A Conception of Inductive Logic: Example

Σχετικά έγγραφα
Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set

2 Composition. Invertible Mappings

Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit

C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions

Lecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic

4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1)

ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II

EE512: Error Control Coding

Example Sheet 3 Solutions

The challenges of non-stable predicates

Homework 3 Solutions

Section 8.3 Trigonometric Equations

Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in

Matrices and Determinants

A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation

MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS

ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER

Phys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required)

Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequality for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x, y, z X.

Reminders: linear functions

Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations

Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor

5. Choice under Uncertainty

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees

Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests

Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs

derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates

Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers

Solution Series 9. i=1 x i and i=1 x i.

Finite Field Problems: Solutions

Strukturalna poprawność argumentu.

Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics

6.1. Dirac Equation. Hamiltonian. Dirac Eq.

Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 19/5/2007

Απόκριση σε Μοναδιαία Ωστική Δύναμη (Unit Impulse) Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο. Απόστολος Σ.

CHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS

Tridiagonal matrices. Gérard MEURANT. October, 2008

Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests

Fourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics

Econ 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1

Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3

k A = [k, k]( )[a 1, a 2 ] = [ka 1,ka 2 ] 4For the division of two intervals of confidence in R +

ω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω

Main source: "Discrete-time systems and computer control" by Α. ΣΚΟΔΡΑΣ ΨΗΦΙΑΚΟΣ ΕΛΕΓΧΟΣ ΔΙΑΛΕΞΗ 4 ΔΙΑΦΑΝΕΙΑ 1

The Simply Typed Lambda Calculus

Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016

Μηχανική Μάθηση Hypothesis Testing

Quadratic Expressions

HOMEWORK 4 = G. In order to plot the stress versus the stretch we define a normalized stretch:

Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude

Homomorphism in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Automata

Math221: HW# 1 solutions

3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β

CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS

Problem Set 3: Solutions

Lecture 21: Properties and robustness of LSE

Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5. Luca Alberucci, University of Berne. Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008

2. Let H 1 and H 2 be Hilbert spaces and let T : H 1 H 2 be a bounded linear operator. Prove that [T (H 1 )] = N (T ). (6p)

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM

Generating Set of the Complete Semigroups of Binary Relations

( y) Partial Differential Equations

SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS

SCITECH Volume 13, Issue 2 RESEARCH ORGANISATION Published online: March 29, 2018

Lecture 34 Bootstrap confidence intervals

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 6/5/2006

Overview. Transition Semantics. Configurations and the transition relation. Executions and computation

6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes

Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2

Solutions to Exercise Sheet 5

Theorem 8 Let φ be the most powerful size α test of H

Coefficient Inequalities for a New Subclass of K-uniformly Convex Functions

On a four-dimensional hyperbolic manifold with finite volume

F A S C I C U L I M A T H E M A T I C I

DIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANSFORMATION SEMIGROUPS

Practice Exam 2. Conceptual Questions. 1. State a Basic identity and then verify it. (a) Identity: Solution: One identity is csc(θ) = 1

Some new generalized topologies via hereditary classes. Key Words:hereditary generalized topological space, A κ(h,µ)-sets, κµ -topology.

DESIGN OF MACHINERY SOLUTION MANUAL h in h 4 0.

Dynamic types, Lambda calculus machines Section and Practice Problems Apr 21 22, 2016

1. Introduction and Preliminaries.

Formal Semantics. 1 Type Logic

ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC = DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION #2. h 0 h h 0 h h 0 ( ) g k = g 0 + g 1 + g g 2009 =?

SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM

Depth versus Rigidity in the Design of International Trade Agreements. Leslie Johns

Partial Differential Equations in Biology The boundary element method. March 26, 2013

PARTIAL NOTES for 6.1 Trigonometric Identities

Math 6 SL Probability Distributions Practice Test Mark Scheme

Trigonometry 1.TRIGONOMETRIC RATIOS

Συντακτικές λειτουργίες

Second Order Partial Differential Equations

Section 7.6 Double and Half Angle Formulas

= {{D α, D α }, D α }. = [D α, 4iσ µ α α D α µ ] = 4iσ µ α α [Dα, D α ] µ.

2. THEORY OF EQUATIONS. PREVIOUS EAMCET Bits.

Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II

On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions.

If we restrict the domain of y = sin x to [ π, π ], the restrict function. y = sin x, π 2 x π 2

Pg The perimeter is P = 3x The area of a triangle is. where b is the base, h is the height. In our case b = x, then the area is

λρ-calculus 1. each λ-variable is a λρ-term, called an atom or atomic term; 2. if M and N are λρ-term then (MN) is a λρ-term called an application;

Transcript:

A Conception of Inductive Logic: Example Patrick Maher Department of Philosophy, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign This paper presents a simple example of inductive logic done according to the conception of inductive logic described in Maher (2006). Thus it defines a function p that is intended to be an explicatum for inductive probability. 1. The language L The arguments of p will be sentences of a formal language L that is defined by the following clauses. 1 1. L contains the following signs: a) Individual constants: a and b b) Predicates: F and G c) Connectives:,, and. d) Parentheses: ( and ) 2. The following rules specify which expressions are sentences in L: a) If φ is a predicate and α an individual constant then φα is a sentence. b) If σ is a sentence then so is σ. c) If σ 1 and σ 2 are sentences then so are (σ 1 σ 2 )and(σ 1.σ 2 ). d) Nothing is a sentence unless its being so follows from a) c). 3. Let there be an urn that at time t contains two balls, one of which is heavier than the other. The meaning of the individual constants and predicates in L is given by the following rules. a) a designates the lighter of the two balls in the urn. b) b designates the heavier of the two balls in the urn. 1 In order to describe this language I will use the following standard conventions: (a) An expression in single quotation marks designates the expression contained by the quotation marks. (b) Signs of L designate themselves. (c) A concatenation of signs that designate expressions of L designates the expression obtained by replacing each sign by the expression it designates. coileg.tex; 16/08/2005; 7:16; p.1

2 c) F designates the property of being white at time t. d) G designates the property of being black at time t. 4. Truth in L is defined by the following rules. a) If φ is a predicate and α is an individual constant then φα is true iff the individual that α designates has the property that φ designates. b) If σ is a sentence then σ is true iff σ is not true. c) If σ 1 and σ 2 are sentences then i) (σ 1 σ 2 ) is true iff at least one of σ 1 and σ 2 is true. ii) (σ 1.σ 2 ) is true iff σ 1 and σ 2 are both true. 2. L-concepts The atomic sentences of L are Fa, Ga, Fb, and Gb. Let a model for L be an assignment of truth values to each of these atomic sentences. There are 2 4 = 16 models for L.IfM is a model for L and σ is a sentence in L then σ is said to be true in M if the truth value assignments of M, together with the rules of truth for the connectives of L, imply that σ is true. For example, (Fa Fb) is true in the models that assign truth to at least one of Fa and Fb. Let a logically true sentence be a sentence that is true in virtue of meanings alone. Since it is logically true that nothing can be black and white at the same time, (F a.ga) and (F b.gb) are logically true sentences in L. Let an admissible model for L be a model in which these sentences are true. There are 3 2 = 9 admissible models for L. A sentence in L will be said to be L-true if it is true in all admissible models for L. For example, (Fa Fa) and ( Fa Ga) are L-true. The concept of L-truth is an explicatum for the vague ordinary concept of logical truth. A sentence in L will be said to be L-false if it is not true in any admissible models. A sentence σ 1 in L will be said to L-imply a sentence σ 2 in L if the set of admissible models in which σ 1 is true is a subset of the set of admissible models in which σ 2 is true. Sentences σ 1 and σ 2 will be said to be L-equivalent if the set of admissible models in which σ 1 is true is the same as the set of admissible models in which σ 2 is true. These concepts are explicata for ordinary concepts of logical falsity, logical implication, and logical equivalence, respectively. coileg.tex; 16/08/2005; 7:16; p.2

3 3. The function p I will now state conditions on the function p that together will serve to define p. To begin, let σ designate the sentence ((Fa Ga).(Fb Gb)). The domain of p is specified by: CONDITION 1. p(σ 1,σ 2 ) exists iff σ 1 and σ 2 are sentences in L and σ 2 L-implies σ. The requirement that σ 2 L-imply σ is imposed because it makes it easier to define a satisfactory p without entirely trivializing the problem. The requirement that p satisfy the mathematical laws of conditional probability is here given the following specific form. (In what follows, outer parentheses are dropped in designations of sentences in L, so e.g., σ 1.σ 2 is to be understood as referring to (σ 1.σ 2 ).) CONDITION 2. If σ 1, σ 2, and σ 3 are sentences in L and σ 3 L-implies σ then: A1. p(σ 1,σ 3 ) 0. A2. p(σ 3,σ 3 )=1. A3. p(σ 1,σ 3 )+p( σ 1,σ 3 )=1, provided σ 3 is not L-false. A4. p(σ 1.σ 2,σ 3 )=p(σ 1,σ 3 )p(σ 2,σ 1.σ 3 ). A5. If σ 1 and σ 3 are L-equivalent to σ 1 and σ 3 respectively, then p(σ 1,σ 3)=p(σ 1,σ 3 ). Maher (2004) stated essentially these axioms and deduced many of their consequences, including the usual elementary theorems of probability. CONDITION 3. p(fa,σ )=p(fb,σ )=1/2. The inductive probability of Fa given σ is 1/2, and likewise for Fb. Condition 3 ensures that p agrees with inductive probability in this respect. CONDITION 4. p(f b, F a.σ )=2/3. The inductive probability of Fb given F a.σ does not have a precise numerical value but it is greater than 1/2 since Fa increases the inductive probability of Fb. The value of 2/3 is chosen as a precise value that is convenient and sufficiently similar to the vague inductive probability. There is one and only one function p that satisfies Conditions 1 4, as I show in the next section. Hence the definition of p is now complete. coileg.tex; 16/08/2005; 7:16; p.3

4 4. Proof of the existence and uniqueness of p Section 4.1 states three new conditions and shows that exactly one function p satisfies them and Condition 1. Sections 4.3 and 4.4 show that these new conditions are equivalent to Conditions 2 4. It follows that exactly one function p satisfies Conditions 1 4. 4.1. Three new conditions DEFINITION 1. σ = Ga.Gb. σ ab = Fa.Fb, σ a = F a.gb, σ b = Ga.F b, and CONDITION 5. p(σ ab,σ )=1/3, p(σ a,σ )=1/6, p(σ b,σ )=1/6, and p(σ,σ )=1/3. DEFINITION 2. If σ 1 is any sentence in L then r(σ 1 ) is the set of all σ α {σ ab,σ a,σ b,σ } such that σ 1.σ α is not L-false. The set r(σ 1 ) is like what Carnap (1950) called the range of σ 1 except that it is relative to σ. Note that r(σ 1 )= (the empty set) iff σ 1.σ is L-false. CONDITION 6. If σ 1 is a sentence in L other than σ ab, σ a, σ b,orσ then p(σ 1,σ )= p(σ, σ ). σ r(σ 1 ) CONDITION 7. If σ 1 and σ 3 are sentences in L, σ 3 is not σ, and σ 3 L-implies σ then { } p(σ1.σ 3,σ ) p(σ 1,σ 3 )= p(σ 3,σ ) if 0. 1 if =0 PROPOSITION 1. Exactly one function p satisfies Conditions 1 and 5 7. Proof. Conditions 5 7 each assign values to p(σ 1,σ 3 ) for different pairs <σ 1,σ 3 >, so these conditions are consistent with one another. Furthermore, these three conditions specify a value of p(σ 1,σ 3 )iffσ 1 and σ 3 are sentences in L and σ 3 L-implies σ, so they are also consistent with Condition 1. Hence there exists a function that satisfies Condition 1 and Conditions 5 7. Since Conditions 5 7 specify a unique value of p(σ 1,σ 3 ) for all such σ 1 and σ 3, there is only one function that satisfies Condition 1 and Conditions 5 7. coileg.tex; 16/08/2005; 7:16; p.4

5 4.2. Propositions not involving p Throughout what follows, σ 1 and σ 2 are any sentences in L. PROPOSITION 2. If σ α {σ ab,σ a,σ b,σ } then σ 1.σ α is L-false or L-equivalent to σ α. Proof. Suppose σ α {σ ab,σ a,σ b,σ }. Then there is only one admissible model for L in which σ α is true. For example, σ ab is true in the model that assigns truth to Fa and Fb and falsity to Ga and Gb ; it is false in the other eight admissible models. Let M be the admissible model in which σ α is true. If σ 1 is true in M then σ 1.σ α is true in M and false in every other admissible model, so σ 1.σ α is L-equivalent to σ α.ifσ 1 is false in M then σ 1.σ α is false in every admissible model and hence L-false. So σ 1.σ α is either L-false or L-equivalent to σ α. PROPOSITION 3. If r(σ 1 ) then every disjunction of all elements of r(σ 1 ) is L-equivalent to σ 1.σ. Proof. Suppose r(σ 1 ) and let σ 1r be a disjunction of all elements of r(σ 1 ). Let denote L-equivalence. Then σ 1r (σ 1.σ ab ) (σ 1.σ a ) (σ 1.σ b ) (σ 1.σ ), by Definition 2 and Proposition 2 σ 1.(σ ab σ a σ b σ ) σ 1.σ, since σ σ ab σ a σ b σ. PROPOSITION 4. r(σ 1.σ 2 ) r( σ 1.σ 2 )=r(σ 2 ) and r(σ 1.σ 2 ) r( σ 1.σ 2 )=. Proof. (i) Suppose σ α r(σ 1.σ 2 ). Then by Definition 2, σ 1.σ 2.σ α is not L-false. It follows that σ 2.σ α is not L-false and hence σ α r(σ 2 ). Thus r(σ 1.σ 2 ) r(σ 2 ). Similarly, r( σ 1.σ 2 ) r(σ 2 ) and so r(σ 1.σ 2 ) r( σ 1.σ 2 ) r(σ 2 ). (1) (ii) Suppose σ α r(σ 2 ). Then by Definition 2, σ 2.σ α is not L-false. It follows that not both of σ 1.σ 2.σ α and σ 1.σ 2.σ α are L-false and hence σ α r(σ 1.σ 2 ) r( σ 1.σ 2 ). Thus r(σ 2 ) r(σ 1.σ 2 ) r( σ 1.σ 2 ). (2) (iii) From (1) and (2) it follows that r(σ 1.σ 2 ) r( σ 1.σ 2 )=r(σ 2 ). coileg.tex; 16/08/2005; 7:16; p.5

6 (iv) Suppose σ α r(σ 1.σ 2 ) r( σ 1.σ 2 ). Then by Definition 2, neither σ 1.σ 2.σ α nor σ 1.σ 2.σ α is L-false. So by Proposition 2, σ 1.σ 2.σ α and σ 1.σ 2.σ α are both L-equivalent to σ α. Hence σ 1.σ 2.σ α is L-equivalent to σ 1.σ 2.σ α. Since these cannot both be true they must both be L- false. But we deduced that neither is L-false. This contradiction shows that the assumption from which we began is false, i.e., there is no σ α r(σ 1.σ 2 ) r( σ 1.σ 2 ) and so r(σ 1.σ 1 ) r( σ 1.σ 2 )=. 4.3. Necessity This section will show that Conditions 2 4 imply Conditions 5 7. Throughout what follows, σ 1 and σ 2 are any sentences in L and σ 3 is any sentence in L that L-implies σ. PROPOSITION 5. Condition 2 implies that if σ 3 L-implies σ 1 then p(σ 1,σ 3 )=1. Proof. Assume Condition 2 holds and σ 3 L-implies σ 1. Then p(σ 1,σ 3 ) = p(σ 1,σ 3 ) p(σ 3,σ 3 ), by A2 = p(σ 1,σ 3 ) p(σ 3,σ 1.σ 3 ), by A5 = p(σ 1.σ 3,σ 3 ), by A4 = p(σ 3,σ 3 ), by A5 = 1, by A2. PROPOSITION 6. Condition 2 implies that if σ 1.σ 3 is L-false and σ 3 is not L-false then p(σ 1,σ 3 )=0. Proof. Assume Condition 2 holds, σ 1.σ 3 is L-false, and σ 3 is not L-false. Then σ 3 L-implies σ 1 and p(σ 1,σ 3 ) = 1 p( σ 1,σ 3 ), by A3 = 1 1, by Proposition 5 = 0. PROPOSITION 7. Condition 2 implies that p(σ 1,σ 3 )=p(σ 1.σ 3,σ 3 ). Proof. Assume Condition 2 holds. Then p(σ 1,σ 3 ) = p(σ 1,σ 3 )p(σ 3,σ 1.σ 3 ), by Proposition 5 = p(σ 1.σ 3,σ 3 ), by A4. PROPOSITION 8. Condition 2 implies that if σ 1.σ 3 is L-equivalent to σ 2.σ 3 then p(σ 1,σ 3 )=p(σ 2,σ 3 ). coileg.tex; 16/08/2005; 7:16; p.6

Proof. Assume Condition 2 holds and σ 1.σ 3 is L-equivalent to σ 2.σ 3. Then p(σ 1,σ 3 ) = p(σ 1.σ 3,σ 3 ), by Proposition 7 = p(σ 2.σ 3,σ 3 ), by A5 = p(σ 2,σ 3 ), by Proposition 7. PROPOSITION 9. Condition 2 implies that if σ 3 L-implies (σ 1.σ 2 ) and σ 3 is not L-false then p(σ 1 σ 2,σ 3 )=p(σ 1,σ 3 )+p(σ 2,σ 3 ). Proof. Assume Condition 2 holds, σ 3 L-implies (σ 1.σ 2 ), and σ 3 is not L-false. If (σ 1 σ 2 ).σ 3 is not L-false then p(σ 1 σ 2,σ 3 ) = p(σ 1 σ 2,σ 3 )[p(σ 1, (σ 1 σ 2 ).σ 3 )+ p( σ 1, (σ 1 σ 2 ).σ 3 )], by A3 = p((σ 1 σ 2 ).σ 1,σ 3 )+p((σ 1 σ 2 ). σ 1,σ 3 ), by A4 = p(σ 1,σ 3 )+p(σ 2. σ 1,σ 3 ), by A5 = p(σ 1,σ 3 )+p(σ 2,σ 3 ), by Proposition 8. If (σ 1 σ 2 ).σ 3 is L-false then σ 1.σ 3 and σ 2.σ 3 are also L-false and it follows from Proposition 6 that p(σ 1 σ 2,σ 3 )=p(σ 1,σ 3 )=p(σ 2,σ 3 )=0. So in either case, p(σ 1 σ 2,σ 3 )=p(σ 1,σ 3 )+p(σ 2,σ 3 ). PROPOSITION 10. Conditions 2 4 imply Condition 5. Proof. Assume Conditions 2 4 hold. Then p(σ ab,σ ) = p(f a.f b, σ ), by Definition 1 = p(fa,σ )p(f b, F a.σ ), by A4 = 1/3, by Conditions 3 and 4. (3) 7 p(σ a,σ ) = p(f a.gb, σ ), by Definition 1 = p(fa,σ )p(gb, F a.σ ), by A4 = p(fa,σ )p( F b, F a.σ ), by Proposition 8 = p(fa,σ )[1 p(f b, F a.σ )], by A3 = 1/6, by Conditions 3 and 4. (4) p(σ b,σ ) = p(ga.f b, σ ), by Definition 1 = p((fa.fb) (Ga.F b),σ ) p(f a.f b, σ ), coileg.tex; 16/08/2005; 7:16; p.7

8 by Proposition 9 = p(fb,σ ) p(f a.f b, σ ), by Proposition 8 = p(fb,σ ) p(σ ab,σ ), by Definition 1 = 1/6, by Condition 3 and (3). (5) p(σ,σ ) = 1 p( σ,σ ), by A3 = 1 p(σ ab σ a σ b,σ ), by Proposition 8 = 1 p(σ ab,σ ) p(σ a,σ ) p(σ b,σ ), by Proposition 9 = 1/3, by (3), (4), and (5). (6) Identities (3) (6) are what Condition 5 asserts. PROPOSITION 11. Condition 2 implies Condition 6. Proof. Assume Condition 2 holds. If σ 1.σ is L-false then p(σ 1,σ ) = 0, by Proposition 6 = p(σ, σ 1 ), since r(σ 1 )=. σ r(σ 1 ) If σ 1.σ is not L-false then r(σ 1 ). Ifσ 1r is a disjunction of all elements of r(σ 1 ) we then have Thus p(σ 1,σ ) = p(σ 1.σ,σ ), by Proposition 7 = p(σ 1r,σ ), by A5 and Proposition 3 = p(σ, σ ), by Proposition 9. σ r(σ 1 ) p(σ 1,σ )= σ r(σ 1 ) p(σ, σ ) for all sentences σ 1 in L, and in particular for all sentences in L other than σ ab, σ a, σ b, and σ. This is what Condition 6 asserts. PROPOSITION 12. Conditions 2 4 imply Condition 7. Proof. Assume Conditions 2 4 hold. Then p(σ 1.σ 3,σ ) = p(σ 3.σ 1,σ ), by A5 = p(σ 1,σ 3.σ ), by A4 = p(σ 1,σ 3 ), by A5. coileg.tex; 16/08/2005; 7:16; p.8

Hence p(σ 1,σ 3 )= p(σ 1.σ 3,σ ),ifp(σ 3,σ ) 0. (7) Now suppose = 0. Then p(σ, σ ) =, by Proposition 11 σ r(σ 3 ) = 0, by assumption. By Proposition 10 and Definition 2, p(σ, σ ) > 0 for all σ r(σ 3 ), so r(σ 3 )=. Hence σ 3.(σ ab σ a σ b σ ) is L-false. Since σ is L- equivalent to σ ab σ a σ b σ, it follows that σ 3.σ is L-false. Since σ 3 L-implies σ, it follows that σ 3 is L-false. An L-false sentence L- implies every sentence, hence σ 3 L-implies σ 1 and so, by Proposition 5, p(σ 1,σ 3 ) = 1. Thus (7) and (8) together imply Condition 7. p(σ 1,σ 3 ) = 1, if = 0. (8) PROPOSITION 13. Conditions 2 4 imply Conditions 5 7. Proof. Propositions 10, 11, and 12. 9 4.4. Sufficiency This section will show that Conditions 5 7 imply Conditions 2 4. As before, σ 1 and σ 2 are here any sentences in L and σ 3 is any sentence in L that L-implies σ. PROPOSITION 14. Condition 6 implies p(σ 1,σ )= p(σ, σ ). (9) σ r(σ 1 ) Proof. Condition 6 states that (9) holds if σ 1 is not σ ab, σ a, σ b,orσ. If σ 1 is σ ab, σ a, σ b,orσ then r(σ 1 )={σ 1 } and so (9) holds trivially. Hence Condition 6 implies that (9) holds for all σ 1. PROPOSITION 15. Conditions 5 7 imply { } p(σ1.σ 3,σ ) p(σ 1,σ 3 )= p(σ 3,σ ) if 0. (10) 1 if =0 coileg.tex; 16/08/2005; 7:16; p.9

10 Proof. Assume Conditions 5 7. If σ 3 σ then (10) holds by Condition 7. Also p(σ,σ ) = p(σ, σ ), by Proposition 14 σ r(σ ) = p(σ ab,σ )+p(σ a,σ )+p(σ b,σ )+p(σ,σ ), (11) by Definition 2 = 1, by Condition 5. (12) So for the case where σ 3 = σ we have 0 and p(σ 1,σ 3 ) = p(σ 1,σ ), since σ 3 = σ = p(σ, σ ), by Proposition 14 = σ r(σ 1 ) σ r(σ 1.σ ) Hence (10) holds for all σ 1 and σ 3. p(σ, σ ), since r(σ 1.σ )=r(σ 1 ) = p(σ 1.σ,σ ), by Proposition 14 = p(σ 1.σ,σ ), by (12) p(σ,σ ) = p(σ 1.σ 3,σ ), since σ 3 = σ. PROPOSITION 16. Conditions 5 7 imply A1. Proof. Assume Conditions 5 7. If 0 then p(σ 1,σ 3 ) = p(σ 1.σ 3,σ ), by Proposition 15 σ r(σ = 1.σ 3 ) p(σ, σ ) σ r(σ 3 ) p(σ, σ, by Proposition 14 ) 0, by Definition 2 and Condition 5. If = 0 then p(σ 1,σ 3 ) = 1 0, by Proposition 15. Hence p(σ 1,σ 3 ) 0 for all σ 1 and σ 3, which is what A1 asserts. PROPOSITION 17. Conditions 5 7 imply A5. Proof. Assume Conditions 5 7. Let σ 1 and σ 3 be L-equivalent to σ 1 and σ 3 respectively. p(σ 1,σ ) = p(σ, σ ), by Proposition 14 σ r(σ 1 ) coileg.tex; 16/08/2005; 7:16; p.10

= σ r(σ 1 ) p(σ, σ ), since r(σ 1 )=r(σ 1 ) 11 = p(σ 1,σ ), by Proposition 14. (13) If 0 then it follows from (13) that p(σ 3,σ ) 0 and so p(σ 1,σ 3) = p(σ 1.σ 3,σ ) p(σ 3,σ, by Proposition 15 ) = p(σ 1.σ 3,σ ), by (13) = p(σ 1,σ 3 ), by Proposition 15. If = 0 then it follows from (13) that p(σ 3,σ ) = 0 and so p(σ 1,σ 3) = 1, by Proposition 15 = p(σ 1,σ 3 ), by Proposition 15. In either case, p(σ 1,σ 3 )=p(σ 1,σ 3 ), as A5 asserts. PROPOSITION 18. Conditions 5 7 imply A2. Proof. Assume Conditions 5 7. If 0 then p(σ 3,σ 3 ) = p(σ 3.σ 3,σ ), by Proposition 15 = p(σ 3,σ ), by Proposition 17 = 1. If = 0 then p(σ 3,σ 3 ) = 1 by Condition 7. In either case, p(σ 3,σ 3 ) = 1, as A2 asserts. PROPOSITION 19. Conditions 5 7 imply A3. Proof. Assume Conditions 5 7 hold and σ 3 is not L-false. It is a standing assumption that σ 3 L-implies σ,soσ 3.σ is not L-false and hence r(σ 3 ). Thus = p(σ, σ ), by Proposition 14 σ r(σ 3 ) > 0, by Condition 5 and r(σ 3 ). (14) p(σ 1,σ 3 )+p( σ 1,σ 3 ) = p(σ 1.σ 3,σ )+p( σ 1.σ 3,σ ), by (14) and Proposition 15 coileg.tex; 16/08/2005; 7:16; p.11

12 σ r(σ = 1.σ 3 ) p(σ, σ )+ σ r( σ 1.σ 3 ) p(σ, σ ), by Proposition 14 σ r(σ = 3 ) p(σ, σ ), by Proposition 4 = p(σ 3,σ ), by Proposition 14 = 1. This is what A3 asserts. PROPOSITION 20. Conditions 5 7 imply that if σ 1 L-implies σ 2 and p(σ 2,σ )=0then p(σ 1,σ )=0. Proof. Assume Conditions 5 7 hold, σ 1 L-implies σ 2, and p(σ 2,σ )= 0. Then p(σ 1,σ ) = p(σ, σ ), by Proposition 14 σ r(σ 1 ) σ r(σ 2 ) p(σ, σ ), since r(σ 1 ) r(σ 2 ) and p(σ, σ ) > 0 for all σ r(σ 2 ) = p(σ 2,σ ), by Proposition 14 = 0, by assumption. By Proposition 16, p(σ 1,σ ) 0. Hence p(σ 1,σ )=0. PROPOSITION 21. Conditions 5 7 imply A4. Proof. Assume Conditions 5 7. We consider three cases. Case 1: p(σ 1.σ 3,σ ) 0. Then it follows from Proposition 20 that 0 and so p(σ 1.σ 2,σ 3 ) = p((σ 1.σ 2 ).σ 3,σ ), by Proposition 15 = p(σ 2.(σ 1.σ 3 ),σ ), by Proposition 17 = p(σ 1.σ 3,σ ) p(σ 2.(σ 1.σ 3 ),σ ), by arithmetic p(σ 1.σ 3,σ ) = p(σ 1,σ 3 )p(σ 2,σ 1.σ 3 ), by Proposition 15. Case 2: p(σ 1.σ 3,σ ) = 0 and 0. Then p(σ 1.σ 2,σ 3 ) = p((σ 1.σ 2 ).σ 3,σ ), by Proposition 15 coileg.tex; 16/08/2005; 7:16; p.12

13 = 0, by Proposition 20 = 0.p(σ 2,σ 1.σ 3 ), by arithmetic = p(σ 1.σ 3,σ ).p(σ 2,σ 1.σ 3 ), by the assumptions of this case = p(σ 1,σ 3 )p(σ 2,σ 1.σ 3 ), by Proposition 15. so Case 3: = 0. Then p(σ 1.σ 3,σ ) = 0 by Proposition 20 and p(σ 1.σ 2,σ 3 ) = 1, by Proposition 15 = p(σ 1,σ 3 )p(σ 2,σ 1.σ 3 ), by Proposition 15. So in every case, p(σ 1.σ 2,σ 3 )=p(σ 1,σ 3 )p(σ 2,σ 1.σ 3 ), as A4 asserts. PROPOSITION 22. Conditions 5 7 imply Condition 2. Proof. Propositions 16 19 and 21. PROPOSITION 23. Conditions 5 7 imply Condition 3. Proof. Assume Conditions 5 7. Then p(fa,σ ) = p(σ ab σ a,σ ), by Propositions 22 and 8 = p(σ ab,σ )+p(σ a,σ ), by Propositions 22 and 9 = 1/2, by Condition 5. Similarly, p(fb,σ )=p(σ ab,σ )+p(σ b,σ )=1/2. PROPOSITION 24. Conditions 5 7 imply Condition 4. Proof. Assume Conditions 5 7. Then p(f a.σ,σ ) = p(fa,σ ), by Propositions 22 and 8 = 1/2, by Proposition 23. (15) So p(f b, F a.σ ) = p(fb.(f a.σ ),σ ), by Proposition 15 p(f a.σ,σ ) = 2p(Fb.(F a.σ ),σ ), by (15) = 2p(F a.f b, σ ), by Propositions 22 and 8 = 2p(σ ab,σ ), by Definition 1 = 2/3, by Condition 5. PROPOSITION 25. Conditions 5 7 imply Conditions 2 4. coileg.tex; 16/08/2005; 7:16; p.13

14 Proof. Propositions 22 24. This completes the proof that I outlined at the beginning of Section 4. References Carnap, R.: 1950, Logical Foundations of Probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Second edition 1962. Maher, P.: 2004, Probability Captures the Logic of Scientific Confirmation. In: C. R. Hitchcock (ed.): Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Science. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 69 93. Maher, P.: 2006, A Conception of Inductive Logic. Presented at PSA 2004 and forthcoming in Philosophy of Science. coileg.tex; 16/08/2005; 7:16; p.14