ON SQUARE-INTEGRABLE REPRESENTATIONS OF CLASSICAL p-adic GROUPS II

Σχετικά έγγραφα
Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set

2 Composition. Invertible Mappings

EE512: Error Control Coding

C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions

Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit

ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER

Homework 3 Solutions

Lecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic

Example Sheet 3 Solutions

Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016

ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II

ON JACQUET MODULES OF REPRESENTATIONS OF SEGMENT TYPE

4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1)

CHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS

Finite Field Problems: Solutions

Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in

Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2

derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates

Section 8.3 Trigonometric Equations

Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor

SCITECH Volume 13, Issue 2 RESEARCH ORGANISATION Published online: March 29, 2018

3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β

Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs

Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3

Problem Set 3: Solutions

Phys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required)

SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES G11LMA Linear Mathematics Examination Solutions

On Square-Integrable Representations of Classical p-adic Groups

Math221: HW# 1 solutions

forms This gives Remark 1. How to remember the above formulas: Substituting these into the equation we obtain with

HOMEWORK 4 = G. In order to plot the stress versus the stretch we define a normalized stretch:

MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS

6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

Second Order Partial Differential Equations

A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation

SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS

Matrices and Determinants

Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II

6.1. Dirac Equation. Hamiltonian. Dirac Eq.

Pacific Journal of Mathematics

Solutions to Exercise Sheet 5

On a four-dimensional hyperbolic manifold with finite volume

Srednicki Chapter 55

Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests

Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude

Απόκριση σε Μοναδιαία Ωστική Δύναμη (Unit Impulse) Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο. Απόστολος Σ.

Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees

Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics

Econ 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1

Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests

Partial Differential Equations in Biology The boundary element method. March 26, 2013

The Simply Typed Lambda Calculus

Jesse Maassen and Mark Lundstrom Purdue University November 25, 2013

9.09. # 1. Area inside the oval limaçon r = cos θ. To graph, start with θ = 0 so r = 6. Compute dr

Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations

Tridiagonal matrices. Gérard MEURANT. October, 2008

Tempered representations for classical p-adic groups

2. Let H 1 and H 2 be Hilbert spaces and let T : H 1 H 2 be a bounded linear operator. Prove that [T (H 1 )] = N (T ). (6p)

Συστήματα Διαχείρισης Βάσεων Δεδομένων

ω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω

Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequality for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x, y, z X.

TMA4115 Matematikk 3

CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS

Section 9.2 Polar Equations and Graphs

( y) Partial Differential Equations

ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC = DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION #2. h 0 h h 0 h h 0 ( ) g k = g 0 + g 1 + g g 2009 =?

Homomorphism in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Automata

Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers

Exercises 10. Find a fundamental matrix of the given system of equations. Also find the fundamental matrix Φ(t) satisfying Φ(0) = I. 1.

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

SOLVING CUBICS AND QUARTICS BY RADICALS

PARTIAL NOTES for 6.1 Trigonometric Identities

Section 7.6 Double and Half Angle Formulas

Main source: "Discrete-time systems and computer control" by Α. ΣΚΟΔΡΑΣ ΨΗΦΙΑΚΟΣ ΕΛΕΓΧΟΣ ΔΙΑΛΕΞΗ 4 ΔΙΑΦΑΝΕΙΑ 1

Coefficient Inequalities for a New Subclass of K-uniformly Convex Functions

New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines

Solution Series 9. i=1 x i and i=1 x i.

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 19/5/2007

Μηχανική Μάθηση Hypothesis Testing

1. Introduction and Preliminaries.

Reminders: linear functions

ΕΛΛΗΝΙΚΗ ΔΗΜΟΚΡΑΤΙΑ ΠΑΝΕΠΙΣΤΗΜΙΟ ΚΡΗΤΗΣ. Ψηφιακή Οικονομία. Διάλεξη 7η: Consumer Behavior Mαρίνα Μπιτσάκη Τμήμα Επιστήμης Υπολογιστών

= λ 1 1 e. = λ 1 =12. has the properties e 1. e 3,V(Y

The challenges of non-stable predicates

Space-Time Symmetries

Intuitionistic Fuzzy Ideals of Near Rings

Strain gauge and rosettes

LECTURE 2 CONTEXT FREE GRAMMARS CONTENTS

Homomorphism of Intuitionistic Fuzzy Groups

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 6/5/2006

Second Order RLC Filters

Abstract Storage Devices

Quadratic Expressions

5. Choice under Uncertainty

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

k A = [k, k]( )[a 1, a 2 ] = [ka 1,ka 2 ] 4For the division of two intervals of confidence in R +

Fourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics

Lecture 21: Properties and robustness of LSE

Transcript:

REPRESENTATION THEORY An Electronic Journal of the American Mathematical Society Volume 4, Pages 127 180 (February 23, 2000) S 1088-4165(00)00081-9 ON SQUARE-INTEGRABLE REPRESENTATIONS OF CLASSICAL p-adic GROUPS II CHRIS JANTZEN Abstract. In this paper, we continue our study of non-supercuspidal discrete series for the classical groups Sp(2n, F ), SO(2n + 1,F), where F is p-adic. 1. Introduction This paper is a continuation of [Jan4]. Suppose ρ is an irreducible, unitary supercuspidal representation of GL n (F )and σ an irreducible, supercuspidal representation of S r (F )=Sp 2r (F )orso 2r+1 (F ). Then, if ρ = ρ (self-contragredient), we have Ind( detn x ρ σ) is irreducible for all x R. Otherwise, there is a unique α 0 such that Ind( det n x ρ σ) is reducible for x = ±α and irreducible for all x R \{±α} (cf. [Sil2], [Tad5]). Assuming certain conjectures, Mœglin [Mœ2] and Zhang [Zh] have shown that α 1 2 Z (also, cf. [M-R], [Re], [Sha1], [Sha2]). In [Jan4], we showed that the problem of classifying non-supercuspidal discrete series could be reduced to classifying discrete series with supercuspidal support in S((ρ, α); σ) ={ν x ρ, ν x ρ} x α+z {σ} (though most of this result is from [Jan2] and [Tad4]). In [Jan4], to an irreducible representation π supported on S((ρ, α); σ), we associated an element χ 0 (π) in the minimal Jacquet module for π (minimal meaning with respect to the smallest parabolic subgroup admitting a nonzero Jacquet module for π). We note that there is an order on the components of the (semisimplified) minimal Jacquet module of π such that χ 0 (π) is minimal with respect to. From χ 0 (π), we can read off a representation δ 0 (π) havingtheform δ 0 (π) =δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ, where δ([ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ]) denotes the generalized Steinberg (for a general linear group) which has ν ai ρ ν ai 1 ρ ν bi ρ as its (minimal) Jacquet module. We have π Ind(δ 0 (π)). Further, one can determine whether π is square-integrable just from δ 0 (π). Our goal is then to constrain the candidates for δ 0 for square-integrable representations, thereby constraining where one needs to look for square-integrable representations. Of course, the ultimate goal is exhaustion: if the constraints are strong enough, every possible δ 0 listed will actually occur as δ 0 (π) for some discrete series π. That is the case for the theorem below when ρ =1 F, σ =1 S0(F ) (cf. [Mœ1]); we expect it holds in general. Received by the editors July 28, 1999 and, in revised form, October 18, 1999. 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary 22E50. 127 c 2000 American Mathematical Society

128 CHRIS JANTZEN In a sense, our point-of-view may be regarded as an extension of that of [B-Z] and [Zel]. Their descriptions of representations of general linear groups are given in combinatorial terms, with the combinatorial descriptions essentially independent of which particular supercuspidal representations appear in the support. Here, we work with discrete series for symplectic and odd-orthogonal groups in an analogous setting; while our results are not independent of the ρ, σ which appear, they depend on ρ, σ only insofar as ρ, σ determine α. (Roughly speaking, α = 1 for the GL counterpart, so this issue does not arise.) Thus, from our point-of-view, α is essentially treated as input data, with discrete series characterizations as the output. The main result in this paper is the following: Theorem 1.1. Suppose ρ is an irreducible, unitary, supercuspidal representation of GL n (F ) and σ an irreducible, supercuspidal representation of S r (F ). Also, suppose Ind( det n x ρ σ) is reducible for x = ±α and irreducible for x R \{±α}, where α 0 has α 1 2Z.Ifπis an irreducible, square-integrable representation supported on S((ρ, α); σ) with δ 0 (π) =δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ, the following conditions must be satisfied: 1. basic conditions: (a) a k a k 1 a 1 > 0. (b) a i >b i for all i. (c) There is a β with α +1 β>0 such that each of { β, β 1,..., α} appears exactly once among b 1,b 2,...,b k and there are no other negative b i s. 2. a i β for all i; b i β 1 for all b i 0. 3. a 1,a 2,...,a k,b 1,b 2,...,b k are all distinct. 4. We do not have a i >a j >b i >b j for any i>j. Remarks 1.2. 1. Coupled with Theorem 3.2.1 of [Jan4], Theorem 1.1 above applies to any irreducible, square-integrable representation if we assume the half-integrality hypothesis in Theorem 1.1 holds in general. That is, for any such (ρ, σ), the value of x R, x 0 which makes Ind( det x ρ σ) reducible (if any) lies in 1 2Z. (The half-integrality hypothesis follows from [Mœ2] or [Zh] if certain conjectures are assumed.) 2. We make two remarks concerning converse directions. (a) If π is an irreducible representation and δ 0 (π) =δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ has a 1,...,a k,b 1,...,b k satisfying 1 4 of Theorem 1.1, then π is square-integrable. (In fact, condition 1 of Theorem 1.1 is sufficient; cf. Theorem 4.2.1, [Jan4].) (b) If a 1,...,a k,b 1,...,b k satisfy 1 4 of Theorem 1.1, one can ask whether there exists an irreducible representation π having δ 0 (π)=δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ. We expect that this is the case, but it is not proved. (Note that in the case where a k > >a 1 >b 1 > >b k, such a π is constructed in section 7; in the case where a k >b k >a k 1 > b k 1 > >a 1 >b 1, the existence of such a π follows from the results in [Tad5].) 3. We note that we can have irreducible, square-integrable representations π 1,π 2 which have π 1 = π2 but δ 0 (π 1 )=δ 0 (π 2 ) (cf. Theorem 7.7; examples may also be easily obtained from [Tad5]).

SQUARE-INTEGRABLE REPRESENTATIONS OF CLASSICAL p-adic GROUPS II 129 The basic proof is by induction on the parabolic rank (cf. 0.3.4 [B-W]) of the supercuspidal support; the whole paper is essentially one large inductive proof. Thus, we establish Theorem 1.1 and complementary results (Theorem 7.7 and Corollaries 7.8 and 7.9) for a fixed parabolic rank p.r. assuming they all hold when the parabolic rank of the supercuspidal support is less than p.r. We note that if δ 0 (π) =δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ, then the supercuspidal support of π has parabolic rank (a 1 + b 1 +1)+ +(a k + b k + 1). To avoid repeating the hypotheses of Theorem 1.1 in the rest of the theorems in this paper, let us simply let (H) denote the hypotheses of Theorem 1.1. We now discuss the contents section by section. The next section reviews notation and some background results. We also record Theorem 2.4, which says that the first condition in Theorem 1.1 holds (it is a combination of results from [Jan4]). In the third section, we verify condition 2 of the theorem. The basic idea in proving this is to show that should condition 2 fail, there must be something in the Jacquet module of π lower than the χ 0 (π) we started with, a contradiction. For the most part, this can be done with a simple string of embeddings and equivalences; there is one subtler case which occupies most of this section. The fourth and fifth sections verify that conditions 3 and 4 hold. Conditions 3 and 4 are essentially conditions on pairs of segments, and are treated as such. In the fourth section, we assume that b i >a i 1 for some i. Roughly speaking, such segments can be removed from consideration. What remains then has lower parabolic rank and the inductive hypothesis allows us to finish this case. The fifth section deals with the case where b i a i 1 for all i. Here we need to show conditions 3 and 4 directly. The basic idea is to show that if 3 or 4 fails, then π may be embedded into an induced representation where the inducing representation is lower than δ 0 (π), a contradiction. To do this, we use Jacquet module arguments to compare certain induced representations. We note that in the case where σ is generic, condition 3 may be deduced from [Mu]. In order to do the comparisons for section 5, we need to know the existence of square-integrable representations with certain properties. The last two sections are geared toward this. In the sixth section, we prove a technical result which is needed in the seventh section. In the seventh section, we show the existence of square-integrable representations with certain specific δ 0 s, in particular, δ 0 having b i <a i 1 for all i. This is done by analyzing the induced representation δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ],...,[ν b k, where δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ],...,[ν b k is a square-integrable representation (by the inductive hypothesis, already constructed) which has δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ as its δ 0. 2. Notation and preliminaries We retain the notation introduced in section 1.2, [Jan4] and will forgo reviewing it here. We will also forgo reviewing certain standard results already discussed in [Jan4]. The Langlands classification and Casselman criteria for S r (F ) ([B-W], [Sil1], [Cas] and [Tad1]) are discussed in section 3.1, [Jan4]. The Langlands classification for GL n (F ) is discussed in section 2.4, [Jan4]. For clarity, we use L (resp. L) when the Langlands subrepresentation is for a general linear group (resp., classical group). We briefly review some of the notation and results from the remainder of [Jan4], and we introduce a few additional items needed for this paper.

130 CHRIS JANTZEN Let ρ be an irreducible unitary supercuspidal representation of GL n (F ), σ an irreducible supercuspidal representation of S r (F ). Also, suppose ν x ρ σ is reducible for x = ±α and irreducible for x R \{±α}, whereα 0hasα 1 2 Z. Definition 2.1. Let π be an irreducible representation supported on S((ρ, α); σ). Set { X(π) = χ s min (π) χ = ν x1 ρ ν xm ρ σ has x 1 + + x m minimal for s min (π) Then, let χ 0 (π) X(π), which is minimal in the lexicographic ordering. The following is Lemma 4.1.2, [Jan4] with a minor change of notation. (As in section 5, [Jan4], it is more convenient to incorporate a negative into the b i s.) Lemma 2.2. χ 0 (π) has the form χ 0 (π) =(ν a1 ρ ν a1 1 ρ ν b1 ρ) (ν a k ρ ν ak 1 ρ ν b k ρ) σ, with a 1 a 2 a k. Definition 2.3. With notation as above, if χ 0 (π) =(ν a1 ρ ν a1 1 ρ ν b1 ρ) (ν a k ρ ν ak 1 ρ ν b k ρ) σ, set δ 0 (π) =δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ. We also recall that if χ 0 (π),δ 0 (π) as above, M = GL (a1 b 1+1)n(F ) GL (ak b k +1)n(F ) S r (F ), then π i GM (δ 0 (π)) (cf. Lemma 4.1.4, [Jan4]). We also note the following, a consequence of Theorem 4.2.1 of [Jan4], Lemma 4.4.1 of [Jan4], and Lemma 4.4.2 of [Jan4]. Theorem 2.4. Suppose (H). Then, condition 1 in Theorem 1.1 holds. We now introduce a bit of notation which will be used in the rest of this paper. In Definition 2.1 above, let t.e.(χ 0 (π)) denote the minimal value of x 1 + +x m which arises. More generally, we let t.e.(π) =t.e.(δ 0 (π)) denote the same value. Implicit in Definition 2.1 is an ordering: χ 1 χ 2 if t.e.(χ 1 ) >t.e.(χ 2 )ort.e.(χ 1 )=t.e.(χ 2 ) and χ 1 is lexicographically higher than χ 2. We extend this ordering as follows: π 1 π 2 if χ 0 (π 1 ) χ 0 (π 2 ). (Typically, π 1 and π 2 will be representations of Levi factors of standard parabolic subgroups.) We introduce one other piece of notation. At times, it will be convenient to write s app when the Jacquet module of S m is taken with respect to the appropriate standard parabolic subgroup. This will only be used when what constitutes the appropriate parabolic subgroup is clear from context. We now recall Definition 5.2.1 of [Jan4]. It uses the Jacquet module structures developed in [Tad2]. Since a summary of the notation and results needed from [Tad2] was given in section 3.1 of [Jan4], we will forgo a discussion here. Definition 2.5. Suppose τ is an irreducible representation of GL m (F )andπ a representation of S n (F ). Write µ (π) = i m i ξ i θ i, }.

SQUARE-INTEGRABLE REPRESENTATIONS OF CLASSICAL p-adic GROUPS II 131 where ξ i θ i is irreducible and m i is its multiplicity. Let I τ = {i ξ i = τ}. Weset µ τ (π) = i I τ m i ξ i θ i = i I τ m i τ θ i. Similarly, if ξ is a representation of GL r (F )and let J τ = {j ξ (1) j M (ξ) = j n j ξ (1) j ξ (2) j, = τ}. Weset Mτ (ξ) = n j ξ (1) j ξ (2) j = n j τ ξ (2) j J τ j J τ It will be convenient to extend this definition to the case where τ = τ 1 τ j. In this case, we write s τ1 τ j rather than µ τ 1 τ j (since s τ1 τ j s app not µ ). We close with a lemma which will expedite certain calculations. Lemma 2.6. 1. Suppose η δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b k. Assume τ is an irreducible representation of a general linear group such that {ν b1 ρ,...,ν b k ρ, ν a1 ρ,...,ν a k ρ} supp(τ) =. Then for any representation ξ of a general linear group, we have µ τ (ξ η) =M τ (ξ) (1 η). 2. Suppose {x Mν ρ(ξ) 0} support(τ) =. Then, x µ τ (ξ η) =(1 ξ) µ τ (η). Further, we note that Mν ρ(τ) 0if and only if the following holds: either x r min (τ) contains a term of the form ν x ρ... or r min (τ) contains a term of the form ν x ρ. Proof. Write M (ξ) = i τ (1) i τ (2) i and µ (η) = j τ j θ j. Then, µ (ξ η) = τ (1) i τ j τ (2) i θ j. i,j Observe that if τ j 1, we must have r min (τ j ) = h να h ρ... with α h {b 1,...,b k,a 1,...,a k } for all h. But, for τ j to contribute to µ τ,wemusthave ν α h ρ supp(τ). Since this is not the case, we must have τ j = 1. Part 1 of the lemma follows. The proof of 2 is straightforward and essentially the same as that of Lemma 5.2.2, [Jan4]; we omit it. 3. Condition 2 The main result in this section is Theorem 3.7, which says that condition 2 in Theorem 1.1 must be satisfied. This condition is interesting only when β 2. We note that when β>2, the proof is fairly straightforward. The case β = 2 occupies most of this section. In this section, we begin the inductive proof. Note that by the inductive hypothesis, we may assume Theorem 1.1, Theorem 7.7 (and Corollaries 7.8 and 7.9) hold when the parabolic rank of the supercuspidal support is less than p.r. By Theorem 2.4, we actually know that condition 1 of Theorem 1.1 holds in general. j.

132 CHRIS JANTZEN Suppose π is an irreducible subquotient of δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ. For c 0, let m(c) denote the number of copies of ν ±c ρ which appear in an element of s min (π). We note that m(c) is well-defined and independent of the particular subquotient π (it is simply a matter of supercuspidal support). Set n + (c) =numberofa i or b i which equal c, n (c) =numberofa i or b i which equal c. For c =0,wesimplywriten(0). If δ 0 (π) =δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ, ν a k ρ]) σ, we similarly define n + (c) =numberofa i or b i which equal c, n (c) =numberofa i or b i which equal c. Again, for c = 0, we simply write n (0). The lemma below then follows from supercuspidal support considerations (it is essentially an extension of Proposition 5.3.2, [Jan4]): Lemma 3.1. For c 1, we have the following: 1. For c>1, n + (c 1) n (c) =m(c 1) m(c) =n +(c 1) n (c). 2. For c =1, n (0) n (1) = 2m(0) m(1) = n(0) n (1). (At times, it will be convenient to let n + (0) = n(0), n +(0) = n (0) and just write n + (c 1) n (c) =n +(c 1) n (c) for c 1.) Proof. Consider the contribution of δ([ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ]). Suppose a i,b i 0. Then δ([ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ]) contributes 1 to both n + (a i ) n (a i +1) andn + (b i ) n (b i +1). Also, δ([ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ]) contributes 1 to both m(a i ) m(a i +1) (resp., 2m(0) m(1) if a i =0)andm(b i ) m(b i +1) (resp., 2m(0) m(1) if b i =0). Thecasesa i 0,b i < 0 and a i < 0,b i 0 may be done similarly (a i,b i < 0 is not possible). Combining these and the corresponding observations for δ([ν b i ρ, ν a i ρ]) gives the lemma. We now note the following observation: Lemma 3.2. Suppose π is an irreducible representation with δ 0 (π) =δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ. Then, there is an irreducible representation θ having δ 0 (θ) =δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ. Proof. Choose θ irreducible such that 1. µ (π) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) θ, 2. s app (θ) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ. Since s app (π) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ 0 (θ), we see that δ 0 (θ) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ. The lemma then follows immediately.

SQUARE-INTEGRABLE REPRESENTATIONS OF CLASSICAL p-adic GROUPS II 133 Lemma 3.3. If β>2, then condition 2 of Theorem 1.1 holds. Proof. By the preceding lemma, Theorem 4.2.1, [Jan4], and the inductive hypothesis, [ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ],...,[ν b k ρ] satisfy the conditions of Theorem 1.1. If b 1 < 0, we must have b 1 = β by Remark 4.4.3, [Jan4], and therefore a 1 β as well. Thus, the only way condition 2 could fail for δ 0 (π) istohaveβ 2 b 1 0 (noting that if a 1 β 1, then b 1 β 2). In particular, this also means β { b 2,..., b k,α+1}, and therefore b i β 1fori 2. First, we check that a 1 β 1. If not, we would have δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ]) irreducible for all i 2(ifb i < 0, then a i b i β>a 1 +1; if b i 0, then a i >b i β 1 a 1 >b 1 ). Then, we could commute δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) to the right to get π δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k = δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k. = δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 = δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) δ([ν a1 ρ, ν b1, by the irreducibility of δ([ν a1 ρ, ν b1 (cf. Theorem 13.2, [Tad3]). However, by Frobenius reciprocity, this contradicts the minimality of δ 0 (π) (justbyt.e. considerations). Thus, a 1 β 1. For the moment, let us assume α Z. Then, π δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b k δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν 1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b k. Now, δ([ν b1 ρ, ν 1 ρ]) δ([ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ]) is irreducible for all i 2(ifb i < 0, then a i b i β > 1; if b i 0, then a i >b i β 1 >b 1 ). Thus, commuting δ([ν b1 ρ, ν 1 ρ]) to the right, we get π δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν 1 = δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) δ([νρ,ν b1 by the irreducibility of δ([ν b1 ρ, ν 1 (since b 1 <α). Since δ([ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ]) δ([νρ,ν b1 ρ]) is irreducible for all i 2(ifb i < 0, then a i b i β>b 1 +1; if b i 0, then a i >b 1 and b i β 1 > 1), we have π δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([νρ,ν b1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b k = δ([νρ,ν b1 ρ]) δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b k δ([νρ,ν b1 ρ]) δ([ν β 1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ρ, ν β 2 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b k

134 CHRIS JANTZEN (noting that a 1 >β 2 b 1 ). Now, the same sort of argument as above, applied to δ([ρ, ν β 2 ρ]) this time, gives π δ([νρ,ν b1 ρ]) δ([ν β 1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) δ([ρ, ν β 2 = δ([νρ,ν b1 ρ]) δ([ν β 1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) δ([ν β+2 ρ, = δ([νρ,ν b1 ρ]) δ([ν β+2 ρ, ρ]) δ([ν β 1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b k, noting that β>2 is required for the irreducibility of δ([ν β 1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν β+2 ρ, ρ]). By Frobenius reciprocity and the Casselman criteria, this contradicts the squareintegrability of π. The case α 1 2 + Z is essentially the same. Lemma 3.4. Suppose δ 0 (π) =δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]) σ. Then we must have a 1 <a 2. Proof. Of course, we automatically have a α > >a 2 a 1. Thus we only need to show that a 1 a 2. Suppose a 1 = a 2. Then, π δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν aα = δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν aα δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ρ, νρ]) δ([ν 3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν aα = δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]) δ([ρ, ν = δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]) δ([ν 1 ρ,, contradicting the minimality of δ 0 (π) (t.e. considerations are enough). Lemma 3.5. Suppose k = α and a α > >a 1 > 0. Suppose π δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a2 ρ],...,[ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]; σ) (noting that the inducing representation exists by Theorem 7.7 and the inductive hypothesis). Then, π ρ δ([νρ,ν a1 ρ], [ν 2 ρ, ν a2 ρ],...,[ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]; σ). Proof. Let π = δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a2 ρ],...,[ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]; σ) and π = ρ δ([νρ,ν a1 ρ], [ν 2 ρ, ν a2 ρ],...,[ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]; σ) π = ρ δ([νρ,ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a2 ρ],...,[ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]; σ).

SQUARE-INTEGRABLE REPRESENTATIONS OF CLASSICAL p-adic GROUPS II 135 Then, π,π π. Next, we claim µ δ([ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) (π )=µ δ([ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) (π )=µ δ([ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) (π ) =2 δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a2 ρ],...,[ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]; σ). For π,π, this follows from Lemma 2.6. For π, it is enough to show µ (π ) 2 δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a2 ρ],...,[ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]; σ) (since π π ). This follows immediately from the observation that M (ρ) 2ρ 1andµ (δ([νρ,ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a2 ρ],...,[ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]; σ)) δ([νρ,ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a2 ρ],...,[ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]; σ). By Frobenius reciprocity, one then has that π must be a subquotient, and therefore (by unitarity) a subrepresentation, of π, as needed. Corollary 3.6. Suppose π δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a2 ρ],...,[ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]; σ) with π irreducible and a α > >a 2 >a 1 > 0. Then, either δ 0 (π) =ρ δ([νρ,ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]) σ or there are terms of the form ν x ρ with x<0 which appear in χ 0 (π). Proof. We consider three cases based upon Lemma 3.1. Case 1: n (1) = 1. We note the following: n (x) = 0 for all x>α. The proof of this is fairly simple: for x>α, ν x ρ does not appear as a lower segment end by Lemma 4.4.1, [Jan4]. Also, ν x ρ does not appear as an upper segment end since s min (π) ν y ρ... has y {b 1,...,b k,a 1,...,a k }, which implies c 1 α, and therefore c i α for all i. (Alternatively, the assumption that no negative exponents occur in χ 0 (π) rules out the possibility that ν x ρ appears as an upper segment end.) Now, from n (0) n (1) = n(0) n (1), we see that since n(0) = 1, n (1) = 0, and n (1) = 1, we must have n (0) = 2. For c>1, we have n (c) =n (c), which implies n +(c 1) = n + (c 1). Thus, δ 0 (π) =δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν dα+1 ρ, ν cα+1 ρ]) σ with d 1,...,d α+1,c 1,...,c α+1 equal to α,..., 1, 0, 0,a 1,...,a α up to permutation. In order to have no negative exponents in χ 0 (π), we must have α,..., 1 as d i s and a 1,...,a α as c i s. This accounts for everything but the two zeros, one of which must be the remaining d i, the other the remaining c i.thus, δ 0 (π) =δ([ν d1 ρ, ρ]) δ([ν d2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν dα+1 ρ, ν aα ρ]) σ. Next, observe that we must have d 1 =0;ifd 1 = 1, we do not have n (1) = 1. By Lemma 3.2, there is an irreducible θ having δ 0 (θ) =δ([ν d2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν dα+1 ρ, ν aα ρ]) σ. By Theorem 4.2.1, [Jan4], θ is square-integrable. By the inductive hypothesis, the conditions of Theorem 1.1 are satisfied. The only way this can happen (cf. conditions 3 and 4 of that theorem) is if d 2 > >d α+1.thusd 2 = 1,...,d α+1 = α. Thus δ 0 (π) =ρ δ([νρ,ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]) σ

136 CHRIS JANTZEN is the only possibility remaining in Case 1. Case 2: n (1) = 0 and n (2) = 1. By Lemma 3.1, one easily gets δ 0 (π) =δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν d2 ρ, ν c2 ρ]) δ([ν dα ρ, ν cα ρ]) σ with d 1,...,d α,c 1,...,c α equal to α,..., 2, 0,a 1,...,a α up to permutation. Again, to avoid picking up any negative exponents, we must have a 1,...,a α as c i s, and therefore α,..., 2, 0asd i s. Thus, δ 0 (π) =δ([ν d1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν d2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν dα ρ, ν aα ρ]) σ. As in Case 1, there is an irreducible θ with δ 0 (θ) =δ([ν d2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν dα ρ, ν aα ρ]) σ. As in Case 1, θ is square-integrable and the inductive assumption and Theorem 1.1 tell us we must have d 2 > >d α. Further, condition 2 of Theorem 1.1 also tells us we cannot have one of d 2,...,d α equal to 0. Thus the only possibility remaining in Case 2 is δ 0 (π) =δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]) σ. However, by Lemma 3.5, this cannot occur. Thus Case 2 can be eliminated. Case 3: n (1) = n (2) = 0. In this case, let β be the minimal value having n (β )=1. Ifn (x) = 0 for all x, we take β = α+1. Then, n (1) = = n (β 1) = 0, n (β )= = n (α) =1, and n (x) = 0 for all x>α.sincen (1) = n (1) = 0, n (0) n (1) = n(0) n (1) tells us n (0) = n(0) = 1. Next, we check that a x = x for 1 x β 2. First, n + (1) n (2) = n + (1) n (2) has n (2) = 0 and n (2) = 1. Since n + (1) 1andn + (1) 0, we see that n + (1) = 1 and n +(1) = 0. To have n + (1) = 1, we must have a 1 =1. We iterate this argument until we get to the following: n + (β 2) n (β 1) = n + (β 2) n (β 1) has n (β 1) = 0 and n (β 1) = 1. Therefore, n + (β 2) = 1 and n +(β 2) = 0. For n + (β 2) = 1, we must have a β 2 = β 2. Finally, observe that for x β,wehaven (x) = n (x). Therefore, since n +(x 1) n (x) =n + (x 1) n (x), we have n +(y) =n + (y) fory β 1. Thus, if δ 0 (π) =δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν dj ρ, ν cj ρ]) σ, we must have d 1,...,d j,c 1,...,c j equal to α,..., β, 0,a β 1,...,a α up to permutation. In order that no negative exponents appear, a β 1,...,a α must be c i s and therefore α,..., β, 0mustbed i s. An argument like that used in the previous case then allows us to conclude that δ 0 (π) =δ([ρ, ν a β 1 ρ]) δ([ν β ρ, ν a β ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν aα ρ]) σ. However, since β > 2, this is in contradiction to Theorem 2.4. Thus we can also eliminate Case 3. The corollary now follows. Theorem 3.7. Suppose (H). Suppose that Theorems 1.1 and 7.7 (and Corollaries 7.8 and 7.9) hold when the parabolic rank of the supercuspidal support is less than p.r. Then, condition 2 in Theorem 1.1 holds.

SQUARE-INTEGRABLE REPRESENTATIONS OF CLASSICAL p-adic GROUPS II 137 Proof. By Lemma 3.3, we may assume β =2(whichmeansα must be an integer). As in the proof of Lemma 3.3 (first paragraph), if b 1 < 0, we have b 1 = β and can easily deduce that condition 2 of Theorem 1.1 holds. Also, as in the proof of Lemma 3.3 (first paragraph), if b 1 0, the only way condition 2 of Theorem 1.1 could fail is if β 2 b 1 0, i.e., b 1 = 0. Therefore, all we need to do is show b 1 0. So, let us suppose b 1 = 0. Then, δ 0 (π) =δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ. Next, let [ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ],...,[ν d k ρ, ν c k ρ] denote a permutation of [ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ],...,[ν b k ρ] satisfying d 1 d k. To make it unique, note that only d i =0 can occur for more than one value of i, and then only for two. If we should have b i =0forsomei>1, then [ρ, ν ai ρ] should appear before [ρ, ν a1 ρ] in the above list. We claim that π δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν d k ρ, ν c k which we may write as π δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν dj ρ, ν cj ρ]) δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν cj+2 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν c k. Suppose [ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]=[ν bj ρ, ν aj ρ]. Observe that for i<j, so [ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ] [ν bj ρ, ν aj ρ] δ([ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ]) δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) = δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ]) (irreducible). Thus, we may commute δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) to the left: π δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν bj 2 ρ, ν aj 2 ρ]) δ([ν bj 1 ρ, ν aj 1 ρ]) δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν bj+1 ρ, ν aj+1 ρ]) δ([ν b k = δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν bj 2 ρ, ν aj 2 ρ]) δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν bj 1 ρ, ν aj 1 ρ]) δ([ν bj+1 ρ, ν aj+1 ρ]) δ([ν b k. = δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν bj 2 ρ, ν aj 2 ρ]) δ([ν bj 1 ρ, ν aj 1 ρ]) δ([ν bj+1 ρ, ν aj+1 ρ]) δ([ν b k. Iterating this argument, we next commute δ([ν d2 ρ, ν c2 ρ]) to the left, etc., and we get the result claimed. Now, by Lemma 5.5, [Jan2], π δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν dj ρ, ν cj ρ]) δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν cj+2 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν c k π δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν dj ρ, ν cj ρ]) θ for some irreducible θ δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν cj+2 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν c k. Since s app (π) δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν dj ρ, ν cj ρ]) δ 0 (θ)

138 CHRIS JANTZEN we must have t.e.(δ 0 (θ)) t.e.(δ([ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν cj+2 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν c k ρ]) σ). By Corollary 3.6, δ 0 (θ) =ρ δ([νρ,ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν cj+2 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν c k ρ]) σ. Then, π δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν dj ρ, ν cj ρ]) θ δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν dj ρ, ν cj ρ]) ρ δ([νρ,ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν cj+2 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν c k = ρ δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν dj ρ, ν cj ρ]) δ([νρ,ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν 2 ρ, ν cj+2 ρ]) δ([ν α ρ, ν c k, contradicting the square-integrability of π. The theorem follows. 4. Conditions 3 and 4 the first part of proof In this section, we begin the proof that conditions 3 and 4 in Theorem 1.1 hold. We will view conditions 3 and 4 of Theorem 1.1 as conditions on pairs of segments. By Lemma 3.2, Theorem 4.2.1, [Jan4], and the inductive hypothesis, we know that [ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ], [ν bj ρ, ν aj ρ] satisfy these conditions when i, j > 1withi j. Thus, our goal is to show [ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ], [ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ] satisfy these conditions for i>1. In this section, we address the case where b i >a 1 for some i 2. For any such i, we have a i >b i >a 1 >b 1, so conditions 3 and 4 of Theorem 1.1. certainly hold for [ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ], [ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ]. Roughly speaking, we show that there is an irreducible representation θ, whereδ 0 (θ) is essentially δ 0 (π) withsuchδ([ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ]) removed. We can then use the inductive hypothesis to show δ 0 (θ) satisfies conditions 3. and 4. of Theorem 1.1, which is enough to finish this case. Let us take a moment to review where we stand with respect to the inductive hypothesis. Of course, we may assume Theorems 1.1 and 7.7 (and Corollaries 7.8 and 7.9) hold when the parabolic rank of the supercuspidal support is less than p.r. In addition, we may assume that condition 1 of Theorem 1.1 holds in general (Theorem 2.4) and that condition 2 of Theorem 1.1 holds when the parabolic rank of the supercuspidal support is equal to p.r. (Theorem 3.7 and the inductive hypothesis). The proof of the following proposition is essentially the same as that used in the proof of Theorem 3.7; we will not go through the details. Proposition 4.1. Suppose δ 0 (π) =δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ. Then there exist (unique) l, m, l + m +1=k and permutation [ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ],...,[ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ], [ν b 1 ρ, ν a1 ρ], [ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ],...,[ν b m ρ, ν a m ρ] of [ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ],...,[ν b k ρ] satisfying the following conditions: 1. b 1 >b 2 > >b l >a 1, 2. a 1 <a 2 < <a m with b i a 1 for all i. Furthermore, π δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b m ρ, ν a m.

SQUARE-INTEGRABLE REPRESENTATIONS OF CLASSICAL p-adic GROUPS II 139 The proof for conditions 3 and 4 of Theorem 1.1 will be broken into two parts we address the case l 1 here; the case l = 0 will be addressed in the next section. So, for the remainder of this section, we assume l 1. Observe that by Lemma 3.2, Theorem 4.2.1, [Jan4], and the inductive hypothesis, conditions 3 and 4 of Theorem 1.1 hold for [ν b 1 ρ, ν a construction, we cannot have a i >b i >a j a m >a m 1 > >a 1 >b 1 >b >b j 1 ρ],...,[ν b m ρ, ν a m ρ]. By for i>j. Therefore, we have 2 > >b m. Then, by Lemma 5.5, [Jan2], π δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b m 1 ρ, ν a m 1 ρ]) (δ([ν b m ρ, ν a m ) π δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b m 1 ρ, ν a m 1 ρ]) ξ for some irreducible ξ δ([ν b m ρ, ν a m. By the inductive hypothesis, ξ is one of the representations from Theorem 7.7; by t.e. (and Frobenius reciprocity), to avoid contradicting the minimality of δ 0 (π), we must have ξ = δ([ν b m ρ, ν a m ρ]; σ)t. Then, π δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b m 2 ρ, ν a m 2 ρ]) (δ([ν b m 1 ρ, ν a m 1 ρ]) δ([ν b m ρ, ν a m ρ]; σ)t ) π δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b m 1 ρ, ν a m 1 ρ]) ξ for some irreducible ξ δ([ν b m 2 ρ, ν a m 2 ρ]) δ([ν b m ρ, ν a m ρ]; σ)t. Again, by the inductive hypothesis, ξ is one of the representations from Theorem 7.7; again, by t.e. considerations, we get ξ = δ([ν b m 1 ρ, ν a m 1 ρ], [ν b m ρ, ν a m ρ]; σ)t. Iterating this argument, we get π δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) θ for some irreducible θ δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ],...,[ν b m ρ, ν a m ρ]; σ)t. Lemma 4.2. With notation as above, s δ([ν b (π) =c 1 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ,ν a l ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) θ for some nonzero integer c. Proof. First, by Lemma 5.5, [Jan2], there is an irreducible θ l δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) θ such that π δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l 1 ρ, ν a l 1 ρ]) θ l. Iterating this argument, we obtain θ l 1,θ l 2,...,θ 2 such that each is irreducible, θ i δ([ν b i ρ, ν a i ρ]) θ i+1,andπ δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b i 1 ρ, ν a i 1 ρ]) θ i. First, consider δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) θ 2. We claim µ δ([ν b 1 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) (δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) θ 2 )=2 δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) θ 2.

140 CHRIS JANTZEN Write µ (θ 2 )= h τ h ξ h. Then, a 1 +1 a 1 +1 µ (δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) θ 2 )= δ([ν i+1 ρ, ν b 1 ρ]) h i= b 1 j=i δ([ν j ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) τh δ([ν i ρ, ν j 1 ρ]) ξ h. We now need an observation (the importance of which was underscored for the author by [Mœ3]). Suppose δ([ν bs ρ, ν as ρ]) appears to the left of δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) in the original δ 0 (π). For s = 1, we have a 1 > b 1 > a 1 > b 1 by construction. For s > 1, we have that [ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ], [ν b s ρ, ν as ρ] satisfy the conditions of Theorem 1.1 (by Lemma 3.2, Theorem 4.2.1, [Jan4], and the inductive hypothesis). Therefore, either a 1 >b 1 >a s >b s or a 1 >a s >b s >b 1;wecanrule out the latter since b 1 is known to be larger than b s by construction. Now, suppose δ([ν bs ρ, ν as ρ]) appears to the right of δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) in the original δ0 (π). Again, since [ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ], [ν b s ρ, ν as ρ] satisfy the conditions of Theorem 1.1, either a s >b s >a 1 >b 1 or a s >a 1 >b 1 >b s; we can rule out the former since b 1 is known to be larger than b s by construction. In particular, the observation we need is the following: there is no element of {a 1,...,a k,b 1,...,b k }\{b 1,a 1} in the interval [b 1,a 1 ]. Therefore, to contribute to µ,wemusthavej δ([ν b 1 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) b 1 +1 in the displayed equation above. Suppose j = b 1 + 1. Then, τ h = δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν i ρ]). If i b 1 + 1, then by central character considerations, θ 2 ν i ρ ν i 1 ρ ν b 1 ρ ξh π δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) ν i ρ ν i 1 ρ ν b1 ρ ξ h = ν i ρ ν i 1 ρ ν b 1 ρ δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) ξh, contradicting the square-integrability of π. Thus,i = b 1 +1, so τ h =1andξ h = θ 2. This contributes one copy of δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) θ 2 (and nothing else) to µ δ([ν b 1 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) (δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) θ 2 ). If j b 1 + 1, then we must have i = b 1 (since νb 1 ρ appear only once in r min (δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]))). A similar argument tells us we must again have τh =1, ξ h = θ 2. So, j = b 1 contributes a second copy of δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) θ 2 to µ δ([ν b 1 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) (δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) θ 2 ). Thus, µ δ([ν b 1 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) (δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) θ 2 )=2 δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) θ 2, as claimed. Let us briefly discuss the first iteration of this argument. Our claim is that µ δ([ν b 2 ρ,ν a 2 ρ]) (δ([ν b 2 ρ, ν a 2 ρ]) θ 3 )=2 δ([ν b 2 ρ, ν a 2 ρ]) θ 3. The analogue to the observation above is that there is nothing in {a 1,...,a k,b 1,...,b k }\{a 1,b 1} which is strictly between b 2 +1 and a 2. Again, let us write

SQUARE-INTEGRABLE REPRESENTATIONS OF CLASSICAL p-adic GROUPS II 141 µ (θ 3 )= h τ h ξ h. Then, µ (δ([ν b 2 ρ, ν a 2 ρ]) θ 3 )= a 2 +1 a 2 +1 δ([ν i+1 ρ, ν b 2 ρ]) h i= b j=i 2 δ([ν j ρ, ν a 2 ρ]) τh δ([ν i ρ, ν j 1 ρ]) ξ h. Again, to contribute to µ,wemusthavej δ([ν b 2 ρ,ν a 2 ρ]) b 2 +1. Ifj = b 2 +1,we get i = b 2 +1asbefore: ifi b 2 + 1, then central character considerations tell us θ 3 ν i ρ ν i 1 ρ ν b 1 ρ ξh π δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b 2 ρ, ν a 2 ρ]) ν i ρ ν i 1 ρ ν b 2 ρ ξh = ν i ρ ν i 1 ρ ν b 2 ρ δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b 2 ρ, ν a 2 ρ]) ξh, which contradicts the square-integrability of π. Wheni = b 2 + 1, we get a contribution of one copy of δ([ν b 2 ρ, ν a 2 ρ]) θ 3 to µ δ([ν b 2 ρ,ν a 2 ρ]) (δ([ν b 2 ρ, ν a 2 ρ]) θ 3 ). If j < b 2 + 1, then we must have i = b 2 and τ h = δ([ν b 2 ρ, ν j 1 ρ]). The same argument as before tells us we must have j = b 2. Therefore, τ h = 1 and ξ h = θ 3, giving a contribution of one more copy of δ([ν b 2 ρ, ν a 2 ρ]) θ 3 to µ δ([ν b 2 ρ,ν a 2 ρ]) (δ([ν b 2 ρ, ν a 2 ρ]) θ 3 ), as claimed. The lemma follows by iterating. It follows immediately from properties of Jacquet functors that there is an irreducible representation θ satisfying 1. s app (π) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) θ, 2. s app (θ ) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b m ρ, ν a m ρ]) σ. The corollary below then follows immediately from Lemma 4.2. Corollary 4.3. With notation as above, θ = θ. Theorem 4.4. Suppose (H). Suppose that Theorems 1.1 and 7.7 (and Corollaries 7.8 and 7.9) are proved when the parabolic rank of the supercuspidal support is less than p.r. and that condition 2 of Theorem 1.1 is also proved when the parabolic rank of the supercuspidal support is equal to p.r. Then, if l 1, conditions 3 and 4 of Theorem 1.1 hold (l as in Proposition 4.1). Proof. By the inductive hypothesis, Lemma 3.2, and Theorem of 4.2.1 [Jan4], we have that [ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ], [ν b k ρ, ν aj ρ] satisfy conditions 3 and 4 of Theorem 1.1 when i>j 2. Therefore, it is enough to show that [ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ], [ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ], i 2 satisfy conditions 3 and 4. Further, by construction [ν b i ρ, ν a i ρ], [ν b 1 ρ, ν a1 ρ] satisfy conditions 3 and 4 Thus, it remains to show that [ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ], [ν b i ρ, ν a i ρ] satisfy conditions 3 and 4. To show [ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ], [ν b i ρ, ν a i ρ] satisfy conditions 3 and 4, it is enough (by the inductive hypothesis) to show the following: δ 0 (θ) =δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b m ρ, ν a m ρ]) σ (θ as above). The theorem then follows immediately. Consider the permutation of [ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ],...,[ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ] where a 1,...,a l appear in increasing order of size. Since it is this permutation we need for the

142 CHRIS JANTZEN remainder of this proof, let us abuse notation somewhat and simply denote it by [ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ],...,[ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ], where a 1 < <a l. Then, π δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b m ρ, ν a m (as in the proof of Theorem 3.7, any δ([ν b i ρ, ν a i ρ]), δ([ν b i+1 ρ, ν a i+1 ρ]) which has a i+1 <a i can be transposed by an irreducibility argument; a sequence of such transpositions suffices to rearrange terms in the order described). First, observe that by construction, δ 0 (θ ) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b m ρ, ν a m ρ]) σ. Also, since we see that s app (π) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) δ0 (θ ), t.e.(δ 0 (θ )) t.e.(δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b m ρ, ν a m ρ]) σ). Therefore, t.e.(δ 0 (θ ))=t.e.(δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b m ρ, ν a m ρ]) σ). Now, suppose δ 0 (θ )=δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν cs ρ, ν cs ρ]) σ. If we assume δ 0 (θ ) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b m ρ, ν a m ρ]) σ, wemusthaveδ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν cs ρ, ν cs ρ]) σ lower than δ 0 (θ ) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b m ρ, ν a m ρ]) σ lexicographically. Suppose δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) is less than δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) lexicographically. Then, a j >b j >a 1 c 1.Ifd 1 b l,thenδ([ν b j ρ, ν a j ρ]) δ([ν d 1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) is irreducible for all j. By Corollary 4.3, π δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) δ([ν d 1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν ds ρ, ν cs = δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) δ([ν ds ρ, ν cs, contradicting the minimality of δ 0 (π). If d 1 >b l,then δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) δ([ν d 1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) = δ([ν b l ρ, ν c 1 ρ]) δ([ν d1 ρ, ν a l ρ]) + L(δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]),δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ])) (noting that c 1 {b 1,b 1,...,b m,a 1,a 1,...,a m} forces c 1 > b l ). Therefore, by Lemma 5.5, [Jan4], π δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l 1 ρ, ν a l 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ, ν c 1 ρ]) δ([ν d1 ρ, ν a l ρ]) δ([ν d 2 ρ, ν c2 ρ]) δ([ν ds ρ, ν cs

SQUARE-INTEGRABLE REPRESENTATIONS OF CLASSICAL p-adic GROUPS II 143 or π δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l 1 ρ, ν a l 1 ρ]) δ([ν d 1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) δ([ν d 2 ρ, ν c2 ρ]) δ([ν ds ρ, ν cs. In the first case, we now argue as we did when d 1 b l to obtain π δ([ν b l ρ, ν c 1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l 1 ρ, ν a l 1 ρ]) δ([ν d1 ρ, ν a l ρ]) δ([ν d 2 ρ, ν c2 ρ]) δ([ν ds ρ, ν cs, again contradicting the minimality of δ 0 (π). In the second case, we can iterate the argument above: if d 1 b l 1, we can again commute ρ, ν δ([ν d1 c1 ρ]) forward to get a contradiction. If d 1 >b l 1, we can again look at δ([ν b l 1 ρ, ν b l 1 ρ]) δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) and repeat the argument above. In either case, we eventually get π δ([ν x ρ, ν c1 ρ])..., with x = d 1 or b j for some j. In any case, we contradict the minimality of δ 0(π). Therefore, we could not have had δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) less than δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) lexicographically. Thus c 1 = a 1 and d 1 = b 1. Since δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) = δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]), let us now suppose δ([ν d2 ρ, ν c2 ρ]) is lexicographically lower than δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]). We can easily see that π δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b l ρ, ν a l ρ]) δ([ν d2 ρ, ν c2 ρ]) δ([ν ds ρ, ν cs. Now, take i such that a i <a 1 <a i+1 (subject to the obvious convention if a 1 <a 1 or a 1 > a l ). Then, [ν b j ρ, ν a j ρ] = [ν b j+1 ρ, ν aj+1 ρ]for1 j i. Further, [ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]=[ν b i+2 ρ, ν ai+2 ρ]. Repeating the argument above, we get π δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b i ρ, ν a i ρ]) δ([ν x ρ, ν c2 ρ])... = δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν bi+1 ρ, ν ai+1 ρ]) δ([ν x ρ, ν c2 ρ])... for x = d 2 or b j some j>i. Again, this contradicts the minimality of δ 0(π). Thus we must have d 2 = b 1 and c 2 = a 1. We can now iterate this argument to see that δ 0 (θ )=δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 ρ, ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b m ρ, ν a m ρ]) σ, as claimed. This finishes the proof. 5. Conditions 3 and 4 the second part of proof In this section, we address the second part of the proof of conditions 3 and 4, the case where l = 0. The basic idea here is this: we assume δ 0 (π) fails to satisfy these conditions, then show that π can be embedded into another induced representation, one which corresponds to a δ 0 lower than assumed. Let us review where we stand with respect to the inductive hypothesis. Of course, we may assume Theorems 1.1 and 7.7 (and Corollaries 7.8 and 7.9) hold when the parabolic rank of the supercuspidal support is less than p.r. In addition, we may assume that condition 1 of Theorem 1.1 holds in general (Theorem 2.4) and

144 CHRIS JANTZEN that condition 2 of Theorem 1.1 holds when the parabolic rank of the supercuspidal support is equal to p.r. (Theorem 3.7 and the inductive hypothesis). We are also free to assume that conditions 3 and 4 of Theorem 1.1 hold when the parabolic rank of the supercuspidal support is equal to p.r. and l 1, but we do not actually use this in dealing with the case l =0. Again, by Lemma 3.2, Theorem 4.2.1 of [Jan4], and the inductive hypothesis, [ν b2 ρ, ν a2 ρ],...,[ν b k ρ] satisfy the conditions of Theorem 1.1. Therefore, for i>j 2, we must have either a i >b i >a j >b j or a i >a j >b j >b i. However, to have l = 0, the former cannot occur. Thus, a i >a j >b j >b i for i, j 2. Therefore, a k > >a 2 >b 2 > >b k. Further, we must have b 2 a 1. By construction, we have a 1 a 2. We now show that the inequality is strict. Lemma 5.1. a 1 a 2. Proof. Suppose not. Let us use a 1 for both a 1 and a 2.Since π δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k = δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k, we see that in order for δ 0 (π) to be minimal lexicographically, we must have b 1 b 2. First, suppose b 1 < 0. By Theorem 2.4, we have b 1 b 2. Then, π δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k = δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b1+1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) ν b1 ρ δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k = δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b1+1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) ν b1 ρ σ = δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b1+1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) ν b1 ρ σ, where ν b1 ρ δ([ν bi ρ, ν ai ρ]) is irreducible for i 3since b 1 < b i 1. This contradicts the minimality of δ 0 (π) (by Frobenius reciprocity and total exponent considerations). Thus, we are now free to assume b 1 0. Next,wenotethatifb 2 < 0, then by Theorem 3.7 we have b 1 b 2 1=β 1. Thus (whether b 2 < 0orb 2 0), Theorem 7.7 and the inductive hypothesis allow us to define π t = δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a1 ρ], [ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k, π t = δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν b1 ρ], [ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k, π t = δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b1+1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν b1 ρ], [ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k

SQUARE-INTEGRABLE REPRESENTATIONS OF CLASSICAL p-adic GROUPS II 145 (noting that [ν b2 ρ, ν b1 ρ]= is possible). By Corollary 7.8, we see that π t πt. By Lemma 5.4, [BDK], πt = ρ, ν δ([ν b1 a1 ρ]) δ([ν a1 ρ, ν b1 1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν b1 ρ], [ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k, so π t π t as well. It follows fairly easily from Lemma 2.6 that µ δ([ν b 1 +1 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 +1 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) (π t )=µ δ([ν b 1 +1 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 +1 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) (π t) = δ([ν b1+1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b1+1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν b1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν b1 ρ], [ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k Since π π t,wehaveµ (π) 0. Now, δ([ν b 1 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b 2 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) m ρ, ν δ([ν b 1 +1 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 +1 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) (δ([ν b1 a1 ρ]) δ([ν b2 ρ, ν a1 ρ])) 0 (π) 0. µ δ([ν b 1 +1 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) δ([ν b 1 +1 ρ,ν a 1 ρ]) From above, this implies π π t. By unitarity, π π t, contradicting the squareintegrability of π. Thuswecouldnothavehada 1 = a 2, as claimed. If b 1 >b 2,wehavea k > >a 2 >a 1 >b 1 >b 2 > >b k, which certainly satisfies conditions 3 and 4 of Theorem 1.1. So, let us assume b 1 b 2. Then, a 2 >a 1 b 2 b 1. Consider the possibility that b 2 = a 1 ; write a 1 for both. Observe that π δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k = δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k π δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) θ, for some irreducible θ δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k (Lemma 5.5, [Jan2]). Now, consider µ δ([ν a 1 ρ,ν a 2 ρ]) (π). Write µ (θ) = h τ h θ h. Then, µ (δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) θ) = a 2+1 a 2+1 [δ([ν i+1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) h i= a 1 j=i δ([ν j ρ, ν a2 ρ]) τ h ] δ([ν i ρ, ν j 1 ρ]) θ h. To contribute to µ ρ. There are three possible δ([ν a 1 ρ,ν a 2 ρ]),wemustpickupaν a1 sources. If the ν a1 ρ comes from δ([ν j ρ, ν a2 ρ]), we must have j = a 1.Theni = a 1 and τ h = 1, giving a contribution of one copy of δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) θ. Suppose δ([ν i+1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) contributes the ν a1 ρ. Then, i = a 1 + 1. By Lemma 2.6, we then have τ h = 1. Therefore, j = a 1 + 1. Thus we get a contribution of one more copy of δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) θ. Finally, suppose τ h contributes the ν a1 ρ. Since anything in r min (τ h ) has the form ν x ρ... with x {b 1,b 3,...,b k,a 1,a 3,...,a k },wesee that r min (τ h )mustcontainsomethingoftheform(ν x ρ ν x 1 ρ ν a1 ρ)... for such an x. Further, since a 3,...,a k >a 2,wemusthavex a 1. Now, we have that s min (θ) contains something of the form (ν x ρ ν x 1 ρ ν a1 ρ)... Therefore, by central character considerations, θ ν x ρ ν x 1 ρ ν a1 ρ θ

146 CHRIS JANTZEN for some irreducible θ. Then, π δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) θ δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) ν x ρ ν x 1 ρ ν a1 ρ θ = ν x ρ ν x 1 ρ ν a1 ρ δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) θ. However, by Frobenius reciprocity, this contradicts the square-integrability of π. Thus we cannot have τ h contributing the ν a1 ρ. It follows immediately that we must have µ δ([ν a 1 ρ,ν a 2 ρ]) (π) =c ρ, ν δ([ν a1 a2 ρ]) θ for some c 2. On the other hand, from properties of the Jacquet functors, we know that there is an irreducible θ such that 1. µ (π) δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) θ, 2. s app (θ ) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ. From the above calculations, it follows that θ = θ. We now claim δ 0 (θ) = δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ. As the argument is similar to the proof of Theorem 4.4 (but easier), we will be somewhat brief. First, it follows easily from θ = θ that t.e.(δ 0 (θ)) = t.e.(δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ). Suppose δ 0 (θ) =δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν d2 ρ, ν c2 ρ]) δ([ν d h ρ, ν c h ρ]) σ is lower than δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ lexicographically. Observe that δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) is either irreducible or is equal to δ([ν a1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν d1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) + L(δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]),δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ])). In any case, we get either π δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν d2 ρ, ν c2 ρ])... (Lemma 5.5, [Jan2]) π δ([ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν d2 ρ, ν c2 ρ])... or δ([ν a1 ρ, ν c1 ρ]) δ([ν d1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν d2 ρ, ν c2 ρ])... Whichever holds, if [ν d1 ρ, ν c1 ρ] is lexicographically lower than [ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]weget a contradiction to the minimality of δ 0 (π). Therefore, d 1 = b 1 and c 1 = a 1. But, in that case, π δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν d2 ρ, ν c2 ρ])... = δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν d2 ρ, ν c2 ρ])..., so δ([ν d2 ρ, ν c2 ρ]) δ([ν d h ρ, ν c h ρ]) σ cannot be lexicographically lower than δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ]) δ([ν b k ρ]) σ. The claim follows. By Theorem 4.2.1, [Jan4], θ is square-integrable; by the inductive hypothesis, the conditions of Theorem 1.1 must be satisfied. Since b 3 <b 2 a 1 (from the assumption l =0), we can easily conclude that a k > >a 3 >a 1 >b 1 >b 3 > >b k.wearenow ready to prove the following:

SQUARE-INTEGRABLE REPRESENTATIONS OF CLASSICAL p-adic GROUPS II 147 Lemma 5.2. a 1 >b 2. Proof. Suppose b 2 = a 1.Observethat π δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k = δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k (Lemma 5.5, [Jan2]) π δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) θ for some irreducible θ δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k By Theorem 7.7 (and the inductive hypothesis), we know the possibilities for δ 0 (θ). Since s app (π) δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ 0 (θ), we see that only θ = δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ], [ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k does not contradict the minimality of δ 0 (π). Note that if k>2, we have t = t automatically. (If k = 2, we could argue that t = t, but it is not needed.) Since b 1 >b 3, we may now define π t = ρ, ν δ([ν a1 a2 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ], [ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k, π t = ρ, ν δ([ν a1 a1 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a2 ρ], [ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k, πt = ρ, ν δ([ν a1 a1 ρ]) δ([ν a1+1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ], [ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k. By Corollary 7.8 (and the inductive hypothesis), π t,π t π t. By Lemma 2.6 (and Corollary 7.8) µ δ([ν a 1 +1 ρ,ν a 2 ρ]) (π t )=µ δ([ν a 1 +1 ρ,ν a 2 ρ]) (π t )=µ δ([ν a 1 +1 ρ,ν a 2 ρ]) (π t ) = δ([ν a1+1 ρ, ν a2 ρ]) δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ], [ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k. Now, µ δ([ν a 1 ρ,ν a 2 ρ]) (π) 0 implies µ δ([ν a 1 +1 ρ,ν a 2 ρ]) (π) 0. Therefore, π π t ; by unitarity, π π t. However, this contradicts the square-integrability of π (or minimality of δ 0 (π)). Thus, we could not have had b 2 = a 1. We now show the following: Lemma 5.3. Assuming a 2 >a 1 >b 2 b 1, we have b 1 b 2. Proof. Suppose b 1 = b 2. By Theorem 2.4, we must have b 1 = b 2 0. As in the beginning of section 4 (the argument immediately preceding the statement of Lemma 4.2), if δ 0 (π) is as assumed, we have π δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a2 ρ], [ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k, for some t. By Theorem 7.7 and the inductive hypothesis, we may define π t = δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a2 ρ], [ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k, π t = δ([ν b1 ρ, ν b1 ρ]) δ([ν a1 ρ, ν a2 ρ], [ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k, πt = δ([ν b1+1 ρ, ν a1 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν b1 ρ]) δ([ν b1 ρ, ν a2 ρ], [ν b3 ρ, ν a3 ρ],...,[ν b k