Simply Typed λ-calculus Akim Demaille akim@lrde.epita.fr EPITA École Pour l Informatique et les Techniques Avancées Many of these slides are largely inspired from Andrew D. Ker
Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests
Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests Side-Note: So far we have seen a few approaches for creating tests such as Neyman-Pearson Lemma ( most powerful tests of H 0 : θ = θ 0 vs H 1 :
Section 8.3 Trigonometric Equations
99 Section 8. Trigonometric Equations Objective 1: Solve Equations Involving One Trigonometric Function. In this section and the next, we will exple how to solving equations involving trigonometric functions.
Finite Field Problems: Solutions
Finite Field Problems: Solutions 1. Let f = x 2 +1 Z 11 [x] and let F = Z 11 [x]/(f), a field. Let Solution: F =11 2 = 121, so F = 121 1 = 120. The possible orders are the divisors of 120. Solution: The
ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER
ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER Abstract. We define ordinal arithmetic and show laws of Left- Monotonicity, Associativity, Distributivity, some minor related properties and the Cantor Normal Form.
Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval
Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential Equations Let a (t), a 2 (t),..., a nn (t), b (t), b 2 (t),..., b n (t) be continuous functions on the interval I. The system of n first-order differential equations
3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β
3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS Page Theorem cos(αβ cos α cos β -sin α cos(α-β cos α cos β sin α NOTE: cos(αβ cos α cos β cos(α-β cos α -cos β Proof of cos(α-β cos α cos β sin α Let s use a unit circle
ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II
ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II 2014/2015: Semester II Tutorial 7 1. Let X be a sample from a population P and consider testing hypotheses H 0 : P = P 0 versus H 1 : P = P 1, where P j is a known
ω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 ω ω + 1 ω + 2 ω + 3 ω + 4 ω2 ω2 + 1 ω2 + 2 ω2 + 3 ω3 ω3 + 1 ω3 + 2 ω4 ω4 + 1 ω5 ω 2 ω 2 + 1 ω 2 + 2 ω 2 + ω ω 2 + ω + 1 ω 2 + ω2 ω 2 2 ω 2 2 + 1 ω 2 2 + ω ω 2 3 ω 3 ω 3 + 1 ω 3 + ω ω 3 +
forms This gives Remark 1. How to remember the above formulas: Substituting these into the equation we obtain with
Week 03: C lassification of S econd- Order L inear Equations In last week s lectures we have illustrated how to obtain the general solutions of first order PDEs using the method of characteristics. We
Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests
Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests Shirsendu Mukherjee Department of Statistics, Asutosh College, Kolkata, India. shirsendu st@yahoo.co.in So far we have treated the testing of one-sided
Phys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required)
Phys460.nb 81 ψ n (t) is still the (same) eigenstate of H But for tdependent H. The answer is NO. 5.5.5. Solution for the tdependent Schrodinger s equation If we assume that at time t 0, the electron starts
Math221: HW# 1 solutions
Math: HW# solutions Andy Royston October, 5 7.5.7, 3 rd Ed. We have a n = b n = a = fxdx = xdx =, x cos nxdx = x sin nx n sin nxdx n = cos nx n = n n, x sin nxdx = x cos nx n + cos nxdx n cos n = + sin
CHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS
CHAPTER 5 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS EXERCISE 104 Page 8 1. Find the positive root of the equation x + 3x 5 = 0, correct to 3 significant figures, using the method of bisection. Let f(x) =
Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude
Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude Jan Behrens 2012-12-31 In this paper we shall provide a method to approximate distances between two points on earth
HOMEWORK 4 = G. In order to plot the stress versus the stretch we define a normalized stretch:
HOMEWORK 4 Problem a For the fast loading case, we want to derive the relationship between P zz and λ z. We know that the nominal stress is expressed as: P zz = ψ λ z where λ z = λ λ z. Therefore, applying
CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS
CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS Shiah-Sen Wang The graphs are prepared by Chien-Lun Lai Based on : Precalculus: Mathematics for Calculus by J. Stuwart, L. Redin & S. Watson, 6th edition, 01, Brooks/Cole Chapter
The Simply Typed Lambda Calculus
Type Inference Instead of writing type annotations, can we use an algorithm to infer what the type annotations should be? That depends on the type system. For simple type systems the answer is yes, and
Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016
Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016 Silvio Capobianco Exercise 1.7 Let H(n) = J(n + 1) J(n). Equation (1.8) tells us that H(2n) = 2, and H(2n+1) = J(2n+2) J(2n+1) = (2J(n+1) 1) (2J(n)+1)
Math 6 SL Probability Distributions Practice Test Mark Scheme
Math 6 SL Probability Distributions Practice Test Mark Scheme. (a) Note: Award A for vertical line to right of mean, A for shading to right of their vertical line. AA N (b) evidence of recognizing symmetry
Fourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics
Fourier Series MATH 211, Calculus II J. Robert Buchanan Department of Mathematics Spring 2018 Introduction Not all functions can be represented by Taylor series. f (k) (c) A Taylor series f (x) = (x c)
Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5. Luca Alberucci, University of Berne. Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008
Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5 Luca Alberucci, University of Berne Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008 Introduction Koz: Axiomatisation for the modal µ-calculus over K Axioms: All classical
Reminders: linear functions
Reminders: linear functions Let U and V be vector spaces over the same field F. Definition A function f : U V is linear if for every u 1, u 2 U, f (u 1 + u 2 ) = f (u 1 ) + f (u 2 ), and for every u U
2. Let H 1 and H 2 be Hilbert spaces and let T : H 1 H 2 be a bounded linear operator. Prove that [T (H 1 )] = N (T ). (6p)
Uppsala Universitet Matematiska Institutionen Andreas Strömbergsson Prov i matematik Funktionalanalys Kurs: F3B, F4Sy, NVP 2005-03-08 Skrivtid: 9 14 Tillåtna hjälpmedel: Manuella skrivdon, Kreyszigs bok
ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 19/5/2007
Οδηγίες: Να απαντηθούν όλες οι ερωτήσεις. Αν κάπου κάνετε κάποιες υποθέσεις να αναφερθούν στη σχετική ερώτηση. Όλα τα αρχεία που αναφέρονται στα προβλήματα βρίσκονται στον ίδιο φάκελο με το εκτελέσιμο
Abstract Storage Devices
Abstract Storage Devices Robert König Ueli Maurer Stefano Tessaro SOFSEM 2009 January 27, 2009 Outline 1. Motivation: Storage Devices 2. Abstract Storage Devices (ASD s) 3. Reducibility 4. Factoring ASD
Solutions to Exercise Sheet 5
Solutions to Eercise Sheet 5 jacques@ucsd.edu. Let X and Y be random variables with joint pdf f(, y) = 3y( + y) where and y. Determine each of the following probabilities. Solutions. a. P (X ). b. P (X
Notes on the Open Economy
Notes on the Open Econom Ben J. Heijdra Universit of Groningen April 24 Introduction In this note we stud the two-countr model of Table.4 in more detail. restated here for convenience. The model is Table.4.
The challenges of non-stable predicates
The challenges of non-stable predicates Consider a non-stable predicate Φ encoding, say, a safety property. We want to determine whether Φ holds for our program. The challenges of non-stable predicates
Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees
Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees Thomas F. Kent Andrea Sorbi Università degli Studi di Siena Italia July 18, 2007 Goal: Introduce a form of Σ 0 2-permitting for the enumeration degrees. Till now,
MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS
MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS FUMIE NAKAOKA AND NOBUYUKI ODA Received 20 December 2005; Revised 28 May 2006; Accepted 6 August 2006 Some properties of minimal closed sets and maximal closed
6.1. Dirac Equation. Hamiltonian. Dirac Eq.
6.1. Dirac Equation Ref: M.Kaku, Quantum Field Theory, Oxford Univ Press (1993) η μν = η μν = diag(1, -1, -1, -1) p 0 = p 0 p = p i = -p i p μ p μ = p 0 p 0 + p i p i = E c 2 - p 2 = (m c) 2 H = c p 2
SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES G11LMA Linear Mathematics Examination Solutions
SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES GLMA Linear Mathematics 00- Examination Solutions. (a) i. ( + 5i)( i) = (6 + 5) + (5 )i = + i. Real part is, imaginary part is. (b) ii. + 5i i ( + 5i)( + i) = ( i)( + i)
Homomorphism in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Automata
International Journal of Fuzzy Mathematics Systems. ISSN 2248-9940 Volume 3, Number 1 (2013), pp. 39-45 Research India Publications http://www.ripublication.com/ijfms.htm Homomorphism in Intuitionistic
Second Order Partial Differential Equations
Chapter 7 Second Order Partial Differential Equations 7.1 Introduction A second order linear PDE in two independent variables (x, y Ω can be written as A(x, y u x + B(x, y u xy + C(x, y u u u + D(x, y
Econ 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1
Eon : Fall 8 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 Email questions or omments to Dan Fetter Problem. Let X be a salar with density f(x, θ) (θx + θ) [ x ] with θ. (a) Find the most powerful level α test
λρ-calculus 1. each λ-variable is a λρ-term, called an atom or atomic term; 2. if M and N are λρ-term then (MN) is a λρ-term called an application;
λρ-calculus Yuichi Komori komori@math.s.chiba-u.ac.jp Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Sciences, Chiba University Arato Cho aratoc@g.math.s.chiba-u.ac.jp Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Sciences,
Partial Differential Equations in Biology The boundary element method. March 26, 2013
The boundary element method March 26, 203 Introduction and notation The problem: u = f in D R d u = ϕ in Γ D u n = g on Γ N, where D = Γ D Γ N, Γ D Γ N = (possibly, Γ D = [Neumann problem] or Γ N = [Dirichlet
Srednicki Chapter 55
Srednicki Chapter 55 QFT Problems & Solutions A. George August 3, 03 Srednicki 55.. Use equations 55.3-55.0 and A i, A j ] = Π i, Π j ] = 0 (at equal times) to verify equations 55.-55.3. This is our third
Απόκριση σε Μοναδιαία Ωστική Δύναμη (Unit Impulse) Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο. Απόστολος Σ.
Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο The time integral of a force is referred to as impulse, is determined by and is obtained from: Newton s 2 nd Law of motion states that the action
ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC = DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION #2. h 0 h h 0 h h 0 ( ) g k = g 0 + g 1 + g g 2009 =?
Teko Classes IITJEE/AIEEE Maths by SUHAAG SIR, Bhopal, Ph (0755) 3 00 000 www.tekoclasses.com ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION # Question Type A.Single Correct Type Q. (A) Sol least
Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3
Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3 1 State vector space and the dual space Space of wavefunctions The space of wavefunctions is the set of all
Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II
Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II October 18, 2012 1 Review First let us recall the situation. Let g be a simple algebra, with maximal toral subalgebra h (which we are calling a CSA, or Cartan Subalgebra).
Problem Set 3: Solutions
CMPSCI 69GG Applied Information Theory Fall 006 Problem Set 3: Solutions. [Cover and Thomas 7.] a Define the following notation, C I p xx; Y max X; Y C I p xx; Ỹ max I X; Ỹ We would like to show that C
CHAPTER 48 APPLICATIONS OF MATRICES AND DETERMINANTS
CHAPTER 48 APPLICATIONS OF MATRICES AND DETERMINANTS EXERCISE 01 Page 545 1. Use matrices to solve: 3x + 4y x + 5y + 7 3x + 4y x + 5y 7 Hence, 3 4 x 0 5 y 7 The inverse of 3 4 5 is: 1 5 4 1 5 4 15 8 3
Overview. Transition Semantics. Configurations and the transition relation. Executions and computation
Overview Transition Semantics Configurations and the transition relation Executions and computation Inference rules for small-step structural operational semantics for the simple imperative language Transition
Section 7.6 Double and Half Angle Formulas
09 Section 7. Double and Half Angle Fmulas To derive the double-angles fmulas, we will use the sum of two angles fmulas that we developed in the last section. We will let α θ and β θ: cos(θ) cos(θ + θ)
de Rham Theorem May 10, 2016
de Rham Theorem May 10, 2016 Stokes formula and the integration morphism: Let M = σ Σ σ be a smooth triangulated manifold. Fact: Stokes formula σ ω = σ dω holds, e.g. for simplices. It can be used to define
Section 9.2 Polar Equations and Graphs
180 Section 9. Polar Equations and Graphs In this section, we will be graphing polar equations on a polar grid. In the first few examples, we will write the polar equation in rectangular form to help identify
5. Choice under Uncertainty
5. Choice under Uncertainty Daisuke Oyama Microeconomics I May 23, 2018 Formulations von Neumann-Morgenstern (1944/1947) X: Set of prizes Π: Set of probability distributions on X : Preference relation
A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation
International Mathematical Forum, 5, 2010, no. 67, 3301-3307 A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy Equivalence Relation D. K. Basnet Dept. of Mathematics, Assam University Silchar-788011, Assam, India dkbasnet@rediffmail.com
Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics
Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics Nov 1, 01 In this lecture we examine root systems from an axiomatic point of view. 1 Reflections If v R n, then it determines a hyperplane, denoted P v, through the
( y) Partial Differential Equations
Partial Dierential Equations Linear P.D.Es. contains no owers roducts o the deendent variables / an o its derivatives can occasionall be solved. Consider eamle ( ) a (sometimes written as a ) we can integrate
6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes
122 CHAPTER 6. ARMA MODELS 6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes The purpose of forecasting is to predict future values of a TS based on the data collected to the present. In this section we will discuss a linear
Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval
Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential Equations Let a (t), a 2 (t),..., a nn (t), b (t), b 2 (t),..., b n (t) be continuous functions on the interval I. The system of n first-order differential equations
Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets
Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets S K Mala #1, Dr. MM Shanmugapriya *2 1 PhD Scholar in Mathematics, Karpagam University, Coimbatore, Tamilnadu- 641021 Assistant Professor of Mathematics,
Simulation of G i with prenex cuts
Simulation of G i with prenex cuts Emil Jeřábek Phuong Nguyen November 25, 2010 Abstract We show that the quantified propositional proof systems G i are polynomially equivalent to their restricted versions
Solution Series 9. i=1 x i and i=1 x i.
Lecturer: Prof. Dr. Mete SONER Coordinator: Yilin WANG Solution Series 9 Q1. Let α, β >, the p.d.f. of a beta distribution with parameters α and β is { Γ(α+β) Γ(α)Γ(β) f(x α, β) xα 1 (1 x) β 1 for < x
SCITECH Volume 13, Issue 2 RESEARCH ORGANISATION Published online: March 29, 2018
Journal of rogressive Research in Mathematics(JRM) ISSN: 2395-028 SCITECH Volume 3, Issue 2 RESEARCH ORGANISATION ublished online: March 29, 208 Journal of rogressive Research in Mathematics www.scitecresearch.com/journals
New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines
New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines Michigan State University Oct 8-31, 016 Anhui University Definition If X = {x 1, x,, x N } S n 1 (unit sphere in R n ) and x i, x j = a
k A = [k, k]( )[a 1, a 2 ] = [ka 1,ka 2 ] 4For the division of two intervals of confidence in R +
Chapter 3. Fuzzy Arithmetic 3- Fuzzy arithmetic: ~Addition(+) and subtraction (-): Let A = [a and B = [b, b in R If x [a and y [b, b than x+y [a +b +b Symbolically,we write A(+)B = [a (+)[b, b = [a +b
SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM
SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM Solutions to Question 1 a) The cumulative distribution function of T conditional on N n is Pr T t N n) Pr max X 1,..., X N ) t N n) Pr max
Tridiagonal matrices. Gérard MEURANT. October, 2008
Tridiagonal matrices Gérard MEURANT October, 2008 1 Similarity 2 Cholesy factorizations 3 Eigenvalues 4 Inverse Similarity Let α 1 ω 1 β 1 α 2 ω 2 T =......... β 2 α 1 ω 1 β 1 α and β i ω i, i = 1,...,
On the Galois Group of Linear Difference-Differential Equations
On the Galois Group of Linear Difference-Differential Equations Ruyong Feng KLMM, Chinese Academy of Sciences, China Ruyong Feng (KLMM, CAS) Galois Group 1 / 19 Contents 1 Basic Notations and Concepts
TMA4115 Matematikk 3
TMA4115 Matematikk 3 Andrew Stacey Norges Teknisk-Naturvitenskapelige Universitet Trondheim Spring 2010 Lecture 12: Mathematics Marvellous Matrices Andrew Stacey Norges Teknisk-Naturvitenskapelige Universitet
LTL to Buchi. Overview. Buchi Model Checking LTL Translating LTL into Buchi. Ralf Huuck. Buchi Automata. Example
Overview LTL to Buchi Buchi Model Checking LTL Translating LTL into Buchi Ralf Huuck Buchi Automata Example Automaton which accepts infinite traces δ A Buchi automaton is 5-tuple Σ, Q, Q 0,δ, F Σ is a
SOLVING CUBICS AND QUARTICS BY RADICALS
SOLVING CUBICS AND QUARTICS BY RADICALS The purpose of this handout is to record the classical formulas expressing the roots of degree three and degree four polynomials in terms of radicals. We begin with
Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates
Kiryl Tsishchanka Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates In this section we develop the formula for the area of a region whose boundary is given by a polar equation. We need to use the formula for the
Finitary proof systems for Kozen s µ
Finitary proof systems for Kozen s µ Bahareh Afshari Graham Leigh TU Wien University of Gothenburg homc & cdps 16, Singapore 1 / 17 Modal µ-calculus Syntax: p p φ ψ φ ψ φ φ x µx φ νx φ Semantics: For Kripke
w o = R 1 p. (1) R = p =. = 1
Πανεπιστήµιο Κρήτης - Τµήµα Επιστήµης Υπολογιστών ΗΥ-570: Στατιστική Επεξεργασία Σήµατος 205 ιδάσκων : Α. Μουχτάρης Τριτη Σειρά Ασκήσεων Λύσεις Ασκηση 3. 5.2 (a) From the Wiener-Hopf equation we have:
On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions.
On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions. Moti Gitik December 31, 2015 Abstract Every set of ordinals of cardinality κ in a Prikry extension with a measure over κ contains an old set of arbitrary
DESIGN OF MACHINERY SOLUTION MANUAL h in h 4 0.
DESIGN OF MACHINERY SOLUTION MANUAL -7-1! PROBLEM -7 Statement: Design a double-dwell cam to move a follower from to 25 6, dwell for 12, fall 25 and dwell for the remader The total cycle must take 4 sec
DIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANSFORMATION SEMIGROUPS
GANIT J. Bangladesh Math. oc. IN 606-694) 0) -7 DIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANFORMATION EMIGROUP ubrata Majumdar, * Kalyan Kumar Dey and Mohd. Altab Hossain Department of Mathematics University
Practice Exam 2. Conceptual Questions. 1. State a Basic identity and then verify it. (a) Identity: Solution: One identity is csc(θ) = 1
Conceptual Questions. State a Basic identity and then verify it. a) Identity: Solution: One identity is cscθ) = sinθ) Practice Exam b) Verification: Solution: Given the point of intersection x, y) of the
CHAPTER 101 FOURIER SERIES FOR PERIODIC FUNCTIONS OF PERIOD
CHAPTER FOURIER SERIES FOR PERIODIC FUNCTIONS OF PERIOD EXERCISE 36 Page 66. Determine the Fourier series for the periodic function: f(x), when x +, when x which is periodic outside this rge of period.
Solutions for exercises in chapter 1 = 2, 3, 1, 4 ; = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2 1 S 1 1 S 0 = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2, 1, 4,1,3. 1, 1,..., 1, S 0
E1.1 Verify that and Solutions for exercises in chapter 1 S 0 S 1 = 2, 3, 1, 4 (S 0 S 1 ) ( S 1 S 0 ) = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2, 1, 4, 1,3. S 0 S 1 = 2 S 0 S 1 = 2 3 1 S 1 = 2, 3, 1, 4 ; (S 0 S 1 ) ( S 1 S 0 ) =
Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations. ------------------ ----------------------------- -----------------
Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations. 1. Sin ( ) = a) b) c) d) Ans b. Solution : Method 1. Ans a: 17 > 1 a) is rejected. w.k.t Sin ( sin ) = d is rejected. If sin
SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS
Sahand Communications in Mathematical Analysis (SCMA) Vol. 3 No. 1 (2016), 21-27 http://scma.maragheh.ac.ir SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS BAYAZ DARABY 1 AND JAVAD JAFARI 2 Abstract. In the mathematical
Arithmetical applications of lagrangian interpolation. Tanguy Rivoal. Institut Fourier CNRS and Université de Grenoble 1
Arithmetical applications of lagrangian interpolation Tanguy Rivoal Institut Fourier CNRS and Université de Grenoble Conference Diophantine and Analytic Problems in Number Theory, The 00th anniversary
Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates
Kiryl Tsishchanka Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates In this section we develop the formula for the area of a region whose boundary is given by a polar equation. We need to use the formula for the
Some new generalized topologies via hereditary classes. Key Words:hereditary generalized topological space, A κ(h,µ)-sets, κµ -topology.
Bol. Soc. Paran. Mat. (3s.) v. 30 2 (2012): 71 77. c SPM ISSN-2175-1188 on line ISSN-00378712 in press SPM: www.spm.uem.br/bspm doi:10.5269/bspm.v30i2.13793 Some new generalized topologies via hereditary
Chapter 2. Ordinals, well-founded relations.
Chapter 2. Ordinals, well-founded relations. 2.1. Well-founded Relations. We start with some definitions and rapidly reach the notion of a well-ordered set. Definition. For any X and any binary relation
Jesse Maassen and Mark Lundstrom Purdue University November 25, 2013
Notes on Average Scattering imes and Hall Factors Jesse Maassen and Mar Lundstrom Purdue University November 5, 13 I. Introduction 1 II. Solution of the BE 1 III. Exercises: Woring out average scattering
Main source: "Discrete-time systems and computer control" by Α. ΣΚΟΔΡΑΣ ΨΗΦΙΑΚΟΣ ΕΛΕΓΧΟΣ ΔΙΑΛΕΞΗ 4 ΔΙΑΦΑΝΕΙΑ 1
Main source: "Discrete-time systems and computer control" by Α. ΣΚΟΔΡΑΣ ΨΗΦΙΑΚΟΣ ΕΛΕΓΧΟΣ ΔΙΑΛΕΞΗ 4 ΔΙΑΦΑΝΕΙΑ 1 A Brief History of Sampling Research 1915 - Edmund Taylor Whittaker (1873-1956) devised a