Cardinals. Y = n Y n. Define h: X Y by f(x) if x X n X n+1 and n is even h(x) = g
|
|
- Σοφοκλής Καλλιγάς
- 7 χρόνια πριν
- Προβολές:
Transcript
1 Cardinals 1. Introduction to Cardinals We work in the base theory ZF. The definitions and many (but not all) of the basic theorems do not require AC; we will indicate explicitly when we are using choice. Definition 1.1. For sets X, Y, we write X Y to mean there is a one-to-one function from X to Y. We write X Y to mean there is a bijection from X to Y. Theorem 1.2. (Cantor-Schröder-Bernstein) If X Y and Y X then X Y. Proof. Let f : X Y and g : Y X be one-to-one. Let X 0 = X, Y 0 = Y and define recursively X n = g(y n 1 ), Y n = f(x n 1 ) for n 1. Thus, X 0 = X, X 1 = g(y ), X 2 = g f(x), X 3 = g f g(y ), etc., and similarly for the Y n. Note that X 0 X 1 X 2..., and Y 0 Y 1 Y Let X = n X n, Y = n Y n. Define h: X Y by f(x) if x X n X n+1 and n is even h(x) = g 1 (x) if x X n X n+1 and n is odd f(x) if x X Easily h is a bijection between X n X n+2 = (X n X n+1 ) (X n+1 X n+2 ) and Y n Y n+2 = (Y n Y n+1 ) (Y n+1 Y n+2 ) for any even n, as f bijects (X n X n+1 ) and (Y n+1 Y n+2 ) and g 1 bijects (X n+1 X n+2 ) and (Y n Y n+1 ). Thus, h is a bijection between X X and Y Y. It is easy to also see that f induces a bijection from X to Y, and thus h is a bijection from X to Y. Note that the above proof did not use AC. Definition 1.3. κ is a cardinal if κ ON and α < κ (α κ). Note that this definition is easily formalized into set-theory, and thus the collection of cardinals is a class. Also, note that AC is not used in the definition of cardinal. We frequently use κ, λ, µ for cardianls. If α ON, we let α denote the least ordinal β such that β α. Clearly α is a cardinal. Also, α α. Again, AC is not needed to define α for α ON. We refer to α as the cardinality of α. Exercise 1. Show that every n ω, (n + 1 n). Make sure you are giving a real proof from within ZF; in particular, you are using only the official definition of integer. Exercise 2. Show that every n ω is a cardinal, and ω is a cardinal. We define addition and multiplication on the cardinals. Note that these are different operations that those defined on the ordinals. Thus, when we write κ λ, it needs to be specified (or be clear from the context) whether we are talking about multiplication as ordinals or as cardinals. Definition 1.4. for cardinals κ, λ: (1) κ + λ = (κ {0}) (λ {1}) (2) κ λ = κ λ 1
2 2 Note that κ+λ is just the cardinality of the ordinals sum of κ and λ, and likewise for multiplication. Thus, these operations are clearly associative (also trivial to show directly). They are also clearly commutative, unlike the ordinal operations. Lemma 1.5. Any infinite cardinal is a limit ordinal. Proof. If κ is an infinite cardinal and κ = α + 1, then α is also infinite. However, if α is an infinite ordinal then α = 1 + α α + 1 and so κ = α, a contradiction. Exercise 3. Show that for any cardinals κ, λ that κ + λ = max{κ, λ}. [hint: Say λ κ. Prove by induction on β ON that if α β and γ is the mingling of α and β according to x η < y η < x η+1 (here γ is the order-type of X Y, and the x η, y η enumerate X, Y respectively), then γ β + n for some n ω if β is a successor, and γ β if β is a limit]. Using AC, we can the notion of cardinality of an arbitrary set. Definition 1.6. (ZFC) Let X denote the least ordinal α such that α X. Using AC, this definition is well-defined, as every set X can be well-ordered, and thus put into bijection with an ordinal. Clearly the least such ordinal, namely X, is a cardinal. Exercise 4. Using AC, give another proof of the Cantor-Schröder-Bernstein theorem. (hint: First identify X, Y with cardinals, say κ, λ. Without loss of generality, κ < λ. Show, without using Cantor-Schröder-Bernstein, that if there were a oneto-one map from λ to κ, then κ λ, a contradiction. Use the previous exercise.) The next result shows that for infinite cardinals κ, λ, κ λ = max{κ, λ}, and thus addition and multiplication on the infinite cardinals coincide. Theorem 1.7. If κ is an infinite cardinal, then κ κ = κ. Proof. We prove this by induction on κ. Consider the following ordering (Gödel ordering) on κ κ: (α, β) (α, β ) max{α, β} < max{α, β } [(max{α, β} = max{α, β }) (α, β) < lex (α, β )]. This is easily a well-order of κ κ. For each (α, β) κ κ, the initial segment of this order determined by (α, β) is in bijection with a subset of max{α, β} max{α, β} which by induction has cardinality at most max{α, β} < κ. Thus, the ordering has length at most κ. Note again that the above theorem, which completely characterizes addition and multiplication on the infinite cardinals, is proved without AC. The next lemma generalizes theorem 1.7, but now requires the axiom of choice. Theorem 1.8. (ZFC) Let κ CARD. Let X = α<κ X α, where X α κ for all α < κ. Then X κ. Proof. Using AC, let f be a function with domain κ such that for all α < κ, f(α): κ X α is a bijection. Define F : κ κ X by F (α, β) = f(α)(β). Clearly F is onto, and the result follws by lemma 1.7. Exercise 5. Show that R = ω ω = 2 ω.
3 3 Definition 1.9. We say a set X is finite if X < ω, we say X is countable if X ω. Exercise 6. Show that Z, Q, and the set of algebraic numbers are countable. Show that the set of formulas is the language of set theory is countable. To show that there is any uncountable cardinal requires the power set axiom (this can be stated as a precise theorem; will mention later). Armed with the power set axiom, however, the following is a basic result. Theorem (Cantor) For any set X, there does not exist a map from X onto P(X). In particular, (X P(X)). Proof. Suppose f : X P(X) were onto. Define A X by A = {x X : x / f(x)}. Since A P(X), let a X be such that f(a) = A. Then a f(a) a A a / f(a), a contradiction. With the axiom of choice it follows that for all cardinals κ that P(κ) has cardinality greater than κ, and thus a cardinal greater than κ exists. We would like to get this without the axiom of choice. To do this, fix a cardinal κ, and let W κ = {S P(κ κ): S is a well-ordering }. Note the use of the power set axiom here. Using the replacement axiom, let A = {α ON: S W κ (o.t.(s) = α)}. Then A ON, in fact, A is easily a limit ordinal so A = A. First note that is α < A then α = κ since by definition α = o.t.(s) where S is a well-ordering of a subset of κ. Since any well-ordering of κ clearly has an order-type which is bijection with κ, we get that α < A ( α κ). Next we claim that A > κ. For suppose f : κ A were a bijection. Let be the corresponding well-ordering of κ defined by γ δ f(γ) < f(δ). F itself is an order-isomorphism between (κ, ) and (A ), and so o.t.( ) = A. This is a contradiction, since A is a limit (i.e., we can easily now define a well-order of length A + 1). We have thus shown in ZF the following: Lemma For each cardinal κ there is a cardinal greater than κ. The following definition is therefore well-defined in ZF. Definition For κ a cardinal, we let κ + denote the least cardinal greater than κ. Lemma If A CARD, then sup(a) CARD. Proof. Let µ = sup(a). Let α < µ. Let κ A be such that alpha < κ. Since κ is a cardinal, there does not exist a one-to-one map from κ into α. Since κ µ, there does not therefore exist a one-to-one map from µ into α. So, α < µ ( α = µ) and µ is thus a cardinal. We can now describe the general picture of the cardinals. We define by transfinite recursion on the ordinals for each α ON the cardinal ℵ α which is also denoted ω α. Definition ω α is defined by transfinite recursion by: (1) ω 0 = ω (2) ω α+1 = (ω α ) + (3) For α limit, ω α = sup β<α ω β.
4 4 Theorem ω α is defined for all α ON and is a cardinal. Furthermore, every cardinal is of the form ω α for some α ON. Proof. That ω α is well-defined and a cardinal follows from the transfinite recursion theorem and lemmas 1.11, Suppose κ CARD. Let α ON be least such that ω α κ. This is well-defined since a trivial induction gives ω β β for all β ON. If α = β + 1 is a successor, then ω β < κ and so ω α = (ω β ) + κ, and thus ω α = κ. If α is a limit, then ω α = sup β<α ω β κ as each ω β for β < α is < κ. So again ω α = κ. Finally in this section we introduce cardinal exponentiation. Definition For α, β ON, let α β = {f : f is a function from α to β}. For κ, λ cardinals, let κ λ = λ κ. Let κ <λ = sup α<λ κ α. Note that we need AC to discuss κ λ, and we henceforth assume AC in discussions where cardinal exponentiation is involved. The following easy lemma says that the familiar exponent rules apply to cardinal exponentiation. Lemma For κ, λ, σ cardinals we have κ λ+σ = κ λ κ σ, (κ λ ) σ = κ λ σ. Proof. This follows from the following facts about sets A, B, C: 1) If B C =, then there is an obvious bijection between (B C) A and B A C A. 2.) There is an obvious bijection between C ( B A) and (C B) A. Here is one easy computation: Lemma If 2 κ λ are cardinals, then κ λ = 2 λ. Proof. Clearly κ λ 2 λ. Also, 2 λ (2 κ ) λ = 2 κ λ = 2 λ. We also have the following easy basic fact. Lemma For all cardinals κ, 2 κ = P(κ). Proof. This follows immediately from the { fact that we may identify any A P(κ) 1 if α A with its characteristic function f A (α) = 0 if α / A. So by Cantor s theorem we have that 2 κ > κ for all cardinals κ. Exactly how big is 2 κ? More generally, how do we compute κ λ? We will turn to these questions shortly, but first we introduce some terminology. Definition The continuum hypothesis, CH, is the assertion that 2 ω = ω 1. The generalized continuum hypothesis, GCH, is the assertion that 2 ωα = ω α+1 for all α ON. Exercise 7. Show that there are 2 2ω functions from R to R. Show that there are 2 ω many continuous functions from R to R. Exercise 8. Let X be a second countable space. Show that there are 2 ω open (likewise for closed) subsets of X. Show that there are 2 ω many Borel subsets of X. Exercise 9. Let f : ω 1 R be an ω 1 sequence of reals. Show that for some α 0 < α 1 < α 2 <... we have f(α 0 ) > f(α 1 ) > f(α 2 ) >... (here we mean in the usual ordering on the reals).
5 5 2. Cofinality The following is a basic, important definition. Definition 2.1. Let α be a limit ordinal. Then cof(α) is the least ordinal β such that there is a function f : β α which is unbounded (also said to be cofinal) in α. That is, α < α β < β (f(β) α ). Clearly cof(α) α and is an infinite limit ordinal. Definition 2.2. An ordinal α is said to be regular if cof(α) = α. Otherwise α is said to be singular. Sometimes the convention is made that for α a successor that cof(α) = 1, but we generally only refer to cof(α) when α is a limit. Lemma 2.3. Let α be a limit ordinal. Then there is an increasing map f : cof(α) α which is cofinal. Proof. Let g : cof(α) α be cofinal. Define f by f(β) = max{g(β), sup f(γ) + 1}. γ<β Thus, cofinalities are always witnessed by strictly increasing maps. The next fact is a sort of converse to this. Lemma 2.4. If α, β are limit ordinals and f : α β is cofinal and monotonically increasing (i.e., if α 1 < α 2 then f(α 1 ) f(α 2 )), then cof(α) = cof(β). Proof. If g : cof(α) α is cofinal, then f g : cof(α) β is cofinal, so cof(β) cof(α). Suppose h: cof(β) β is increasing, cofinal. Define k : cof(β) α by k(γ) = least η such that f(η) > g(γ). This is well-defined, and easily cofinal into α. Thus, cof(α) cof(β). Lemma 2.5. If α is a limit ordinal, then cof(α) is a regular cardinal. Proof. We have already observed that cof(α) is an infinite limit ordinal. We have cof(α) regular, that is, cof(cof(α)) = cof(α) as otherwise by composing functions (as in lemma 2.4) we would have a cofinal map from cof(cof(α)) to α. It remains to observe that a regular ordinal is necessarily a cardinal. Suppose β is a regular limit ordinal, but κ = β < β. Let f : κ β be a bijection. In particular, f is cofinal, so cof(β) κ < β, a contradiction. Thus, cof(cof(α)) = cof(α) for all (limit) α. The above lemmas did not use AC. The next lemma does use AC, and can fail without it. Lemma 2.6. (ZFC) For every cardinal κ, κ + is regular. Proof. If not, then there would be a cofinal map f : λ κ, where λ κ. This would write κ + as a κ union of sets, each of which size κ. This contradicts theorem 1.8. Thus, in ZFC all successor cardinals are regular. What about limit cardinals? (note: by limit cardinal we mean a cardinal not of the form κ +. Of course, all infinite cardinals are limit ordinals.) The next lemma computes the cofinality of a limit cardinal.
6 6 Lemma 2.7. Let ω α be a limit cardinal. Then α is a limit ordinal and cof(ω α ) = cof(α). Proof. Clearly α must be a limit ordinal as otherwise ω α would be a successor cardianl. The map β ω β is increasing and cofinal from α to ω α, so by lemma 2.4 it follows that cof(ω α ) = cof(α). Examples. ω is regular. Assuming ZFC, so are ω 1, ω 2,..., ω n,.... ω ω is singular of cofinality ω. All limit cardinals below ω ω1 are singular of cofinality ω. ω ω1 is singular of cofinality ω 1. ω (ωω2 +ω 1) is singular of cofinality ω 1, while cof(ω ωω2 ) = ω 2. All the limit cardinals mentioned above are singular. Are there any regular limit cardinals? We will see that this question is independent of ZFC (in fact, the existence of such cardinals has a stronger consistency strength than ZFC). For now, we make this into a definition. Definition 2.8. κ is weakly inaccessible if κ is a regular limit cardinal. κ is strongly inaccessible if κ is regular and λ < κ (2 λ < κ). κ is a strong limit cardinal if λ < κ (2 λ < κ). Exercise 10. Assuming GCH, identify the strong limit cardinals, and show that κ is weakly inaccessible iff κ is strongly inaccessible. We end this section with a basic result on cardinal arithmetic. Theorem 2.9. (König) For every infinite cardinal κ, κ cof(κ) > κ. Proof. Let f : cof(κ) κ be cofinal. Suppose {g α } α<κ enumerated (cof(κ)) κ. Define g (cof(κ)) κ by g(β) = the least element of κ {g α (β): β < f(β)}. Clearly g g α for any α, a contradiction. Corollary For every infinite cardinal κ, cof(2 κ ) > κ. cof(κ λ ) > λ. More generally, Proof. Since (κ λ ) λ = κ λ, theorem 2.9 gives that cof(κ λ ) must be greater than λ. We can also state König s theorem in a slightly more general form. First, we define the infinitary sum and products operations. Definition If {κ α } α<δ is a sequence of cardinals, we define α<δ κ α to be the cardinality of the disjoint union of sets X α, α < δ, where X α = κ α. We define α<δ κ α to the cardinality of the functions f with domain δ such that f(α) κ α for all α < δ. Exercise 11. Show that α<δ κ α = δ sup α<δ (κ α ). The same diagonal argument used in theorem 2.9 also shows the following. Theorem (König) Let κ α < λ α for all α < δ. Then α<δ κ α < α<δ λ α. Proof. Let X α α<δ λ α, for α < δ, and X α = κ α. We must show that α<δ X α α<δ λ α. For each α < δ, let f(α) be an element of λ α which is not in {g(α): g X α }. This exists since X α = κ α < λ α. Clearly, g / α<δ X α. Note that theorem 2.12 implies theorem 2.9 by taking κ α = κ for all α < δ = cof(κ).
7 7 3. Cardinal Arithmetic Under the GCH Assuming ZFC + GCH we can readily compute κ λ for all κ and λ. Theorem 3.1. Assume ZFC + GCH. Let κ be an infinite cardinal. Then: (1) If λ < cof(κ), then κ λ = κ. (2) If cof(κ) λ κ, then κ λ = κ +. (3) If λ > κ then κ λ = λ +. Proof. If λ < cof(κ), then any function f : λ κ has bounded range. Thus, κ λ = α<κ αλ. Also, α λ 2 max(α,λ) κ since α, λ < κ, using the GCH. If cof(κ) λ κ, then κ λ κ by theorem 2.9. Also, κ λ κ κ = κ + by GCH. If λ > κ, then κ λ 2 λ = λ +. Also, clearly κ λ 2 λ = λ Cardinal Arithmetic in General We discuss now some properties of cardinal arithmetic assuming only ZFC. We only scratch the surface here, aiming toward one specific result. We first introduce two cardinal functions. Definition 4.1. The beth function ℶ α is defined for α ON by recursion on α as follows: ℶ 0 = ω, ℶ α+1 = 2 ℶα, and for α limit, ℶ α = sup β<α ℶ β. Definition 4.2. The gimel function ג α is defined by ( κ )ג = κ cof(κ), for all cardinals κ. Exercise 12. Show that ( κ )ג > κ and cof(ג(κ)) > cof(κ). We now show that cardinal exponentiation is determined etirely from the gimel function and the cofinality function. From these two functions we compute κ λ by induction on κ as follows. Theorem 4.3. For all infinite cardinals κ, λ we have: (1) If λ κ then κ λ = 2 λ. (2) If for some µ < κ we have µ λ κ, then κ λ = µ λ. (3) If for all µ < κ we have µ λ < κ, then: If λ < cof(κ) then κ λ = κ. If cof(κ) λ < κ, then κ λ =.( κ )ג Proof. (1) is clear, and (2) follows from κ λ (µ λ ) λ = µ λ. The first case of (3) follows from the fact that κ λ = sup µ<κ µ λ = κ from the assumption of the case. For the second case of (3), clearly we have κ λ κ cof(κ) =.( κ )ג The upper bound follows from the following lemma. Lemma 4.4. If λ cof(κ), then κ λ = (sup α<κ α λ ) cof(κ). Proof. Fix a cofinal map h: cof(κ) κ. To each f : λ κ, and each β < cof(κ) we associate a partial function f β : λ h(β). Namely, let f β = f (λ h(β)). The map f (f β ) β<cof(κ) is clearly a one-to-one map from κ λ to (sup α<κ α λ ) cof(κ). The next lemma gives somes information about the continuum function at singular cardinals. Lemma 4.5. Let κ be a singular cardinal and suppose the continuum function below κ is eventually constant, that is, there is a γ < κ such that 2 <κ = 2 γ. Then 2 κ = 2 γ.
8 8 Proof. An argument similar to lemma 4.4 shows that for any κ we have 2 κ (2 <κ ) cof(κ), and hence easily 2 κ = (2 <κ ) cof(κ). Thus, 2 κ = (2 <κ ) cof(κ) = (2 γ ) cof(κ) = (2 δ ) cof(κ) = 2 δ = 2 γ, where γ < δ < κ and δ cof(κ). We thus have the following theorem, which shows that the continuum function can be computed entirely from the gimel function. Theorem 4.6. For any cardinal κ: (1) If κ is a successor cardinal, then 2 κ =.( κ )ג (2) If κ is a limit cardinal and the continuum below κ is eventually constant, then 2 κ = 2 <κ.( κ )ג (3) If κ is a limit cardinal and the continuum below κ is not eventually constant, then 2 κ = 2 )ג <κ ). Proof. The first part is clear as successor cardinals are regular. Suppose that κ is a limit cardinal, and the continuum function is eventually constant below κ, say 2 <κ = 2 γ. If κ is singular, then 2 κ = 2 γ by the previous lemma. If κ is regular, then 2 κ = κ κ = κ cof(κ) =.( κ )ג In the singular case, note that 2 γ = 2 <κ κ. Thus, Thus, ( κ )ג = κ cof(κ) (2 γ ) cof(κ) = (2 δ ) cof(κ) = 2 δ = 2 γ (where cof(κ) < δ < κ). 2 <κ ( κ )ג = 2 <κ. If κ is regular, then 2 <κ 2 κ = κ κ =.( κ )ג So, 2 <κ ( κ )ג =.( κ )ג In either case, 2 κ = 2 <κ.( κ )ג Finally, suppose κ is a limit cardinal and the continuum function below κ is not eventually constant. Then cof(2 <κ ) = cof(κ). Then 2 κ = (2 <κ ) cof(κ) = 2 )ג <κ ). Note that if κ is a strong limit cardinal (i.e., 2 <κ = κ) then 2 κ =,( κ )ג so the continuum function and gimel function coincide in the main case of interest. What can be said about the value of 2 κ or ( κ )ג in general? We shall see that if κ is regular, then nothing more can be said that 2 κ > κ and cof(2 κ ) > κ (and of course if κ 1 < κ 2 then 2 κ1 2 κ2 ). So, for κ regular, 2 κ = ( κ )ג is basically arbitrary subject to Cantor s and König s theorems. If κ is a singular limit cardinal, the situation is much more difficult. Here there are restrictions on 2 κ. For now, let s just observe one more fact about the gimel function. Note that if there is a λ < κ such that λ cof(κ) κ, then ( κ )ג = λ cof(κ), and so is computed by exponentiation on smaller cardinals. Exercise 13. Suppose κ is a singular limit cardinal. Suppose there is a λ < κ such that λ cof(κ) κ, and let λ be the least such. Show that cof(λ) cof(κ). More generally, if there is a λ < κ with cof(λ) cof(κ) and ( λ )ג κ, then.( λ )ג = cof(λ) ( κ )ג = κ cof(κ) λ cof(λ) cof(κ) = λ Finally, suppose κ is a singular limit cardinal and there is no λ < κ such that λ cof(κ) κ. We claim that cof(ג(κ)) the the least α such that λ α κ for some λ < κ. For suppose λ α < κ for all λ < κ, we show that cof(ג(κ)) > α. Then cof(κ). cof(ג(κ)) ( κ )ג α = κ cof(κ) α. We may assume α cof(κ) as we know that Thus, ( κ )ג α = κ α = (sup λ<κ λ α ) cof(κ) = κ cof(κ) =.( κ )ג Thus, cof(ג(κ)) > α by König. We have thus shown: Lemma 4.7. Suppose κ is a singular strong limit cardinal. Then cof(ג(κ)) > κ.
Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit
Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit Ting Zhang Stanford May 11, 2001 Stanford, 5/11/2001 1 Outline Ordinal Classification Ordinal Addition Ordinal Multiplication Ordinal
Διαβάστε περισσότερα2 Composition. Invertible Mappings
Arkansas Tech University MATH 4033: Elementary Modern Algebra Dr. Marcel B. Finan Composition. Invertible Mappings In this section we discuss two procedures for creating new mappings from old ones, namely,
Διαβάστε περισσότεραEvery set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set
Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set May 6, 2008 Abstract A set of first-order formulas, whatever the cardinality of the set of symbols, is equivalent to an independent
Διαβάστε περισσότεραChapter 3: Ordinal Numbers
Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers There are two kinds of number.. Ordinal numbers (0th), st, 2nd, 3rd, 4th, 5th,..., ω, ω +,... ω2, ω2+,... ω 2... answers to the question What position is... in a sequence? What
Διαβάστε περισσότεραORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER
ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER Abstract. We define ordinal arithmetic and show laws of Left- Monotonicity, Associativity, Distributivity, some minor related properties and the Cantor Normal Form.
Διαβάστε περισσότεραFractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs
Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs Who? Nichole Schimanski When? July 27, 2011 Graphs A graph, G, consists of a vertex set, V (G), and an edge set, E(G). V (G) is any finite set E(G) is
Διαβάστε περισσότεραC.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions
C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions Paul Liu November 15, 2007 Note that these are sample solutions only; in many cases there were many acceptable answers. 1 Reynolds Problem 10.1 1.1 Normal-order
Διαβάστε περισσότεραA Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation
International Mathematical Forum, 5, 2010, no. 67, 3301-3307 A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy Equivalence Relation D. K. Basnet Dept. of Mathematics, Assam University Silchar-788011, Assam, India dkbasnet@rediffmail.com
Διαβάστε περισσότεραExample Sheet 3 Solutions
Example Sheet 3 Solutions. i Regular Sturm-Liouville. ii Singular Sturm-Liouville mixed boundary conditions. iii Not Sturm-Liouville ODE is not in Sturm-Liouville form. iv Regular Sturm-Liouville note
Διαβάστε περισσότεραHomework 3 Solutions
Homework 3 Solutions Igor Yanovsky (Math 151A TA) Problem 1: Compute the absolute error and relative error in approximations of p by p. (Use calculator!) a) p π, p 22/7; b) p π, p 3.141. Solution: For
Διαβάστε περισσότεραω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 ω ω + 1 ω + 2 ω + 3 ω + 4 ω2 ω2 + 1 ω2 + 2 ω2 + 3 ω3 ω3 + 1 ω3 + 2 ω4 ω4 + 1 ω5 ω 2 ω 2 + 1 ω 2 + 2 ω 2 + ω ω 2 + ω + 1 ω 2 + ω2 ω 2 2 ω 2 2 + 1 ω 2 2 + ω ω 2 3 ω 3 ω 3 + 1 ω 3 + ω ω 3 +
Διαβάστε περισσότεραST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II
ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II 2014/2015: Semester II Tutorial 7 1. Let X be a sample from a population P and consider testing hypotheses H 0 : P = P 0 versus H 1 : P = P 1, where P j is a known
Διαβάστε περισσότερα2. Let H 1 and H 2 be Hilbert spaces and let T : H 1 H 2 be a bounded linear operator. Prove that [T (H 1 )] = N (T ). (6p)
Uppsala Universitet Matematiska Institutionen Andreas Strömbergsson Prov i matematik Funktionalanalys Kurs: F3B, F4Sy, NVP 2005-03-08 Skrivtid: 9 14 Tillåtna hjälpmedel: Manuella skrivdon, Kreyszigs bok
Διαβάστε περισσότεραEE512: Error Control Coding
EE512: Error Control Coding Solution for Assignment on Finite Fields February 16, 2007 1. (a) Addition and Multiplication tables for GF (5) and GF (7) are shown in Tables 1 and 2. + 0 1 2 3 4 0 0 1 2 3
Διαβάστε περισσότεραChapter 2. Ordinals, well-founded relations.
Chapter 2. Ordinals, well-founded relations. 2.1. Well-founded Relations. We start with some definitions and rapidly reach the notion of a well-ordered set. Definition. For any X and any binary relation
Διαβάστε περισσότεραConcrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016
Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016 Silvio Capobianco Exercise 1.7 Let H(n) = J(n + 1) J(n). Equation (1.8) tells us that H(2n) = 2, and H(2n+1) = J(2n+2) J(2n+1) = (2J(n+1) 1) (2J(n)+1)
Διαβάστε περισσότερα4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1)
84 CHAPTER 4. STATIONARY TS MODELS 4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(,) This section is an introduction to a wide class of models ARMA(p,q) which we will consider in more detail later in this
Διαβάστε περισσότεραNowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in
Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in : tail in X, head in A nowhere-zero Γ-flow is a Γ-circulation such that
Διαβάστε περισσότεραOn density of old sets in Prikry type extensions.
On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions. Moti Gitik December 31, 2015 Abstract Every set of ordinals of cardinality κ in a Prikry extension with a measure over κ contains an old set of arbitrary
Διαβάστε περισσότεραUniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor
Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor Given f L 1 T 1 ), we consider the partial sums of the Fourier series of f: N 1) S N fθ) = ˆfk)e ikθ. k= N A calculation gives the Dirichlet formula
Διαβάστε περισσότεραKnaster-Reichbach Theorem for 2 κ
Knaster-Reichbach Theorem for 2 κ Micha l Korch February 9, 2018 In the recent years the theory of the generalized Cantor and Baire spaces was extensively developed (see, e.g. [1], [2], [6], [4] and many
Διαβάστε περισσότεραSection 8.3 Trigonometric Equations
99 Section 8. Trigonometric Equations Objective 1: Solve Equations Involving One Trigonometric Function. In this section and the next, we will exple how to solving equations involving trigonometric functions.
Διαβάστε περισσότεραFinite Field Problems: Solutions
Finite Field Problems: Solutions 1. Let f = x 2 +1 Z 11 [x] and let F = Z 11 [x]/(f), a field. Let Solution: F =11 2 = 121, so F = 121 1 = 120. The possible orders are the divisors of 120. Solution: The
Διαβάστε περισσότεραMath 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequality for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x, y, z X.
Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequalit for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x,, z X. Prove that d(x, z) d(, z) d(x, ). (ii): Reverse triangle inequalit for norms:
Διαβάστε περισσότεραLecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic
Lecture 2 Soundness and completeness of propositional logic February 9, 2004 1 Overview Review of natural deduction. Soundness and completeness. Semantics of propositional formulas. Soundness proof. Completeness
Διαβάστε περισσότεραSOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS
Sahand Communications in Mathematical Analysis (SCMA) Vol. 3 No. 1 (2016), 21-27 http://scma.maragheh.ac.ir SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS BAYAZ DARABY 1 AND JAVAD JAFARI 2 Abstract. In the mathematical
Διαβάστε περισσότεραChapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval
Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential Equations Let a (t), a 2 (t),..., a nn (t), b (t), b 2 (t),..., b n (t) be continuous functions on the interval I. The system of n first-order differential equations
Διαβάστε περισσότεραLecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics
Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics Nov 1, 01 In this lecture we examine root systems from an axiomatic point of view. 1 Reflections If v R n, then it determines a hyperplane, denoted P v, through the
Διαβάστε περισσότεραSplitting stationary sets from weak forms of Choice
Splitting stationary sets from weak forms of Choice Paul Larson and Saharon Shelah February 16, 2008 Abstract Working in the context of restricted forms of the Axiom of Choice, we consider the problem
Διαβάστε περισσότεραStatistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests
Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests Shirsendu Mukherjee Department of Statistics, Asutosh College, Kolkata, India. shirsendu st@yahoo.co.in So far we have treated the testing of one-sided
Διαβάστε περισσότερα1. Introduction and Preliminaries.
Faculty of Sciences and Mathematics, University of Niš, Serbia Available at: http://www.pmf.ni.ac.yu/filomat Filomat 22:1 (2008), 97 106 ON δ SETS IN γ SPACES V. Renuka Devi and D. Sivaraj Abstract We
Διαβάστε περισσότεραk A = [k, k]( )[a 1, a 2 ] = [ka 1,ka 2 ] 4For the division of two intervals of confidence in R +
Chapter 3. Fuzzy Arithmetic 3- Fuzzy arithmetic: ~Addition(+) and subtraction (-): Let A = [a and B = [b, b in R If x [a and y [b, b than x+y [a +b +b Symbolically,we write A(+)B = [a (+)[b, b = [a +b
Διαβάστε περισσότεραPhys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required)
Phys460.nb 81 ψ n (t) is still the (same) eigenstate of H But for tdependent H. The answer is NO. 5.5.5. Solution for the tdependent Schrodinger s equation If we assume that at time t 0, the electron starts
Διαβάστε περισσότεραMINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS
MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS FUMIE NAKAOKA AND NOBUYUKI ODA Received 20 December 2005; Revised 28 May 2006; Accepted 6 August 2006 Some properties of minimal closed sets and maximal closed
Διαβάστε περισσότεραMatrices and Determinants
Matrices and Determinants SUBJECTIVE PROBLEMS: Q 1. For what value of k do the following system of equations possess a non-trivial (i.e., not all zero) solution over the set of rationals Q? x + ky + 3z
Διαβάστε περισσότεραCongruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2
International Journal of Algebra, Vol. 8, 24, no. 5, 239-246 HIKARI Ltd, www.m-hikari.com http://dx.doi.org/.2988/ija.24.422 Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2 Ligong An and
Διαβάστε περισσότερα3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β
3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS Page Theorem cos(αβ cos α cos β -sin α cos(α-β cos α cos β sin α NOTE: cos(αβ cos α cos β cos(α-β cos α -cos β Proof of cos(α-β cos α cos β sin α Let s use a unit circle
Διαβάστε περισσότεραderivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates
derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates swapnizzle 03-03- :5:43 We begin by recognizing the familiar conversion from rectangular to spherical coordinates (note that φ is used
Διαβάστε περισσότεραHomomorphism in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Automata
International Journal of Fuzzy Mathematics Systems. ISSN 2248-9940 Volume 3, Number 1 (2013), pp. 39-45 Research India Publications http://www.ripublication.com/ijfms.htm Homomorphism in Intuitionistic
Διαβάστε περισσότεραSINGULAR CARDINALS AND SQUARE PROPERTIES
SINGULAR CARDINALS AND SQUARE PROPERTIES MENACHEM MAGIDOR AND DIMA SINAPOVA Abstract. We analyze the effect of singularizing cardinals on square properties. By work of Džamonja-Shelah and of Gitik, if
Διαβάστε περισσότεραProblem Set 3: Solutions
CMPSCI 69GG Applied Information Theory Fall 006 Problem Set 3: Solutions. [Cover and Thomas 7.] a Define the following notation, C I p xx; Y max X; Y C I p xx; Ỹ max I X; Ỹ We would like to show that C
Διαβάστε περισσότεραSolutions to Exercise Sheet 5
Solutions to Eercise Sheet 5 jacques@ucsd.edu. Let X and Y be random variables with joint pdf f(, y) = 3y( + y) where and y. Determine each of the following probabilities. Solutions. a. P (X ). b. P (X
Διαβάστε περισσότεραSome new generalized topologies via hereditary classes. Key Words:hereditary generalized topological space, A κ(h,µ)-sets, κµ -topology.
Bol. Soc. Paran. Mat. (3s.) v. 30 2 (2012): 71 77. c SPM ISSN-2175-1188 on line ISSN-00378712 in press SPM: www.spm.uem.br/bspm doi:10.5269/bspm.v30i2.13793 Some new generalized topologies via hereditary
Διαβάστε περισσότεραOther Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests
Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests Side-Note: So far we have seen a few approaches for creating tests such as Neyman-Pearson Lemma ( most powerful tests of H 0 : θ = θ 0 vs H 1 :
Διαβάστε περισσότεραPractice Exam 2. Conceptual Questions. 1. State a Basic identity and then verify it. (a) Identity: Solution: One identity is csc(θ) = 1
Conceptual Questions. State a Basic identity and then verify it. a) Identity: Solution: One identity is cscθ) = sinθ) Practice Exam b) Verification: Solution: Given the point of intersection x, y) of the
Διαβάστε περισσότεραInverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations. ------------------ ----------------------------- -----------------
Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations. 1. Sin ( ) = a) b) c) d) Ans b. Solution : Method 1. Ans a: 17 > 1 a) is rejected. w.k.t Sin ( sin ) = d is rejected. If sin
Διαβάστε περισσότεραEcon 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1
Eon : Fall 8 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 Email questions or omments to Dan Fetter Problem. Let X be a salar with density f(x, θ) (θx + θ) [ x ] with θ. (a) Find the most powerful level α test
Διαβάστε περισσότεραReminders: linear functions
Reminders: linear functions Let U and V be vector spaces over the same field F. Definition A function f : U V is linear if for every u 1, u 2 U, f (u 1 + u 2 ) = f (u 1 ) + f (u 2 ), and for every u U
Διαβάστε περισσότεραSCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES G11LMA Linear Mathematics Examination Solutions
SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES GLMA Linear Mathematics 00- Examination Solutions. (a) i. ( + 5i)( i) = (6 + 5) + (5 )i = + i. Real part is, imaginary part is. (b) ii. + 5i i ( + 5i)( + i) = ( i)( + i)
Διαβάστε περισσότεραBounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees
Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees Thomas F. Kent Andrea Sorbi Università degli Studi di Siena Italia July 18, 2007 Goal: Introduce a form of Σ 0 2-permitting for the enumeration degrees. Till now,
Διαβάστε περισσότεραANSWERSHEET (TOPIC = DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION #2. h 0 h h 0 h h 0 ( ) g k = g 0 + g 1 + g g 2009 =?
Teko Classes IITJEE/AIEEE Maths by SUHAAG SIR, Bhopal, Ph (0755) 3 00 000 www.tekoclasses.com ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION # Question Type A.Single Correct Type Q. (A) Sol least
Διαβάστε περισσότεραThus X is nonempty by supposition. By (i), let x be a minimal element of X. Then let
4. Ordinals July 26, 2011 In this chapter we introduce the ordinals, prove a general recursion theorem, and develop some elementary ordinal arithmetic. A set A is transitive iff x A y x(y A); in other
Διαβάστε περισσότεραMath221: HW# 1 solutions
Math: HW# solutions Andy Royston October, 5 7.5.7, 3 rd Ed. We have a n = b n = a = fxdx = xdx =, x cos nxdx = x sin nx n sin nxdx n = cos nx n = n n, x sin nxdx = x cos nx n + cos nxdx n cos n = + sin
Διαβάστε περισσότεραF A S C I C U L I M A T H E M A T I C I
F A S C I C U L I M A T H E M A T I C I Nr 46 2011 C. Carpintero, N. Rajesh and E. Rosas ON A CLASS OF (γ, γ )-PREOPEN SETS IN A TOPOLOGICAL SPACE Abstract. In this paper we have introduced the concept
Διαβάστε περισσότεραTHE GENERAL INDUCTIVE ARGUMENT FOR MEASURE ANALYSES WITH ADDITIVE ORDINAL ALGEBRAS
THE GENERAL INDUCTIVE ARGUMENT FOR MEASURE ANALYSES WITH ADDITIVE ORDINAL ALGEBRAS STEFAN BOLD, BENEDIKT LÖWE In [BoLö ] we gave a survey of measure analyses under AD, discussed the general theory of order
Διαβάστε περισσότεραLecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II
Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II October 18, 2012 1 Review First let us recall the situation. Let g be a simple algebra, with maximal toral subalgebra h (which we are calling a CSA, or Cartan Subalgebra).
Διαβάστε περισσότεραHOMEWORK 4 = G. In order to plot the stress versus the stretch we define a normalized stretch:
HOMEWORK 4 Problem a For the fast loading case, we want to derive the relationship between P zz and λ z. We know that the nominal stress is expressed as: P zz = ψ λ z where λ z = λ λ z. Therefore, applying
Διαβάστε περισσότεραCompleteness Theorem for System AS1
11 The Completeness Theorem for System AS1 1. Introduction...2 2. Previous Definitions...2 3. Deductive Consistency...2 4. Maximal Consistent Sets...5 5. Lindenbaum s Lemma...6 6. Every Maximal Consistent
Διαβάστε περισσότεραTridiagonal matrices. Gérard MEURANT. October, 2008
Tridiagonal matrices Gérard MEURANT October, 2008 1 Similarity 2 Cholesy factorizations 3 Eigenvalues 4 Inverse Similarity Let α 1 ω 1 β 1 α 2 ω 2 T =......... β 2 α 1 ω 1 β 1 α and β i ω i, i = 1,...,
Διαβάστε περισσότεραLecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3
Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3 1 State vector space and the dual space Space of wavefunctions The space of wavefunctions is the set of all
Διαβάστε περισσότεραChapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval
Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential Equations Let a (t), a 2 (t),..., a nn (t), b (t), b 2 (t),..., b n (t) be continuous functions on the interval I. The system of n first-order differential equations
Διαβάστε περισσότεραFourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics
Fourier Series MATH 211, Calculus II J. Robert Buchanan Department of Mathematics Spring 2018 Introduction Not all functions can be represented by Taylor series. f (k) (c) A Taylor series f (x) = (x c)
Διαβάστε περισσότεραCHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS
CHAPTER 5 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS EXERCISE 104 Page 8 1. Find the positive root of the equation x + 3x 5 = 0, correct to 3 significant figures, using the method of bisection. Let f(x) =
Διαβάστε περισσότεραSecond Order Partial Differential Equations
Chapter 7 Second Order Partial Differential Equations 7.1 Introduction A second order linear PDE in two independent variables (x, y Ω can be written as A(x, y u x + B(x, y u xy + C(x, y u u u + D(x, y
Διαβάστε περισσότεραSOLVING CUBICS AND QUARTICS BY RADICALS
SOLVING CUBICS AND QUARTICS BY RADICALS The purpose of this handout is to record the classical formulas expressing the roots of degree three and degree four polynomials in terms of radicals. We begin with
Διαβάστε περισσότεραStrain gauge and rosettes
Strain gauge and rosettes Introduction A strain gauge is a device which is used to measure strain (deformation) on an object subjected to forces. Strain can be measured using various types of devices classified
Διαβάστε περισσότεραSection 9.2 Polar Equations and Graphs
180 Section 9. Polar Equations and Graphs In this section, we will be graphing polar equations on a polar grid. In the first few examples, we will write the polar equation in rectangular form to help identify
Διαβάστε περισσότεραde Rham Theorem May 10, 2016
de Rham Theorem May 10, 2016 Stokes formula and the integration morphism: Let M = σ Σ σ be a smooth triangulated manifold. Fact: Stokes formula σ ω = σ dω holds, e.g. for simplices. It can be used to define
Διαβάστε περισσότεραNew bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines
New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines Michigan State University Oct 8-31, 016 Anhui University Definition If X = {x 1, x,, x N } S n 1 (unit sphere in R n ) and x i, x j = a
Διαβάστε περισσότεραΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 19/5/2007
Οδηγίες: Να απαντηθούν όλες οι ερωτήσεις. Αν κάπου κάνετε κάποιες υποθέσεις να αναφερθούν στη σχετική ερώτηση. Όλα τα αρχεία που αναφέρονται στα προβλήματα βρίσκονται στον ίδιο φάκελο με το εκτελέσιμο
Διαβάστε περισσότεραSecond Order RLC Filters
ECEN 60 Circuits/Electronics Spring 007-0-07 P. Mathys Second Order RLC Filters RLC Lowpass Filter A passive RLC lowpass filter (LPF) circuit is shown in the following schematic. R L C v O (t) Using phasor
Διαβάστε περισσότερα( y) Partial Differential Equations
Partial Dierential Equations Linear P.D.Es. contains no owers roducts o the deendent variables / an o its derivatives can occasionall be solved. Consider eamle ( ) a (sometimes written as a ) we can integrate
Διαβάστε περισσότεραAbstract Storage Devices
Abstract Storage Devices Robert König Ueli Maurer Stefano Tessaro SOFSEM 2009 January 27, 2009 Outline 1. Motivation: Storage Devices 2. Abstract Storage Devices (ASD s) 3. Reducibility 4. Factoring ASD
Διαβάστε περισσότεραSCITECH Volume 13, Issue 2 RESEARCH ORGANISATION Published online: March 29, 2018
Journal of rogressive Research in Mathematics(JRM) ISSN: 2395-028 SCITECH Volume 3, Issue 2 RESEARCH ORGANISATION ublished online: March 29, 208 Journal of rogressive Research in Mathematics www.scitecresearch.com/journals
Διαβάστε περισσότεραPartial Differential Equations in Biology The boundary element method. March 26, 2013
The boundary element method March 26, 203 Introduction and notation The problem: u = f in D R d u = ϕ in Γ D u n = g on Γ N, where D = Γ D Γ N, Γ D Γ N = (possibly, Γ D = [Neumann problem] or Γ N = [Dirichlet
Διαβάστε περισσότεραTHE SECOND ISOMORPHISM THEOREM ON ORDERED SET UNDER ANTIORDERS. Daniel A. Romano
235 Kragujevac J. Math. 30 (2007) 235 242. THE SECOND ISOMORPHISM THEOREM ON ORDERED SET UNDER ANTIORDERS Daniel A. Romano Department of Mathematics and Informatics, Banja Luka University, Mladena Stojanovića
Διαβάστε περισσότεραCommutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets
Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets S K Mala #1, Dr. MM Shanmugapriya *2 1 PhD Scholar in Mathematics, Karpagam University, Coimbatore, Tamilnadu- 641021 Assistant Professor of Mathematics,
Διαβάστε περισσότεραSolution Series 9. i=1 x i and i=1 x i.
Lecturer: Prof. Dr. Mete SONER Coordinator: Yilin WANG Solution Series 9 Q1. Let α, β >, the p.d.f. of a beta distribution with parameters α and β is { Γ(α+β) Γ(α)Γ(β) f(x α, β) xα 1 (1 x) β 1 for < x
Διαβάστε περισσότεραΑπόκριση σε Μοναδιαία Ωστική Δύναμη (Unit Impulse) Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο. Απόστολος Σ.
Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο The time integral of a force is referred to as impulse, is determined by and is obtained from: Newton s 2 nd Law of motion states that the action
Διαβάστε περισσότεραCRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS
CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS Shiah-Sen Wang The graphs are prepared by Chien-Lun Lai Based on : Precalculus: Mathematics for Calculus by J. Stuwart, L. Redin & S. Watson, 6th edition, 01, Brooks/Cole Chapter
Διαβάστε περισσότεραDIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANSFORMATION SEMIGROUPS
GANIT J. Bangladesh Math. oc. IN 606-694) 0) -7 DIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANFORMATION EMIGROUP ubrata Majumdar, * Kalyan Kumar Dey and Mohd. Altab Hossain Department of Mathematics University
Διαβάστε περισσότεραApproximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude
Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude Jan Behrens 2012-12-31 In this paper we shall provide a method to approximate distances between two points on earth
Διαβάστε περισσότερα12. Radon-Nikodym Theorem
Tutorial 12: Radon-Nikodym Theorem 1 12. Radon-Nikodym Theorem In the following, (Ω, F) is an arbitrary measurable space. Definition 96 Let μ and ν be two (possibly complex) measures on (Ω, F). We say
Διαβάστε περισσότεραw o = R 1 p. (1) R = p =. = 1
Πανεπιστήµιο Κρήτης - Τµήµα Επιστήµης Υπολογιστών ΗΥ-570: Στατιστική Επεξεργασία Σήµατος 205 ιδάσκων : Α. Μουχτάρης Τριτη Σειρά Ασκήσεων Λύσεις Ασκηση 3. 5.2 (a) From the Wiener-Hopf equation we have:
Διαβάστε περισσότεραΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 6/5/2006
Οδηγίες: Να απαντηθούν όλες οι ερωτήσεις. Ολοι οι αριθμοί που αναφέρονται σε όλα τα ερωτήματα είναι μικρότεροι το 1000 εκτός αν ορίζεται διαφορετικά στη διατύπωση του προβλήματος. Διάρκεια: 3,5 ώρες Καλή
Διαβάστε περισσότερα5. Choice under Uncertainty
5. Choice under Uncertainty Daisuke Oyama Microeconomics I May 23, 2018 Formulations von Neumann-Morgenstern (1944/1947) X: Set of prizes Π: Set of probability distributions on X : Preference relation
Διαβάστε περισσότεραThe Simply Typed Lambda Calculus
Type Inference Instead of writing type annotations, can we use an algorithm to infer what the type annotations should be? That depends on the type system. For simple type systems the answer is yes, and
Διαβάστε περισσότεραLecture 21: Properties and robustness of LSE
Lecture 21: Properties and robustness of LSE BLUE: Robustness of LSE against normality We now study properties of l τ β and σ 2 under assumption A2, i.e., without the normality assumption on ε. From Theorem
Διαβάστε περισσότεραTheorem 8 Let φ be the most powerful size α test of H
Testing composite hypotheses Θ = Θ 0 Θ c 0 H 0 : θ Θ 0 H 1 : θ Θ c 0 Definition 16 A test φ is a uniformly most powerful (UMP) level α test for H 0 vs. H 1 if φ has level α and for any other level α test
Διαβάστε περισσότεραJordan Journal of Mathematics and Statistics (JJMS) 4(2), 2011, pp
Jordan Journal of Mathematics and Statistics (JJMS) 4(2), 2011, pp.115-126. α, β, γ ORTHOGONALITY ABDALLA TALLAFHA Abstract. Orthogonality in inner product spaces can be expresed using the notion of norms.
Διαβάστε περισσότεραThe challenges of non-stable predicates
The challenges of non-stable predicates Consider a non-stable predicate Φ encoding, say, a safety property. We want to determine whether Φ holds for our program. The challenges of non-stable predicates
Διαβάστε περισσότεραLecture 34 Bootstrap confidence intervals
Lecture 34 Bootstrap confidence intervals Confidence Intervals θ: an unknown parameter of interest We want to find limits θ and θ such that Gt = P nˆθ θ t If G 1 1 α is known, then P θ θ = P θ θ = 1 α
Διαβάστε περισσότεραOn a four-dimensional hyperbolic manifold with finite volume
BULETINUL ACADEMIEI DE ŞTIINŢE A REPUBLICII MOLDOVA. MATEMATICA Numbers 2(72) 3(73), 2013, Pages 80 89 ISSN 1024 7696 On a four-dimensional hyperbolic manifold with finite volume I.S.Gutsul Abstract. In
Διαβάστε περισσότερα6.1. Dirac Equation. Hamiltonian. Dirac Eq.
6.1. Dirac Equation Ref: M.Kaku, Quantum Field Theory, Oxford Univ Press (1993) η μν = η μν = diag(1, -1, -1, -1) p 0 = p 0 p = p i = -p i p μ p μ = p 0 p 0 + p i p i = E c 2 - p 2 = (m c) 2 H = c p 2
Διαβάστε περισσότεραHomework 8 Model Solution Section
MATH 004 Homework Solution Homework 8 Model Solution Section 14.5 14.6. 14.5. Use the Chain Rule to find dz where z cosx + 4y), x 5t 4, y 1 t. dz dx + dy y sinx + 4y)0t + 4) sinx + 4y) 1t ) 0t + 4t ) sinx
Διαβάστε περισσότερα6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes
122 CHAPTER 6. ARMA MODELS 6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes The purpose of forecasting is to predict future values of a TS based on the data collected to the present. In this section we will discuss a linear
Διαβάστε περισσότεραdim(u) = n 1 and {v j } j i
SOLUTIONS Math B4900 Homework 1 2/7/2018 Unless otherwise specified, U, V, and W denote vector spaces over a common field F ; ϕ and ψ denote linear transformations; A, B, and C denote bases; A, B, and
Διαβάστε περισσότεραAreas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates
Kiryl Tsishchanka Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates In this section we develop the formula for the area of a region whose boundary is given by a polar equation. We need to use the formula for the
Διαβάστε περισσότεραThe Probabilistic Method - Probabilistic Techniques. Lecture 7: The Janson Inequality
The Probabilistic Method - Probabilistic Techniques Lecture 7: The Janson Inequality Sotiris Nikoletseas Associate Professor Computer Engineering and Informatics Department 2014-2015 Sotiris Nikoletseas,
Διαβάστε περισσότεραSequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5. Luca Alberucci, University of Berne. Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008
Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5 Luca Alberucci, University of Berne Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008 Introduction Koz: Axiomatisation for the modal µ-calculus over K Axioms: All classical
Διαβάστε περισσότερα