PCF: THE ADVANCED PCF THEOREMS E69 SAHARON SHELAH
|
|
- Μορφευς Μοσχοβάκης
- 7 χρόνια πριν
- Προβολές:
Transcript
1 PCF: THE ADVANCED PCF THEOREMS E69 SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. This is a revised version of [Sh:430, 6]. Date: January 21, The author thanks Alice Leonhardt for the beautiful typing. I thank Peter Komjath for some comments. 1
2 2 SAHARON SHELAH 0. Introduction
3 PCF: THE ADVANCED PCF THEOREMS E On pcf This is a revised version of [Sh:430, 6] more self-contained, large part done according to lectures in the Hebrew University Fall 2003 Recall Definition 1.1. Let f = f α : α < δ,f α κ Ord,I an ideal on κ. 1) We say that f κ Ord is a I -l.u.b. of f when: (a) α < δ f α I f (b) if f κ Ord and ( α < δ)(f α I f ) then f I f. 2) We say that f is a I -e.u.b. of f when (a) α < δ f α I f (b) if f κ Ordand f < I Max{f,1 κ }then f < I Max{f α,1 κ } forsomeα < δ. 3) f is I -increasing if α < β f α I f β, similarly < I -increasing. We say f is eventually < I -increasing: it is I -increasing and ( α < δ)( β < δ)(f α < I f β ). 4) We may replace I by the dual ideal on κ. {1.1} Remark 1.2. For κ,i, f as in Definition 1.1, if f is a I -e.u.b. of f then f is a {1.1} I -l.u.b. of f. {1.2} Definition ) We say that s witness or exemplifies f is (< σ)-chaotic for D when, for some κ (a) f = f α : α < δ is a sequence of members of κ Ord (b) D is a filter on κ (or an ideal on κ) (c) f is < D -increasing (d) s = s i : i < κ,s i a non-empty set of < σ ordinals (e) for every α < δ for some β (α,δ) and g s i we have f α D g D f β. 2) Instead (< σ + )-chaotic we may say σ-chaotic. Claim 1.4. Assume (a) I an ideal on κ (b) f = f α : α < δ is < I -increasing, f α κ Ord (c) J I is an ideal on κ and s witnesses f is (< σ)-chaotic for J. {1.3} Then f has no I -e.u.b. f such that {i < κ : cf(f(i)) σ} J. {1.4} Discussion 1.5. What is the aim of clause (c) of 1.4? For I -increasing sequence {1.3} f, f α : α < δ in κ Ordwe areinterested whether it has an appropriate I -e.u.b. Of course, I may be a maximal ideal on κ and f t : t cf((ω,<) κ /D)) is < I -increasing cofinalin(ω,<) κ /D, soithasan< I -e.u.b. thesequenceω κ = ω : i < κ, butthisis notwhatinterestsusnow; weliketohavea I -e.u.b. g suchthat ( i)(cf(g(i)) > κ). Proof. Toward contradiction assume that f κ Ord is a I -e.u.b. of f and A 1 := {i < κ : cf(f(i)) σ} / I hence A / I. We define a function f κ Ord as follows: (a) if i A then f (i) = sup(s i f(i))+1
4 4 SAHARON SHELAH (b) if i κ\a then f (i) = 0. {1.5} Now that i A cf(g(i)) σ > s i f (i) < f(i) Max{g(i),1} and i κ\a f (i) = 0 f (i) < Max{f(i),1}. So by clause (b) of Definition {1.1} 1.1(2) we know that for some α < δ we have f < I Max{f α,1}. But s witness that f is (< σ)-chaotic hence we can find g s i and β (α,δ) such that f α I g I f β and as f is < I -increasing without loss of generality g < I f β. So A 2 := {i < κ : f α (i) g(i) < f β (i) f(i) and f (i) < Max{f α (i),1} = κ} mod I hence A := A 1 A 2 mod I hence A. So for any i A we have f α (i) g(i) < f β (i) f(i) and f(i) s i hence g(i) < f (i) := sup(s i f(i)) +1 and so f (i) 1. Also f (i) < Max{f α (i,1)} hence f (i) < f α (i). Together f (i) < f α (i) g(i) < f (i), contradiction. 1.4 Lemma 1.6. Suppose cf(δ) > κ +,I an ideal on κ and f α κ Ord for α < δ is I -increasing. Then there are J, s, f satisfying: (A) s = s i : i < κ, each s i a set of κ ordinals, (B) sup{f α (i) : α < δ} s i ; moreover is max(s i ) (C) f = f α : α < δ where f α s i is defined by f α (i) = Min{s i\f α (i)}, (similar to rounding!) (D) cf[f α(i)] κ (e.g. f α(i) is a successor ordinal) implies f α(i) = f α (i) (E) J = J α : α < δ,j α is an ideal on κ extending I (for α < δ), decreasing with α (in fact for some a α,β κ (for α < β < κ) we have a α,β /I decreases with β, increases with α and J α is the ideal generated by I {a α,β : β belongs to (α,)}) so possibly J α = P(κ) and possibly J α = I such that: (F) if D is an ultrafilter on κ disjoint to J α then f α /D is a < D-l.u.b and even < D -e.u.b. of f β /D : β < α which is eventually < D -increasing and {i < κ : cf[f α(i))] > κ} D. Moreover (F) + if κ / J α then f α is an < Jα -e.u.b (= exact upper bound) of f β : β < δ and β (α,δ) f β = J α f α (G) if D is an ultrafilter on κ disjoint to I but for every α not disjoint to J α then s exemplifies f α : α < δ is κ chaotic for D as exemplified by s (see Definition 1.3), i.e., for some club E of δ,β < γ E f β D f β < {1.2} D f γ (H) if cf(δ) > 2 κ then f α : α < δ has a I -l.u.b. and even I -e.u.b. and for every large enough α we have I α = I (I) if b α =: {i : f α(i) has cofinality κ (e.g., is a successor)} / J α then: for every β (α,δ) we have f α b α = f β b α mod J α. Remark 1.7. Compare with [Sh:506]. Proof. Let α = {f α (i) + 1 : α < δ,i < κ} and S = {j < α : j has cofinality κ},ē = e j : j S be such that
5 PCF: THE ADVANCED PCF THEOREMS E69 5 (a) e j j, e j κ for every j S (b) if j = i+1 then e j = {i} (c) if j is limit, then j = sup(e j ) and j S e j e j e j. For a set a α let clē(a) = a e j hence by clause (c) clearly clē(clē(a)) = j a S clē(a) and [a b clē(a) clē(b)] and clē(a) a + κ. We try to choose by induction on ζ < κ +, the following objects: α ζ, D ζ, g ζ, s ζ = s ζ,i : i < κ, f ζ,α : α < δ such that: (a) g ζ κ Ord and g ζ (i) {f α (i) : α < δ} (b) s ζ,i = clē[{g ǫ (i) : ǫ < ζ} {sup α<δ f α (i)}] so it is a set of κ ordinals increasing with ζ and sup α<δ f α (i) s ζ,i, moreover sup α<δ f α (i) = max(s ζ,i ) (c) f ζ,α κ Ord is defined by f ζ,α (i) = Min{s ζ,i \f α (i)}, (d) D ζ is an ultrafilter on κ disjoint to I (e) f α Dζ g ζ for α < δ (f) α ζ is an ordinal < δ (g) α ζ α < δ g ζ < Dζ f ζ,α. If we succeed, let α( ) = sup{α ζ : ζ < κ + }, so as cf(δ) > κ + clearly α( ) < δ. Now let i < κ and look at f ζ,α( ) (i) : ζ < κ + ; by its definition (see clause (c)), f ζ,α( ) (i) is the minimal member of the set s ζ,i \f α( ) (i). This set increases with ζ, so f ζ,α( ) (i) decreases with ζ (though not necessarily strictly), hence is eventually constant; so for some ξ i < κ + we have ζ [ξ i,κ + ) f ζ,α( ) (i) = f ξi,α( )(i). Let ξ( ) = sup ξ i, so ξ( ) < κ +, hence 1 ζ [ξ( ),κ+ )andi < κ f ζ,α( ) (i) = f ξ( ),α( ) (i). By clauses (e) + (g) of we know that f α( ) Dξ( ) g ξ( ) < Dξ( ) f ξ( ),α( ) hence for some i < κ we have f α( ) (i) g ξ( ) (i) < f ξ( ),α( ) (i). But g ξ( ) (i) s ξ( )+1,i by clause (b) of hence recalling the definition of f ξ( )+1,α( ) (i) in clause (c) of and the previous sentence f ξ( )+1,α( ) (i) g ξ( ) (i) < f ξ( ),α( ) (i), contradicting the statement 1. So necessarily we are stuck in the induction process. Let ζ < κ + be the first ordinal that breaks the induction. Clearly s ζ,i (i < κ),f ζ,α (α < δ) are well defined. Let s i =: s ζ,i (for i < κ) and f α = f ζ,α (for α < δ), as defined in, clearly they are well defined. Clearly s i is a set of κ ordinals and: ( ) 1 f α f α ( ) 2 α < β f α I f β ( ) 3 if b = {i : f α (i) < f β (i)} / I and α < β < δ then f α b < I f β b. We let for α < δ 2 J α = { b κ : b I or b / I and for every β (α,δ) we have: f α (κ\b) = I f β (κ\b)} 3 for α < β < δ we let a α,β =: {i < κ : f α(i) < f β (i)}. Then as f α : α < δ is I-increasing (i.e., ( ) 2 ):
6 6 SAHARON SHELAH {1.2} ( ) 4 a α,β /I increases with β, decreases with α, J α increases with α ( ) 5 J α is an ideal on κ extending I, in fact is the ideal generated by I {a α,β : β (α,δ)} ( ) 6 if D is an ultrafilter on κ disjoint to J α, then f α /D is a < D-lub of {f β /D : β < δ}. [Why? We know that β (α,δ) a α,β = mod D, so f β f β = D f α for β (α,δ), so f α /D is an D-upper bound. If it is not a least upper bound then for some g κ Ord, for every β < δ we have f β D g < D f α and we can get a contradiction to the choice of ζ, s,f β because: (D,g,α) could serve as D ζ,g ζ,α ζ.] ( ) 7 If D is an ultrafilter on κ disjoint to I but not to J α for every α < δ then s exemplifies that f α : α < δ is κ + -chaotic for D, see Definition 1.3. [Why? For every α < δ for some β (α,δ) we have a α,β D, i.e., {i < κ : f α(i) < f β (i)} D, so f α /D : α < δ is not eventually constant, so if α < β,f α < D f β then f α < D f β (by ( ) 3 ) and f α D f α (by (c)). So f α D f α < D f β as required.] ( ) 8 if κ / J α then f α is an J α -e.u.b. of f β : β < δ. [Why? By ( ) 6, f α is a J α -upper bound of f β : β < δ ; so assume that it is not a Jα -e.u.b. of f β : β < δ, hence there is a function g with domain κ, such that g < Jα Max{1,f α}, but for no β < δ do we have c β =: {i < κ : g(i) < Max{1,f β (i)}} = κ mod J α. Clearly c β : β < δ is increasingmodulo J α so there is an ultrafilter D on κ disjoint to J α {c β : β < δ}. So β < δ f β D g D f α, so we get a contradiction to ( ) 6 except when g = D f α and then f α = D 0 κ (as g(i) < 1 g(i) < f α(i)). If we can demand c = {i : f α (i) = 0} / D we are done, but easily c \c β J α so we finish.] ( ) 9 If cf[f α (i)] κ then f α (i) = f α(i) so clause (D) of the lemma holds. [Why? By the definition of s ζ = clē[...] and the choice of ē, and of f α(i).] ( ) 10 Clause (I) of the conclusion holds. [Why? As f α Jα f β Jα f α and f α b α = Jα f α b α by ( ) 9.] ( ) 11 if α < β < δ then f α = f β mod J α, so clause (F) + holds. [Why? First, f is I -increasing hence it is Jα -increasing. Second, β α f β I f α f α f β Jα f α. Third, if β (α,δ) then a α,β = {i < κ : f α(i) < f β (i)} J α, hence f β J α f α but as f α I f β clearly f α I f β hence f α J α f β, so together f α = Jα f β.] ( ) 12 if cf(δ) > 2 κ then for some α( ),J α( ) = I (hence f has a I -e.u.b.) [Why? As J α : α < δ isa -decreasingsequenceofsubsetsof P(κ)itiseventually constant, say, i.e., there is α( ) < δ such that α( ) α < δ J α = J α( ). Also I J α( ), but if I J α( ) then there is an ultrafilter D of κ disjoint to I but not to J α( ) hence s i : i < κ witness being κ-chaotic. But this implies cf(δ) s i κ κ = 2 κ, contradiction.] The reader can check the rest. 1.6
7 PCF: THE ADVANCED PCF THEOREMS E69 7 Example ) We show that l.u.b and e.u.b are not the same. Let I be an ideal on κ,κ + < = cf(),ā = a α : α < be a sequence of subsets of κ, (strictly) increasing modulo I, κ\a α / I but there is no b P(κ)\I such that b a α I. [Does this occur? E.g., for I = [κ] <κ, the existence of such ā is α known to be consistent; e.g., MA andκ = ℵ 0 and = 2 ℵ0. Moreover, for any κ and κ + < = cf() 2 κ we can find a α κ for α < such that, e.g., any Boolean combination of the a α s has cardinality κ (less needed). Let I 0 be the ideal on κ generated by [κ] <κ {a α \a β : α < β < }, and let I be maximal in {J : J an ideal on κ,i 0 J and [α < β < a β \a α / J]}. So if G.C.H. fails, we have examples.] For α <, we let f α : κ Ord be: f α (i) = { α if i κ\a α, +α if i a α. {1.6} Now the constant function f κ Ord,f(i) = + is a l.u.b of f α : α < but not an e.u.b. (both mod I) (no e.u.b. is exemplified by g κ Ord which is constantly ). 2) Why do we require cf(δ) > κ + rather than cf(δ) > κ? As we have to, by Kojman-Shelah [KjSh:673]. Recall (see [Sh:506, 2.3(2)]) Definition 1.9. We say that f = f α : α < δ obeys u α : α S when {1.7} (a) f α : w Ord for some fixed set w (b) S a set of ordinals (c) u α α (d) if α S δ and β u α then t w f β (t) f α (t). Claim Assume I is an ideal on κ, f = f α : α < δ is I -increasing and obeys ū = u α : α S. The sequence f has a I -e.u.b. when for some S + we have 1 or 2 where 1 (a) S + {α < δ : cf(α) > κ} (b) S + is a stationary subset of δ (c) for each α S + there are unbounded subsets u,v of α for which β v u β u β. 2 S + = {δ} and for δ clause (c) of 1 holds. Proof. By [Sh:506] {1.8} Remark ) Connected to Ǐ[], see [Sh:506]. {1.10} Claim Suppose J a σ-complete ideal on δ,µ > κ = cf(µ),µ = tlim J i : i < δ,δ < µ, i = cf( i ) > δ for i < δ and = tcf( i<δ i /J), and f α : α < exemplifies this. Then we have
8 8 SAHARON SHELAH ( ) if u β : β < is a sequence of pairwise disjoint non-empty subsets of, each of cardinality σ (not < σ!) and α < µ +, then we can find B such that: (a) otp(b) = α, (b) if β B,γ B and β < γ then sup(u β ) < min(u γ ), (c) we can find s ζ J for ζ u i such that: if ζ u β,ξ i B β B u β,ζ < ξ and i δ\(s ζ s ξ ), then f ζ (i) < f ξ (i). β B Proof. First assume α < µ. For each regular θ < µ, as θ + < = cf() there is a stationary S θ {δ < : cf(δ) = θ < δ} which is in Ǐ[] (see [Sh:420, 1.5]) which is equivalent (see [Sh:420, 1.2(1)]) to: ( ) there is C θ = C θ α : α < (α) C θ α a subset of α, with no accumulation points (in C θ α), (β) [α nacc(c θ β ) Cθ α = Cθ β α], (γ) for some club E 0 θ of, [δ S θ Eθ 0 cf(δ) = θ < δ δ = sup(cδ) otp(c θ δ) θ = θ]. Without loss of generality S θ Eθ 0, and otp(cα θ ) θ. By [Sh:365, 2.3,Def.1.3] α<δ for some club E θ of, gl(cα θ,e θ) : α S θ guess clubs (i.e., for every club E E θ of, for stationarily many ζ S θ, gl(cζ θ,e θ) E) (remember gl(cδ θ,e θ) = {sup(γ E θ ) : γ Cδ θ;γ > Min(E θ)}). Let Cα θ, = {γ Cα θ : γ = Min(Cα\sup(γ θ E θ ))}, they have all the properties of the Cα θ s and guess clubs in a weak sense: for every club E of for some α S θ E, if γ 1 < γ 2 are successive members of E then (γ 1,γ 2 ] Cα θ, 1; moreover, the function γ sup(e γ) is one to one on Cθ,. Now we define by induction on ζ <, an ordinal α ζ and functions g ζ θ α (for each θ Θ =: {θ : θ < µ,θ regular uncountable}). For given ζ, let α ζ < be minimal such that: ξ < ζ α ξ < α ζ ξ < ζ θ Θ g ξ θ < f α ζ mod J. Now α ζ exists as f α : α < is < J -increasing cofinal in θ Θ we define g ζ θ as follows: i<δ i i<δ i /J. Now for each for i < δ,g ζ θ (i) is sup[{gξ θ (i)+1 : ξ Cθ ζ } {f α ζ (i)+1}] if this number is < i, and f αζ (i)+1 otherwise. Having made the definition we prove the assertion. We are given u β : β <, a sequence of pairwise disjoint non-empty subsets of, each of cardinality σ and α < µ. We should find B as promised; let θ =: ( α + δ ) + so θ < µ is regular > δ. Let E = {δ E θ : ( ζ)[ζ < δ sup(u ζ ) < δ u ζ δ α ζ < δ]}. Choose α S θ acc(e) such that gl(cζ θ,e θ) E; hence letting Cα θ, = {γ i : i < θ} (increasing), γ(i) = γ i, we know that i < δ (γ i,γ i+1 ) E. Now let
9 PCF: THE ADVANCED PCF THEOREMS E69 9 B =: {γ 5i+3 : i < α } we shall prove that B is as required. For α u γ(5ζ+3),ζ < α, let s o α = {i < δ : g γ(5ζ+1) θ (i) < f α (i) < g γ(5ζ+4) θ (i)}, for each ζ < α let α ζ,ε : ε < u γ(5ζ+3) enumerate u γ(5ζ+3) and let s 1 α ζ,ε = {i : for every ξ < ǫ,f αζ,ξ (i) < f αζ,ǫ (i) α ζ,ξ < α ζ,ǫ f αζ,ξ (i) f αζ,ǫ (i)}. Lastly,forα ζ<α u 5ζ+3 lets α = s o α s1 α anditisenoughtocheckthat ζ α : α B witness that B is as required. Also we have to consider α [µ,µ + ), we prove this by induction on α and in the induction step we use θ = (cf(α ) + δ ) + using a similar proof {1.11} Remark In 1.12: {1.10} 1) We can avoid guessing clubs. 2) Assume σ < θ 1 < θ 2 < µ are regular and there is S {δ < : cf(δ) = θ 1 } from I[] such that for every ζ < (or at least a club) of cofinality θ 2, S ζ is stationary and f α : α < obey suitable C θ (see [Sh:345a, 2]). Then for some A unbounded, for every u β : β < θ 2 sequence of pairwise disjoint non-empty subsets ofa, each ofcardinality < σ with [minu β,supu β ] pairwisedisjoint we have: for every B 0 A of order type θ 2, for some B B 0, B = θ 1, (c) of ( ) of 1.12 {1.10} holds. 3) In ( ) of 1.12, α < µ can be replaced by α < µ + (prove by induction on {1.10} α ). {1.12} Observation Assume < <,µ = Min{τ : 2 τ > }. Then there are δ,χ and T, satisfying the condition ( ) below for χ = 2 µ or at least arbitrarily large regular χ < 2 µ ( ) T a tree with δ levels, (where δ µ) with a set X of χ δ-branches, and for α < δ, T β <. β<α Proof. So let χ 2 µ be regular, χ >. Case 1: 2 α <. Then T = µ> 2, T α = α 2 are O.K. (the set of branches µ 2 α<µ has cardinality 2 µ ). Case 2: Not Case 1. So for some θ < µ, 2 θ, but by the choice of µ,2 θ, so 2 θ =,θ < µ and so θ α < µ 2 α = 2 θ. Note µ> 2 = as µ. Note also that µ = cf(µ) in this case (by the Bukovsky-Hechler theorem). Subcase 2A: cf() µ = cf(µ). Let µ> 2 = B j,b j increasing with j, B j <. For each η µ 2, (as cf() j< cf(µ)) for some j η <, µ = sup{ζ < µ : η ζ B jη }. So as cf(χ) µ, for some ordinal j < we have {η µ 2 : j η j } has cardinality χ.
10 10 SAHARON SHELAH As cf() cf(µ) and µ (by its definition) clearly µ <, hence B j µ <. Let It is as required. T = {η ǫ : ǫ < lg(η) and η B j }. {6.4} {1.21} Subcase 2B: Not 2A so cf() = µ = cf(µ). If = µ we get = < contradicting an assumption. So > µ, so singular. Now if α < µ,µ < σ i = cf(σ i ) < for i < α then (see [Sh:g,?, 1.3(10)]) maxpcf{σ i : i < α} σ i α (2 θ ) α 2 <µ =, but as is singular and maxpcf{σ i : i < α} is regular (see [Sh:345a, 1.9]), clearly the inequality is strict, i.e., maxpcf{σ i : i < α} <. So let σ i : i < µ be a strictly increasing sequence of regulars in (µ,) with limit, and by [Sh:355, 3.4] there is T σ i satisfying {ν i : ν T } maxpcf{σ j : j < i} <, and number of i<µ µ-branches >. In fact we can get any regular cardinal in (,pp + ()) in the same way. Let = min{ : µ <,cf( ) = µ and pp( ) > }, so (by [Sh:355, 2.3]), also has those properties and pp( ) pp(). So if pp + ( ) = (2 µ ) + or pp( ) = 2 µ is singular, we are done. So assume this fails. If µ > ℵ 0, then (as in [Sh:430, 3.4]) α < 2 µ cov(α,µ +,µ +,µ) < 2 µ and we can finish as in subcase 2A (actually cov(2 <µ,µ +,µ +,µ) < 2 µ suffices which holds by the previous sentence and [Sh:355, 5.4]). If µ = ℵ 0 all is easy Claim Assume b 0... b k b k+1 for k < ω,a = b k (and k<ω a + < Min(a)) and pcf(a)\ pcf(b k ). k<ω 1) We can find finite d k pcf(b k \b k 1 ) (stipulating b 1 = ) such that pcf( {d k : k < ω}). 2) Moreover, we can demand d k pcf(b k )\(pcf(b k 1 )). Proof. We start to repeat the proof of [Sh:371, 1.5] for κ = ω. But there we apply [Sh:371, 1.4] to b ζ : ζ < κ and get c ζ,l : l n(ζ) : ζ < κ and let ζ,l = maxpcf(c ζ,l ). Here we apply the same claim ([Sh:371, 1.4]) to b k \b k 1 : k < ω to get part (1). As for part (2), in the proof of [Sh:371, 1.5] we let δ = a + +ℵ 2 choose N i : i < δ, but now we have to adapt the proof of [Sh:371, 1.4] (applied to a, b k : k < ω, N i : i < δ ); we have gotten there, toward the end, α < δ such that E α E. Let E α = {i k : k < ω},i k < i k+1. But now instead of applying [Sh:371, 1.3] to each b l separately, we try to choose c ζ,l : l n(ζ) by induction on ζ < ω. Forζ = 0weapply[?, 1.3]. Forζ > 0, weapply[sh:371, 1.3]tob ζ buttheredefining by induction on l,c l = c ζ,l a such that max(pcf(a\c ζ,0 \ \c ζ,l 1 ) pcf(b ζ ) is strictly decreasing with l. We use: i<α Observation If a i < Min(a i ) for i < i, then c = element or is empty. i<i pcf(a i ) has a last Proof. By renaming without loss of generality a i : i < i is non-decreasing. By [Sh:345b, 1.12]
11 PCF: THE ADVANCED PCF THEOREMS E69 11 ( ) 1 d cand d < Min(d) pcf(d) c. By [Sh:371, 2.6] or 2.7(2) ( ) 2 if pcf(d),d c, d < Min(d) then for some d we have Min(a 0 ), pcf( ). {6.7C.1} Now choose by induction on ζ < a 0 +,θ ζ c, satisfying θ ζ > maxpcf{θ ǫ : ǫ < ζ}. If we are stuck in ζ, maxpcf{θ ǫ : ǫ < ζ} is the desired maximum by ( ) 1. If we succeed the cardinal θ = maxpcf{θ ǫ : ǫ < a 0 + } is in pcf{θ ǫ : ǫ < ζ} for some ζ < a 0 + by ( ) 2 ; easy contradiction {1.22} Conclusion Assume ℵ 0 = cf(µ) κ µ 0 < µ,[µ (µ 0,µ)andcf(µ ) κ pp κ (µ ) < ] and pp + κ (µ) > = cf() > µ. Then we can find n for n < ω,µ 0 < n < n+1 < µ, µ = n and = tcf( n /J) for some ideal J on ω (extending J bd ω ). n<ω Proof. Let a (µ 0,µ) Reg, a κ, pcf(a). Without loss of generality = maxpcf(a), let µ = µ 0 n, µ 0 µ 0 n < µ 0 n+1 < µ, let µ 1 n = µ 0 n+sup{pp κ (µ ) : µ 0 < n<ω µ µ 0 n and cf(µ ) κ}, by [Sh:355, 2.3] µ 1 n < µ,µ 1 n = µ 0 n + sup{pp κ (µ ) : µ 0 < µ < µ 1 n and cf(µ ) κ} and obviously µ 1 n µ1 n+1 ; by replacing by a subsequence without loss of generality µ 1 n < µ 1 n+1. Now let b n = a µ 1 n and apply the previous claim 1.15: to b k =: a (µ 1 n )+, note: {6.4} n<ω maxpcf(b k ) µ 1 k < Min(b k+1\b k ) {1.23} Claim ) Assume ℵ 0 < cf(µ) = κ < µ 0 < µ,2 κ < µ and [µ 0 µ < µandcf(µ ) κ pp κ (µ ) < µ]. If µ < = cf() < pp + (µ) then there is a tree T with κ levels, each level of cardinality < µ, T has exactly κ-branches. 2) Suppose i : i < κ is a strictly increasing sequence of regular cardinals, 2 κ < 0,a =: { i : i < κ}, = maxpcf(a), j > maxpcf{ i : i < j} for each j < κ (or at least i<j i > maxpcf{ i : i < j}) and a / J where J = {b a : b is the union of countably many members of J < [a]} (so J Ja bd and cf(κ) > ℵ 0 ). Then the conclusion of (1) holds with µ = i. Proof. 1) By (2) and [Sh:371, 1] (or can use the conclusion of [Sh:g, AG,5.7]). 2) For each b a define the function g b : κ Reg by g b (i) = maxpcf[b { j : j < i}]. Clearly[b 1 b 2 g b1 g b2 ]. Ascf(κ) > ℵ 0,J isℵ 1 -complete,thereisb a,b / J such that: c bandc / J g c < J g b. Let i = maxpcf(b { j : j < i}). For each i let b i = b { j : j < i} and f,α b : α < : pcf(b) be as in [Sh:371, 1]. Let
12 12 SAHARON SHELAH {1.24} {1.25} {1.25} T 0 i = { Max 0<l<n fb l,α l b i : l pcf(b i ),α l < l,n < ω}. Let T i = {f T 0 i : for every j < i,f b j T 0 j moreover for some f for every j, f b j T 0 j and f f }, and T = j<κ j, T i, clearly it is a tree, T i its ith level (or empty), T i i. By [Sh:371, 1.3,1.4] for every g b for some f b, f b i Ti 0 hence f b i T i. So T i = i, and T has κ-branches. By the observation below we can finish (apply it essentially to F = {η: for some f b for i < κ we have η(i) = f b i and for every i < κ,f b i Ti 0}), then find A κ,κ \ A J and g ( i +1) such that Y =: {f F : f A < g A} has cardinality and then the tree will be T where T i =: {f b i : f Y } and T = T i. (So actually this proves that if we have such a tree with θ(cf(θ) > 2 κ ) κ-branches then there is one with exactly θ κ-branches.) 1.18 Observation If F i, J an ℵ 1 -complete ideal on κ, and [f g F f J g] and F θ,cf(θ) > 2 κ, then for some g ( i +1) we have: (a) Y = {f F : f < J g } has cardinality θ, (b) for f < J g, we have {f F : f J f } < θ, (c) there 1 are f α Y for α < θ such that: f α < J g,[α < β < θ f β < J f α ]. (Also in [Sh:829, 1]). Proof. Let Z =: {g : g ( i +1) and Y g =: {f F : f J g} has cardinality θ}. Clearly i : i < κ Z so there is g Z such that: [g Z g < J g ]; so clause (b) holds. Let Y = {f F : f < J g }, easily Y Y g and Y g \Y 2 κ hence Y θ, also clearly [f 1 f 2 Fandf 1 J f 2 f 1 < J f 2 ]. If (a) fails, necessarily by the previous sentence Y > θ. For each f Y let Y f = {h Y : h J f}, so by clause (b) we have Y f < θ hence by the Hajnal free subset theorem for some Z Z, Z = +, and f 1 f 2 Z f 1 / Y f2 so [f 1 f 2 Z f 1 < J f 2 ]. But there is no such Z of cardinality > 2 κ ([Sh:111, 2.2,p.264]) so clause (a) holds. As for clause (c): choose f α F by induction on α, suchthat f α Y \ β<α Y f β ; it existsby cardinalityconsiderationsand f α : α < θ is as required (in (c)) Observation Let κ < be regular uncountable, 2 κ < µ i < (for i < κ), µ i increasing in i. The following are equivalent: (A) there is F κ such that: (i) F =, (ii) {f i : f F} µ i, (iii) [f g F f J bd g]; κ 1 Or straightening clause (i) see the proof of 1.20
13 PCF: THE ADVANCED PCF THEOREMS E69 13 (B) there be a sequence i : i < κ such that: (i) 2 κ < i = cf( i ) µ i, (ii) maxpcf{ i : i < κ} =, (iii) for j < κ,µ j maxpcf{ i : i < j}; (C) there is an increasing sequence a i : i < κ suchthat pcf( a i ),pcf(a i ) µ i (so Min( a i ) > a i ). Proof. (B) (A): By [Sh:355, 3.4]. (A) (B): If ( θ)[θ 2 κ θ κ θ + ] we can directly prove (B) if for a club of i < κ,µ i > µ j, and contradict (A) if this fails. Otherwise every normal filter D j<i on κ is nice (see [Sh:386, 1]). Let F exemplify (A). Let K = {(D,g) : D a normal filter on κ, g κ (+1), = {f F : f < D g} }. ClearlyK is not empty (let g be constantly ) so by [Sh:386] we can find (D,g) K such that: ( ) 1 if A κ,a mod D,g 1 < D+A g then > {f F : f < D+A g 1 }. Let F = {f F : f < D g}, so (as in the proof of 1.18) F =. {1.23} We claim: ( ) 2 if h F then {f F : h D f} has cardinality <. [Why? Otherwise for some h F, F =: {f F : h D f} has cardinality, for A κ let F A = {f F : f A h A} so F = {F A : A κ,a mod D}, hence (recall that 2 κ < ) for some A κ,a mod D and F A = ; now (D+A,h) contradicts ( ) 1 ]. By ( ) 2 we can choose by induction on α <, a function f α F such that f β < D f α. By [Sh:355, 1.2A(3)] f α : α < has an e.u.b. f. Let i = β<α cf(f (i)), clearly {i < κ : i 2 κ } = mod D, so without loss of generality cf(f (i)) > 2 κ so i is regular (2 κ,], and = tcf( i /D). Let J i = {A i : maxpcf{ j : j A} µ i }; so (remembering (ii) of (A)) we can find h i j<if (i) such that: ( ) 3 if {j : j < i} / J i, then for every f F,f i < Ji h i. Let h f (i) be defined by: h(i) = sup{h j (i) : j (i,κ) and {j : j < i} / J i }. As cf[f (i)] > 2 κ, clearly i h < f hence by the choice of f for some α( ) < we have: h < D f α( ) and let A =: {i < κ : h(i) < f α( ) (i)}, so A D. Define i as follows: i is i if i A, and is (2 κ ) + if i κ\a. Now i : i < κ is as required in (B). (B) (C): Straightforward. (C) (B): By [Sh:371, 1] {1.26} Claim If F κ Ord,2 κ < θ = cf(θ) F then we can find g κ Ord and a proper ideal I on κ and A κ,a I such that:
14 {1.27} {1.26} {1.28} {1.28a} {1.28} {1.29} {1.27} 14 SAHARON SHELAH (a) g (i)/i has true cofinality θ, and for each i κ\a we have cf[g (i)] > 2 κ, (b) for every g κ Ord satisfying g A = g A, g (κ\a) < g (κ\a) we can find f F such that: f A = g A,g (κ\a) < f (κ\a) < g (κ\a). Proof. As in [Sh:410, 3.7], proof of (A) (B). (In short let f α F for α < θ be distinct, χ large enough, N i : i < (2 κ ) + as there, δ i =: sup(θ N i ),g i κ Ord,g i (ζ) =: Min[N Ord\f δi (ζ)],a κ and S {i < (2 κ ) + : cf(i) = κ + } stationary, [i S g i = g ], [ζ < αandi S [f δi (ζ) = g (ζ) ζ A] and for some i( ) < (2 κ ) +, g N i( ), so [ζ κ\a cf(g (ζ)) > 2 κ ] Claim Suppose D is a σ-complete filter on θ = cf(θ),κ an infinite cardinal, θ > α κ for α < σ, and for each α < θ, β = βǫ α : ǫ < κ is a sequence of ordinals. Then for every X θ,x mod D there is βǫ : ǫ < κ (a sequence of ordinals) and w κ such that: (a) ǫ κ\w σ cf(βǫ) θ, (b) if β ǫ β ǫ and [ǫ w β ǫ = β ǫ ], then {α X: for every ǫ < κ we have β ǫ βǫ α βǫ and [ǫ w βǫ α = βǫ]} mod D. Proof. Essentially by the same proof as 1.21 (replacing δ i by Min{α X: for every Y N i D we have α Y}). See more [Sh:513, 6]. (See [Sh:620, 7]) Remark We can rephrase the conclusion as: (a) B =: {α X: if ǫ w then β α ǫ = β ǫ, and: if ǫ κ\w then βα ǫ is < β ǫ but > sup{β ζ : ζ < ǫ,βα ζ < β ǫ}} is mod D (b) If β ǫ < β ǫ for ǫ κ \ w then {α B: if ǫ κ \ w then βα ǫ > β ǫ } mod D (c) ǫ κ\w cf(β ǫ) is θ but σ. Remark If a < min(a), F Πa, F = θ = cf(θ) / pcf(a) and even θ > σ = sup(θ + pcf(a)) then for some g Πa, the set {f F : f < g} is unbounded in θ (or use a σ-complete D as in 1.23). (This is as Πa/J <θ [a] is min(pcf(a) \ θ)-directed as the ideal J <θ [a] is generated by σ sets; this is discussed in [Sh:513, 6].) Remark It is useful to note that 1.22 is useful to use [Sh:462, 4,5.14]: e.g., for if n < ω, θ 0 < θ 1 < < θ n, satisfying ( ) below, for any β ǫ βǫ satisfying [ǫ w β ǫ < βǫ] we can find α < γ in X such that: where ǫ w β α ǫ = β ǫ, {ǫ,ζ} κ\wand{cf(β ε),cf(β ζ)} [θ l,θ l+1 ))andl even β α ǫ < β γ ζ, {ǫ,ζ} κ\wand{cf(β ε ),cf(β ζ )} [θ l,θ l+1 )andl odd β γ ǫ < βα ζ ( ) (a) ǫ κ\w cf(β ǫ) [θ 0,θ n ), and
15 PCF: THE ADVANCED PCF THEOREMS E69 15 (b) maxpcf[{cf(β ǫ ) : ǫ κ\w} θ l] θ l (which holds ifθ l = σ + l, σκ l = σ l for l {l,...,n}).
16 16 SAHARON SHELAH {1.31} 2. Nice generating sequences Claim 2.1. For any a, a < Min(a), we can find b = b : a such that: (α) b is a generating sequence, i.e. a J [a] = J < [a]+b, (β) b is smooth, i.e., for θ < in a, θ b b θ b, {1.32} {1.33} {1.33} (γ) b is closed, i.e., for a we have b = a pcf(b ). Definition ) Foraset a and set a ofregularcardinalslet Ch a a be the function with domain a a defined by Ch a a (θ) = sup(a θ). 2) We may write N instead of N, where N is a model (usually an elementary submodel of (H (χ),,< χ) for some reasonable χ. Observation 2.3. If a a and a < Min(a) then ch a a Πa. Proof. Let b θ [a] : θ pcf(a) be as in [Sh:371, 2.6] or Definition [Sh:506, 2.12]. For a, let f a, = fα a, : α < be a < J< [a]-increasing cofinal sequence of members of a, satisfying: ( ) 1 if δ <, a < cf(δ) < Min(a) and θ a then: f a, δ (θ) = Min{ fα a, (θ) : C a club of δ} α C [exists by [Sh:345a, Def.3.3,(2) b + Fact 3.4(1)]]. Let χ = ℶ ω (sup(a)) + and κ satisfies a < κ = cf(κ) < Min(a) (without loss of generality there is such κ) and let N = N i : i < κ be an increasing continuous sequenceof elementarysubmodels of(h (χ),,< χ), N i κ an ordinal, N (i+1) N i+1, N i < κ, and a, f a, : a and κ belong to N 0. Let N κ = N i. Clearly by 2.3 ( ) 2 Ch a N i Πa for i κ. Now for every a the sequence Ch a N i () : i κ is increasing continuous (note that N 0 N i N i+1 and N i, N i+1 hence sup(n i ) N i+1 hence Ch a N i () is < sup(n i+1 )). Hence {Ch a N i () : i < κ} is a club of Ch a N κ (); moreover, for every club E of κ the set {Ch a N i () : i E} is a club of Ch a N κ (). Hence by ( ) 1, for every a, for some club E of κ, ( ) 3 (α) ifθ aande E isaclubofκthenf a, sup(n κ ) (θ) = α E f a, sup(n α ) (θ) (β) f a, sup(n (θ) cl(θ N κ ) κ), (i.e., the closure as a set of ordinals). Let E = E, so E is a club of κ. For any i < j < κ let a b i,j = {θ a : Cha N i (θ) < f a, sup(n j ) (θ)}.
17 PCF: THE ADVANCED PCF THEOREMS E69 17 ( ) 4 for i < j < κ and a, we have: (α) J [a] = J < [a]+b i,j [Why? (hence bi,j = b [ā] mod J < [a]), (β) b i,j + a, (γ) b i,j : a N j+1, (δ) f a, sup(n κ ) Cha N κ = sup(n κ θ) : θ a. Clause (α): First as Ch a N i Πa (by 2.3) there is γ < such that Ch a N i < J= [a] {1.33} fγ a, and as a {a,n i } Ch a N i+1 clearly Ch a N i N i+1 hence without loss of generality γ N i+1 but i + 1 j hence N i+1 N j hence γ N j hence γ < sup(n j ) hence fγ a, < J= [a] f a, sup(n. Together j ) Cha N i < J= [a] f a, sup(n j ) hence by the definition of b i,j we have a\bi,j J =[a] hence / pcf(a\b i,j ) so J [a] J < [a]+b i,j. Second, (Πa,< J [a]) is + -directed hence there is g Πa such that α < f a, α < J [a] g. As f a, N 0 without loss of generality g N 0 hence g N i so g < Ch a N i. By the choice of g,f a, sup(n < j ) J [a] g so together f a, sup(n < j ) J [a] Ch a N i hence b i,j J [a]. As J < [a] J [a] clearly J < [a]+b i,j J [a]. Together we are done. Clause (β): Because Π(a\ + ) is + -directed we have θ a\ + {θ} / J [a]. Clause (γ): As Ch a N i,f,a sup(n j ), f belongs to N j+1. Clause (δ): For θ a( N 0 ) we have f a, sup(n κ ) (θ) = {fa, sup(n (θ) : ε E ε ) } sup(n κ θ). So we have proved ( ) 4.] ( ) 5 ε( ) < κ when ε( ) = {ε,θ : θ < are from a} where ε,θ = Min{ε < κ: if f a, sup(n (θ) < sup(n κ ) κ θ) then f a, sup(n (θ) < sup(n κ ) ε θ)}. [Why? Obvious.] ( ) 6 f a, sup(n κ ) bi,j = Cha N κ b i,j when i < j are from E\ε( ). [Why? Let θ b i,j, so by ( ) 3(β) we know that f a, sup(n (θ) κ ) Cha N κ (θ). If the inequality is strict then there is β N κ θ such that f a, sup(n (θ) β < κ ) Ch a N κ (θ) hence for some ε < κ,β N ε hence ζ (ε,κ) f a, sup(n (θ) < κ ) Cha N ζ (θ) hence (as i ε,θ holds) we have f a, sup(n (θ) < κ ) Cha N i (θ) so f a, sup(n (θ) j ) f a, sup(n (θ) < κ ) Cha N, (thefirstinequalityholdsasj E i(θ) ). Butbythedefinition of b i,j this contradicts θ bi,j.] We now define by induction on ǫ < a +, for a (and i < j < κ), the set b i,j,ǫ ( ) 7 (α) b i,j,0 (β) b i,j,ǫ+1 j (γ) b i,j,ǫ = b i,j = b i,j,ǫ = ζ<ǫ b i,j,ζ {b i,j,ǫ θ : θ b i,j,ǫ } {θ a : θ pcf(b i,j,ǫ )}, for ǫ < a + limit. :
18 18 SAHARON SHELAH Clearlyfor a, b i,j,ǫ : ǫ < a + belongston j+1 andisanon-decreasingsequence of subsets of a, hence for some ǫ(i,j,) < a +, we have {1.31} [ǫ (ǫ(i,j,), a + ) b i,j,ǫ So letting ǫ(i,j) = sup a ǫ(i,j,) < a + we have: ( ) 8 ǫ(i,j) ǫ < a + b i,j,ǫ(i,j) = b i,j,ǫ. a = b i,j,ǫ(i,j,) ]. We restrict ourselves to the case i < j are from E\ε( ). Which of the properties required from b : a are satisfied by b i,j,ǫ(i,j) : a? In the conclusion of 2.1 properties (β), (γ) hold by the inductive definition of b i,j,ǫ (and the choice of ǫ(i,j)). As for property (α), one half, J [a] J < [a]+b i,j,ǫ(i,j) hold by ( ) 4 (α) (and b i,j = bi,j,0 b i,j,ǫ(i,j) ), so it is enough to prove (for a): ( ) 9 b i,j,ǫ(i,j) J [a]. For this end we define by induction on ǫ < a + functions f a,,ǫ α for every pair (α,) satisfying α < a, such that ζ < ǫ fα a,,ζ domain increases with ǫ. We let f a,,0 α = f a, α b i,j,fa,,ε α defined by defining each f a,,ǫ+1 α Case 1: If θ b i,j,ǫ then f a,,ε+1 α = ζ<ǫ f a,,ζ α (θ) as follows: (θ) = f a,,ǫ (θ). α with domain b i,j,ǫ fα a,,ǫ, so the for limit ǫ < a + and f a,,ǫ+1 α Case 2: If µ b i,j,ǫ,θ b i,j,ǫ µ and not Case 1 and µ minimal under those conditions, then fα a,,ε+1 (θ) = f a,µ,ǫ (θ where we choose β = fα a,,ǫ (µ). β Case 3: If θ a pcf(b i,j,ǫ ) and neither Case 1 nor Case 2, then fα a,,ǫ+1 (θ) = Min{γ < θ : fα a,,ǫ b θ [a] J<θ [a] fγ a,θ,ǫ }. Now b i,j,ǫ : a : ǫ < a + can be computed from a and b i,j : a. But the latter belongs to N j+1 by ( ) 4 (γ), so the former belongs to N j+1 and as b i,j,ǫ : a : ǫ < a + is eventually constant, also each member of the sequence belongs to N j+1. As also fα a, : α < : pcf(a) belongs to N j+1 we clearly get that f a,,ǫ α : ǫ < a + : α < : a belongs to N j+1. Next we prove by induction on ǫ that, for a, we have: 1 θ b i,j,ǫ and a f a,,ǫ sup(n κ ) (θ) = sup(n κ θ). For ǫ = 0 this holds by ( ) 6. For ǫ limit this holds by the induction hypothesis and the definition of fα a,,ǫ (as union of earlier ones). For ǫ+1, we check f a,,ǫ+1 sup(n (θ) κ ) according to the case in its definition; for Case 1 use the induction hypothesis applied to f a,,ǫ sup(n κ ). For Case 2 (with µ), by the induction hypothesis applied to f a,µ,ǫ sup(n κ µ). Lastly, for Case 3 (with θ) we should note: is
19 (i) b i,j,ǫ PCF: THE ADVANCED PCF THEOREMS E69 19 b θ [a] / J <θ [a]. [Why? By the case s assumption b i,j,ε (ii) f a,,ǫ sup(n κ ) (bi,j,ǫ b i,j,ǫ θ ) f a,θ,ǫ sup(n. κ θ) (J θ [a]) + and ( ) 4 (α) above.] [Why? By the induction hypothesis for ǫ, used concerning and θ.] Hence (by the definition in case 3 and (i) + (ii)), (iii) f a,,ǫ+1 sup(n κ ) (θ) sup(n κ θ). Now if γ < sup(n κ θ) then for some γ(1) we have γ < γ(1) N κ θ, so letting b =: b i,j,ǫ b θ [a] b i,j,ǫ θ, it belongs to J θ [a]\j <θ [a] and we have f a,θ γ b < J<θ [a] f a,θ γ(1) b fa,θ,ǫ sup(n κ θ) hence f a,,ǫ+1 sup(n κ ) (θ) > γ; as this holds for every γ < sup(n κ θ) we have obtained (iv) f a,,ǫ+1 sup(n κ ) (θ) sup(n κ θ); together we have finished proving the inductive step for ǫ+1, hence we have proved 1. This is enough for proving b i,j,ǫ J [a]. Why? If it fails, as b i,j,ǫ N j+1 and fα a,,ǫ : α < belongs to N j+1, there is g b i,j,ǫ such that ( ) α < f a,,ǫ α b i,j,ǫ < g mod J [a]. Without loss of generality g N j+1 ; by ( ), f a,,ǫ sup(n < g mod J κ ) [a]. But g < sup(n κ θ) : θ b i,j,ǫ. Together this contradicts 1! This ends the proof of {1.31} If pcf(a) < Min(a) then 2.1 is fine and helpful. But as we do not know this, we {1.31} shall use the following substitute. {6.7A} Claim 2.4. Assume a < κ = cf(κ) < Min(a) and σ is an infinite ordinal satisfying σ + < κ. Let f, N = Ni : i < κ, N κ be as in the proof of 2.1. Then we can find {1.31} ī = i α : α σ, ā = a α : α < σ and b β [ā] : a β : β < σ such that: (a) ī is a strictly increasing continuous sequence of ordinals < κ, (b) for β < σ we have i α : α β N iβ+1 hence N iα : α β N iβ+1 and b γ [ā] : a γ and γ β N iβ+1, we can get ī (β + 1) N iβ +1 if κ succesor of regular (we just need a suitable partial square) (c) a β = N iβ pcf(a), so a β is increasing continuous with β,a a β pcf(a) and a β < κ, (d) b β [ā] a β (for a β ), (e) J [a β ] = J < [a β ]+b β [ā] (so bβ [a] and bβ [ā] + ), (f) if µ < are from a β and µ b β [ā] then bβ µ [ā] bβ [ā] (i.e., smoothness), (g) b β [ā] = a β pcf(b β [ā]) (i.e., closedness),
20 20 SAHARON SHELAH {6.7B} {6.7A} {6.7A} {6.7B} {6.7C} {6.7C} {6.7B} {6.7B} {6.7A} {6.7C.1} {6.7A} {6.7A} {6.7A} {6.7A} {6.7A} (h) if c a β,β < σ and c N iβ+1 then for some finite d a β+1 pcf(c), we have c b β+1 µ [ā]; µ d more generally (note that in (h) + if θ = ℵ 0 then we get (h)). (h) + if c a β,β < σ,c N iβ+1,θ = cf(θ) N iβ+1, then for some d N iβ+1,d a β+1 pcf θ complete (c) we have c b β+1 µ [ā] and d < θ, (i) b β [ā] increases with β. This will be proved below. Claim 2.5. In 2.4 we can also have: (1) if we let b [ā] = b σ [a] = b β [ā], a σ = a β then also for β = σ we have β<σ (b) (use N iβ +1), (c), (d), (f), (i) (2) If σ = cf(σ) > a then for β = σ also (e), (g) (3) If cf(σ) > a,c N iσ, c a σ (hence c < Min(c) and c a σ ), then for some finite d (pcf(c)) a σ we have c b µ [ā]. Similarly for θ-complete, µ d β<σ θ < cf(σ) (i.e., we have clauses (h), (h) + for β = σ). (4) We can have continuity in δ σ when cf(δ) > a, i.e., b δ [ā] = We shall prove 2.5 after proving 2.4. µ d β<δ b β [ā]. Remark ) If we would like to use length κ, use N as produced in [Sh:420, L2.6] so σ = κ. 2) Concerning 2.5, in 2.6(1) for a club E of σ = κ, we have α E b α [ā] = b [ā] a α. 3) We can also use 2.4,2.5 to give an alternative proof of part of the localization theorems similar to the one given in the Spring 89 lectures. For example: Claim ) If a < θ = cf(θ) < Min(a), for no sequence i : i < θ of members of pcf(a), do we have [ α > maxpcf{ i : i < α}]. α<θ 2) If a < Min(a), b < Min(b),b pcf(a) and pcf(a), then for some c b we have c a and pcf(c). Proof. Relying on 2.4: 1) Without loss of generality Min(a) > θ +3, let κ = θ +2, let N, N κ, ā, b (as a function), i α : α σ =: a + be as in 2.4 but we in addition assume that i : i < θ N 0. So for j < θ, c j =: { i : i < j} N 0 (so c j pcf(a) N 0 = a 0 ) hence (by clause (h) of 2.4), for some finite d j a 1 pcf(c j ) = N i1 pcf(a) pcf(c j ) we have c j d j b 1 [ā]. Assume j(1) < j(2) < θ. Now if µ a [ā] then d j(1) b 1 for some µ 0 d j(1) we have µ b 1 µ 0 [ā]; now µ 0 d j(1) pcf(c j(1) ) pcf(c j(2) ) pcf( b 1 [ā]) = (pcf(b 1 [ā]) hence (by clause (g) of 2.4 as µ 0 d j(0) N 1 ) d j(2) d j(2) forsomeµ 1 d j(2),µ 0 b 1 µ 1 [ā]. Sobyclause(f) of2.4wehaveb 1 µ 0 [ā] b 1 µ 1 [ā]hence remembering µ b 1 µ 0 [ā], we have µ b 1 µ 1 [ā]. Remembering µ was any member of
21 PCF: THE ADVANCED PCF THEOREMS E69 21 a b 1 [ā], we have a b 1 [ā] a b 1 [ā] (holds also without a d j(1) dj(1) dj(2) but not used). So a [ā] : j < θ is a -increasing sequence of subsets of a, d j b 1 but cf(θ) > a, so the sequence is eventually constant, say for j j( ). But maxpcf(a d j b 1 [ā]) maxpcf( b 1 [ā]) d j = max(maxpcf(b 1 [ā])) d j = max maxpcf{ i : i < j} < j d j = maxpcf(a b 1 [ā]) d j+1 (last equality as b j [ā] b 1 [ā] mod J <[a 1 ]). Contradiction. 2) (Like [Sh:371, 3]): If this fails choose a counterexample b with b minimal, and amongthosewithmaxpcf(b)minimalandamongthosewith {µ + : µ pcf(b)} minimal. So by the pcf theorem ( ) 1 pcf(b) has no last member ( ) 2 µ = sup[ pcf(b)] is not in pcf(b) or µ =. ( ) 3 maxpcf(b) =. Try to choose by induction on i < a +, i pcf(b), i > maxpcf{ j : j < i}. Clearly by part (1), we will be stuck at some i. Now pcf{ j : j < i} has a last member and is included in pcf(b), hence by ( ) 3 and being stuck at necessarily pcf({ j : j < i}) but it is pcf(b) +, so = maxpcf{ j : j < i}. For each j, by the choice of minimal counterexample for some b j b, we have b j a, j pcf(b j ). So pcf{ j : j < i} pcf( b j ) but frb j is a subset of b of j<i cardinality i a = a, so we are done. 2.7 {6.7D} Proof. Without loss of generality σ = ωσ (as we can use ω ω σ so ω ω σ = σ ). Let f a = f a, = fα a, : α < : pcf(a) and N i : i κ be chosen as in the proof of 2.1 and without loss of generality f a belongs to N 0. For ζ < κ we {1.31} define a ζ =: N ζ pcf(a); we also define ζ f as f aζ, α : α < : pcf(a) where a ζ is defined as follows: f aζ, α (a) if θ a,f aζ, α (θ) = fα a,(θ), (b) if θ a ζ \a and cf(α) / ( a ζ,min(a)), then f aζ, α (θ) = Min{γ < θ : fα a, b θ[a] J<θ [b θ [a]] fγ a,θ b θ [a]}, (c) if θ a ζ \a and cf(α) ( a ζ,min(a)), define f aζ, α (θ) so as to satisfy ( ) 1 in the proof of 2.1. {1.31} Now ζ f is legitimate except that we have only j<i β < γ < pcf(a) f aζ, β f aζ, γ mod J < [a ζ ]
22 22 SAHARON SHELAH {1.31} {1.31} {1.31} (insteadofstrictinequality)howeverwestillhave [f aζ, β<γ< β < f aζ, γ mod J < [a ζ ]], but this suffices. (The first statement is actually proved in [Sh:371, 3.2A], the second in [Sh:371, 3.2B]; by it also ζ f is cofinal in the required sense.) For every ζ < κ we can apply the proof of 2.1 with (N ζ pcf(a)), ζ f and N ζ+1+i : i < κ here standing for a, f, N there. In the proofof 2.1 get a club E ζ of κ (corresponding to E there and without loss of generality ζ+min(e ζ ) = Min(E ζ ) so any i < j from E ζ are O.K.). Now we can define for ζ < κ and i < j from E ζ, ζ b i,j and ζ b i,j,ǫ : ǫ < a ζ +, ǫ ζ (i,j,) : a ζ,ǫ ζ (i,j), as well as in the proof of 2.1. Let: E = {i < κ : i is a limit ordinal ( j < i)(j +j < iandj j < i) and i E j }. j<i So by [Sh:420, 1] we can find C = C δ : δ S,S {δ < κ : cf(δ) = cf(σ)} stationary, C δ a club of δ,otp(c δ ) = σ such that: (1) foreachα <,{C δ α : α nacc(c δ )}hascardinality< κ. Ifκissuccessor of regular, then we can get [γ C α C β C α γ = C β γ] and (2) for every club E of κ for stationarily many δ S,C δ E. {1.31} {1.31} {6.7A} {1.31} Without loss of generality C N 0. For some δ,c δ E, and let {j ζ : ζ ω 2 σ} enumerate C δ {δ }. So j ζ : ζ ω 2 σ is a strictly increasing continuous sequence of ordinals from E κ such that j ǫ : ǫ ζ N jζ+1 and if, e.g., κ is a successor of regulars then j ε : ε ζ N jζ +1. Let j(ζ) = j ζ and for l {0,2} let i l (ζ) = i l ζ =: j ω (1+ζ),a l ζ = Ni l ζ pcf(a), and ā l =: a l ζ : ζ < σ,l b ζ [ā] =: i l (ζ) b j(ωl ζ+1),j(ω l ζ+2),ǫ ζ (j(ω l ζ+1),j(ω l ζ+2)). Recall that σ = ωσ so σ = ω 2 σ; if the value of l does not matter we omit it. Most of the requirements follow immediately by the proof of 2.1, as for each ζ < σ, we have b ζ, b ζ [ā] : a ζ are as in the proof (hence conclusion of 2.1) and belongs to N iβ +3 N iβ+1. We are left (for proving 2.4) with proving clauses (h) + and (i) (remember that (h) is a special case of (h) + choosing θ = ℵ 0 ). For proving clause (i) note that for ζ < ξ < κ, f aζ, α f aξ, α hence ζ b i,j ξ b i,j. Now we can prove by induction on ǫ that ζ b i,j,ǫ ξ b i,j,ǫ for every a ζ (check the definition in ( ) 7 in the proof of 2.1) and the conclusion follows. Instead of proving (h) + we prove an apparently weaker version (h) below, but having (h) for the case l = 0 gives (h) + for l = 2 so this is enough [[then note that ī = i ω 2 ζ : ζ < σ, ā = a ω 2 ζ : ζ < σ, N i(ω 2 ζ) : ζ < σ, b ω2 ζ [ā ] : ζ < σ, a ζ = a ω 2 ζ will exemplify the conclusion]] where: (h) if c a β, β < σ, c N iβ+1,θ = cf(θ) N iβ+1 then for some frd N iβ+ω+1 +1 satisfying d a β+ω pcf θ complete (c) we have c b β+ω µ [ā] and d < θ. µ d
23 PCF: THE ADVANCED PCF THEOREMS E69 23 Proof. Proof of (h) So let θ,β,c be given; let b µ [ā] : µ pcf(c) ( N iβ+1 ) be a generating sequence. We define by induction on n < ω, A n, (c η, η ) : η A n such that: (a) A 0 = { },c = c, = maxpcf(c), (b) A n n θ, A n < θ, (c) if η A n+1 then η n A n, c η c η n, η < η n and η = maxpcf(c η ), (d) A n, (c η, η ) : η A n belongs to N iβ+1+n hence η N iβ+1+n, (e) if η A n and η pcf θ-complete (c η ) and c η b β+1+n η [ā] then ( ν)[ν A n+1 andη ν ν = ηˆ 0 ] and c ηˆ 0 = c η \b β+1+n η [ā] (so ηˆ 0 = maxpcf(c ηˆ 0 ) < η = maxpcf(c η ), (f) if η A n and η / pcf θ-complete (c η ) then c η = {b γˆ i [c] : i < i n < θ,ηˆ i A n+1 }, and if ν = ηˆ i A n+1 then c ν = b ν [c], (g) if η A n, and η pcf θ-complete (c η ) but c η b β+1 n n [ā], then ( ν)[η ν A n+1 ]. There is no problem to carry the definition (we use 2.8(1), the point is that c {6.7F} N iβ+1+n implies b (c) : pcf θ [c] N iβ+1+n and as there is d as in 2.8(1), there {6.7F} is one in N iβ+1+n+1 so d a β+1+n+1 ). Now let d n =: { η : η A n and η pcf θ-complete (c η )} and d =: d n ; we shall show that it is as required. n<ω The main point is c b β+ω [ā]; note that d henceitsufficestoshowc [ η d,η A n b β+1+n η n<ω b β+1+n d n [ā] b β+ω [ā]] η [ā],soassumeθ c\ n<ω b β+1+n d n and we choose by induction on n, η n A n such that η 0 =<>, η n+1 n = η n and θ c η ; by clauses (e) + (f) above this is possible and maxpcf(c ηn ) : n < ω is (strictly) decreasing, contradiction. The minor point is d < θ; if θ > ℵ 0 note that A n < θ and θ = cf(θ) clearly n d n A n < θ +ℵ 1 = θ. If θ = ℵ 0 (i.e. clause (h)) we should show that n A n finite; the proof is as above noting that the clause (f) is vacuous now. So n < ω A n = 1 and for some n n A n =, so n A n is finite. Another minor point is d N iβ+ω+1 ; this holds as the construction is unique from c, b µ [c] : µ pcf(c), N j : j < i β+ω, i j : j β +ω, (a i(ζ), b ζ [ā] : a i(ζ) ) : ζ β + ω ; no outside information is used so (A n, (c η, η ) : η A n ) : n < ω N iβ+ω+1, so (using a choice function) really d N iβ+ω [ā],
24 {6.7B} {6.7} {6.7F} {6.7G} {6.7C.1} {6.7A} {6.7A} {6.7A} {6.7F} {6.7A} {6.7F} {6.7A} 24 SAHARON SHELAH Proof. Let b [ā] = b σ = b β [a β] and a σ = a ζ. Part (1) is straightforward. β<σ ζ<σ For part (2), for clause (g), for β = σ, the inclusion is straightforward; so assume µ a β pcf(b β [ā]). Then by 2.4(c) for some β 0 < β, we have µ a β0, {6.7A} and by 2.7 (which depends on 2.4 only) for some β 1 < β, µ pcf(b β1 [ā]); by {6.7C.1} {6.7A} monotonicity without loss of generality β 0 = β 1, by clause (g) of 2.4 applied to β 0, {6.7A} µ b β0 [ā]. Hence by clause (i) of 2.4, µ bβ [ā], thus proving the other inclusion. {6.7A} The proof of clause (e) (for 2.5(2)) is similar, and also 2.5(3). For??(B)(4) for δ < σ,cf(δ) > a redefine b δ [ā] as i<α β<δ Claim 2.8. Let θ be regular. 0) If α < θ,pcf θ-complete ( a i ) = pcf θ-complete (a i ). i<α b β+1 [ā] ) If b [a] : pcf(a) is a generating sequence for a, c a, then for some d pcf θ-complete (c) we have: d < θ and c b θ [a]. 2) If a c < Min(a),c pcf θ-complete (a), pcf θ-complete (c) then pcf θ-complete (a). 3) In (2) we can weaken a c < Min(a) to a < Min(a), c < Min(c). Proof. (0) and (1): Left to the reader. 2) See [Sh:345b, ]. 3) Similarly. 2.8 Claim ) Let θ be regular a. We cannot find α pcf θ-complete (a) for α < a + such that i > suppcf θ-complete ({ j : j < i}). 2) Assume θ a,c pcf θ-complete (a) (and c < Min(c); of course a < Min(a)). If pcf θ-complete (c) then for some d c we have d a and pcf θ-complete (d). Proof. 1) If θ = ℵ 0 we already know it (see 2.7), so assume θ > ℵ 0. We use 2.4 with {θ, i : i < a + } N 0, σ = a +, κ = a +3 where, without loss of generality, κ < Min(a). For each α < a + by (h) + of 2.4 there is a α N i1,d α pcf θ-complete ({ i : i < α}), d α < θ such that { i : i < α} b 1 θ [ā]; hence by clause (g) of 2.4 θ d α and part (0) Claim 2.8 we have a 1 pcf θ-complete ({ i : i < α}) [ā]. So θ a θ d α b 1 θ for α < β < a +, d α a 1 pcf θ-complete { i : i < α} a 1 pcf θ-complete { i : i < β} b 1 θ [ā]. As the sequence is smooth (i.e., clause (f) of 2.4) clearly θ d β α < β b 1 µ [ā] b 1 µ [ā]. µ d α µ d β So b 1 µ [ā] a : α < a + is a non-decreasing sequence of subsets of a of µ d α length a +, hence for some α( ) < a + we have: ( ) 1 α( ) α < a + b 1 µ[ā] a = b 1 µ[ā] a. µ d α µ d α( ) If τ a 1 pcf θ-complete ({ i : i < α}) then τ pcf θ-complete (a) (by parts (2),(3) of Claim 2.8), and τ b 1 µ τ [ā] for some µ τ d α so b 1 τ[ā] b 1 µ τ [ā], also τ pcf θ-complete (b 1 τ [ā] a) (by clause (e) of 2.4), hence τ pcf θ-complete (b 1 τ[ā] a) pcf θ-complete (b 1 µ τ [ā] a) pcf θ-complete ( µ d α b 1 µ [ā] a).
25 PCF: THE ADVANCED PCF THEOREMS E69 25 So a 1 pcf θ-complete ({ i : i < α}) pcf θ-complete ( µ d α b 1 µ [ā] a). But for each α < a + we have α > suppcf θ-complete ({ i : i < α}), whereas d α pcf σ-complete { i : i < α}, hence α > supd α hence ( ) 2 α > sup µ dα maxpcf(b 1 µ[ā]) suppcf θ-complete ( b 1 µ[ā] a). µ d α On the other hand, ( ) 3 α pcf θ-complete { i : i < α+1} pcf θ-complete ( b 1 µ [ā] a). µ d α+1 For α = α( ) we get contradiction by ( ) 1 +( ) 2 +( ) 3. 2) Assume a,c, form a counterexample with minimal. Without lossof generality a +3 < Min(a) and = maxpcf(a) and = maxpcf(c) (just let a =: b [a],c =: c pcf θ [a ]; if / pcf θ-complete (c ) then necessarily pcf(c\c ) (by 2.8(0)) and {6.7F} similarly c\c pcf θ-complete (a\a ) hence by parts (2),(3) of Claim 2.8 we have {6.7F} pcf θ-complete (a\a ), contradiction). Also without loss of generality / c. Let κ,σ, N, i α = i(α) : α σ,ā = a i : i σ be as in 2.4 with a N 0,c N 0, N 0,σ = a +,κ = a +3 < Min(a). We {6.7A} choose by induction on ǫ < a +, ǫ,d ǫ such that: (a) ǫ a ω2 ǫ+ω+1,d ǫ N i(ω2 ǫ+ω+1), (b) ǫ c, (c) d ǫ a ω 2 ǫ+ω+1 pcf θ-complete ({ ζ : ζ < ǫ}), (d) d ǫ < θ, (e) { ζ : ζ < ǫ} (f) ǫ / pcf θ-complete ( b ω 2 ǫ+ω+1 θ θ d ǫ [ā], b ω 2 ǫ+ω+1 θ θ d ǫ [ā]). Foreveryǫ < a + wefirstchoosed ǫ asthe< χ-firstelementsatisfying(c)+(d)+(e) andthenifpossible ǫ asthe< χ-firstelementsatisfying(b)+(f). Itiseasytocheck the requirements and in fact ζ : ζ < ǫ N ω 2 ǫ+1, d ζ : ζ < ǫ N ω 2 ǫ+1 (so clause (a) will hold). But why can we choose at all? Now / pcf θ-complete { ζ : ζ < ǫ} as a,c, form a counterexample with minimal and ǫ < a + (by 2.8(3)). As {6.7F} = maxpcf(a) necessarily pcf θ-complete ({ ζ : ζ < ǫ}) hence d ǫ (by clause (c)). By part (0) of Claim 2.8 (and clause (a)) we know: {6.7F} pcf θ-complete [ b ω 2 ǫ+ω+1 µ [ā]] = pcf θ-complete [b ω 2 +ω+1 µ [ā]] µ d ǫ µ d ǫ (µ+1) µ d ǫ (note µ = maxpcf(b β µ[ā])). So / pcf θ-complete ( b ω 2 ǫ+ω+1 µ [ā]) hence by part (0) µ d ǫ of Claim 2.8 c b ω 2 ǫ+ω+1 µ [ā] so ǫ exists. Now d ǫ exists by 2.4 clause (h) +. µ d ǫ Now clearly a 2 ǫ+ω+1 µ [ā] : ǫ < a + is non-decreasing(as in the earlier µ d ǫ b ω proof) hence eventually constant, say for ǫ ǫ( ) (where ǫ( ) < a + ). But {6.7A} {6.7F}
26 {6.7A} {6.7A} 26 SAHARON SHELAH (α) ǫ b ω 2 ǫ+ω+1 µ d ǫ+1 µ [ā] [clause (e) in the choice of ǫ,d ǫ ], (β) b ω2 ǫ+ω+1 ǫ [ā] µ d ǫ+1 b ω2 ǫ+ω+1 µ [ā] [by clause (f) of 2.4 and (α) alone], (γ) ǫ pcf θ-complete (a) [as ǫ c and a hypothesis], (δ) ǫ pcf θ-complete (b ω2 ǫ+ω+1 ǫ [ā]) [by (γ) above and clause (e) of 2.4], (ǫ) ǫ / pcf(a\b ω2 ǫ+ω+1 ǫ ), (ζ) ǫ pcf θ-complete (a b ω 2 ǫ+ω+1 µ d ǫ+1 µ [ā]) [by (δ)+(ǫ)+(β)]. But for ǫ = ǫ( ), the statement (ζ) contradicts the choice of ǫ( ) and clause (f) above. 2.9
Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit
Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit Ting Zhang Stanford May 11, 2001 Stanford, 5/11/2001 1 Outline Ordinal Classification Ordinal Addition Ordinal Multiplication Ordinal
ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER
ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER Abstract. We define ordinal arithmetic and show laws of Left- Monotonicity, Associativity, Distributivity, some minor related properties and the Cantor Normal Form.
Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set
Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set May 6, 2008 Abstract A set of first-order formulas, whatever the cardinality of the set of symbols, is equivalent to an independent
Example Sheet 3 Solutions
Example Sheet 3 Solutions. i Regular Sturm-Liouville. ii Singular Sturm-Liouville mixed boundary conditions. iii Not Sturm-Liouville ODE is not in Sturm-Liouville form. iv Regular Sturm-Liouville note
2 Composition. Invertible Mappings
Arkansas Tech University MATH 4033: Elementary Modern Algebra Dr. Marcel B. Finan Composition. Invertible Mappings In this section we discuss two procedures for creating new mappings from old ones, namely,
ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II
ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II 2014/2015: Semester II Tutorial 7 1. Let X be a sample from a population P and consider testing hypotheses H 0 : P = P 0 versus H 1 : P = P 1, where P j is a known
EE512: Error Control Coding
EE512: Error Control Coding Solution for Assignment on Finite Fields February 16, 2007 1. (a) Addition and Multiplication tables for GF (5) and GF (7) are shown in Tables 1 and 2. + 0 1 2 3 4 0 0 1 2 3
C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions
C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions Paul Liu November 15, 2007 Note that these are sample solutions only; in many cases there were many acceptable answers. 1 Reynolds Problem 10.1 1.1 Normal-order
arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 15 Oct 1996
ISRAEL JOURNAL OF MATHEMATICS 95 (1996), 61 114 FURTHER CARDINAL ARITHMETIC BY arxiv:math/9610226v1 [math.lo] 15 Oct 1996 Saharon Shelah Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Jerusalem,
Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in
Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in : tail in X, head in A nowhere-zero Γ-flow is a Γ-circulation such that
Splitting stationary sets from weak forms of Choice
Splitting stationary sets from weak forms of Choice Paul Larson and Saharon Shelah February 16, 2008 Abstract Working in the context of restricted forms of the Axiom of Choice, we consider the problem
Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor
Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor Given f L 1 T 1 ), we consider the partial sums of the Fourier series of f: N 1) S N fθ) = ˆfk)e ikθ. k= N A calculation gives the Dirichlet formula
Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs
Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs Who? Nichole Schimanski When? July 27, 2011 Graphs A graph, G, consists of a vertex set, V (G), and an edge set, E(G). V (G) is any finite set E(G) is
NOTES ON SQUARES, SCALES, AND REFLECTION
NOTES ON SQUARES, SCALES, AND REFLECTION MAXWELL LEVINE 1. Some Basic Facts Proposition 1. If κ
Cardinals. Y = n Y n. Define h: X Y by f(x) if x X n X n+1 and n is even h(x) = g
Cardinals 1. Introduction to Cardinals We work in the base theory ZF. The definitions and many (but not all) of the basic theorems do not require AC; we will indicate explicitly when we are using choice.
Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016
Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016 Silvio Capobianco Exercise 1.7 Let H(n) = J(n + 1) J(n). Equation (1.8) tells us that H(2n) = 2, and H(2n+1) = J(2n+2) J(2n+1) = (2J(n+1) 1) (2J(n)+1)
ω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 ω ω + 1 ω + 2 ω + 3 ω + 4 ω2 ω2 + 1 ω2 + 2 ω2 + 3 ω3 ω3 + 1 ω3 + 2 ω4 ω4 + 1 ω5 ω 2 ω 2 + 1 ω 2 + 2 ω 2 + ω ω 2 + ω + 1 ω 2 + ω2 ω 2 2 ω 2 2 + 1 ω 2 2 + ω ω 2 3 ω 3 ω 3 + 1 ω 3 + ω ω 3 +
On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions.
On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions. Moti Gitik December 31, 2015 Abstract Every set of ordinals of cardinality κ in a Prikry extension with a measure over κ contains an old set of arbitrary
Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers
Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers There are two kinds of number.. Ordinal numbers (0th), st, 2nd, 3rd, 4th, 5th,..., ω, ω +,... ω2, ω2+,... ω 2... answers to the question What position is... in a sequence? What
arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 21 Jun 2010
BLACK BOXES arxiv:0812.0656v2 [math.lo] 21 Jun 2010 SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We shall deal comprehensively with Black Boxes, the intention being that provably in ZFC we have a sequence of guesses of extra
SINGULAR CARDINALS AND SQUARE PROPERTIES
SINGULAR CARDINALS AND SQUARE PROPERTIES MENACHEM MAGIDOR AND DIMA SINAPOVA Abstract. We analyze the effect of singularizing cardinals on square properties. By work of Džamonja-Shelah and of Gitik, if
3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β
3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS Page Theorem cos(αβ cos α cos β -sin α cos(α-β cos α cos β sin α NOTE: cos(αβ cos α cos β cos(α-β cos α -cos β Proof of cos(α-β cos α cos β sin α Let s use a unit circle
4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1)
84 CHAPTER 4. STATIONARY TS MODELS 4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(,) This section is an introduction to a wide class of models ARMA(p,q) which we will consider in more detail later in this
ON INCOMPACTNESS FOR CHROMATIC NUMBER OF GRAPHS SH1006 SAHARON SHELAH
ON INCOMPACTNESS FOR CHROMATIC NUMBER OF GRAPHS SH1006 SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We deal with incompactness. Assume the existence of non-reflecting stationary subset of the regular cardinal λ of cofinality
2. Let H 1 and H 2 be Hilbert spaces and let T : H 1 H 2 be a bounded linear operator. Prove that [T (H 1 )] = N (T ). (6p)
Uppsala Universitet Matematiska Institutionen Andreas Strömbergsson Prov i matematik Funktionalanalys Kurs: F3B, F4Sy, NVP 2005-03-08 Skrivtid: 9 14 Tillåtna hjälpmedel: Manuella skrivdon, Kreyszigs bok
A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation
International Mathematical Forum, 5, 2010, no. 67, 3301-3307 A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy Equivalence Relation D. K. Basnet Dept. of Mathematics, Assam University Silchar-788011, Assam, India dkbasnet@rediffmail.com
The challenges of non-stable predicates
The challenges of non-stable predicates Consider a non-stable predicate Φ encoding, say, a safety property. We want to determine whether Φ holds for our program. The challenges of non-stable predicates
Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests
Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests Side-Note: So far we have seen a few approaches for creating tests such as Neyman-Pearson Lemma ( most powerful tests of H 0 : θ = θ 0 vs H 1 :
arxiv: v4 [math.lo] 15 Jun 2010
DIAMONDS arxiv:0711.3030v4 [math.lo] 15 Jun 2010 SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. If λ = χ + = 2 χ > ℵ 1 then diamond on λ holds. Moreover, if λ = χ + = 2 χ and S {δ < λ : cf(δ) cf(χ)} is stationary then S holds.
derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates
derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates swapnizzle 03-03- :5:43 We begin by recognizing the familiar conversion from rectangular to spherical coordinates (note that φ is used
Finite Field Problems: Solutions
Finite Field Problems: Solutions 1. Let f = x 2 +1 Z 11 [x] and let F = Z 11 [x]/(f), a field. Let Solution: F =11 2 = 121, so F = 121 1 = 120. The possible orders are the divisors of 120. Solution: The
Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude
Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude Jan Behrens 2012-12-31 In this paper we shall provide a method to approximate distances between two points on earth
Partial Differential Equations in Biology The boundary element method. March 26, 2013
The boundary element method March 26, 203 Introduction and notation The problem: u = f in D R d u = ϕ in Γ D u n = g on Γ N, where D = Γ D Γ N, Γ D Γ N = (possibly, Γ D = [Neumann problem] or Γ N = [Dirichlet
Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests
Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests Shirsendu Mukherjee Department of Statistics, Asutosh College, Kolkata, India. shirsendu st@yahoo.co.in So far we have treated the testing of one-sided
Matrices and Determinants
Matrices and Determinants SUBJECTIVE PROBLEMS: Q 1. For what value of k do the following system of equations possess a non-trivial (i.e., not all zero) solution over the set of rationals Q? x + ky + 3z
k A = [k, k]( )[a 1, a 2 ] = [ka 1,ka 2 ] 4For the division of two intervals of confidence in R +
Chapter 3. Fuzzy Arithmetic 3- Fuzzy arithmetic: ~Addition(+) and subtraction (-): Let A = [a and B = [b, b in R If x [a and y [b, b than x+y [a +b +b Symbolically,we write A(+)B = [a (+)[b, b = [a +b
Econ 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1
Eon : Fall 8 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 Email questions or omments to Dan Fetter Problem. Let X be a salar with density f(x, θ) (θx + θ) [ x ] with θ. (a) Find the most powerful level α test
Chapter 2. Ordinals, well-founded relations.
Chapter 2. Ordinals, well-founded relations. 2.1. Well-founded Relations. We start with some definitions and rapidly reach the notion of a well-ordered set. Definition. For any X and any binary relation
Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequality for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x, y, z X.
Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequalit for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x,, z X. Prove that d(x, z) d(, z) d(x, ). (ii): Reverse triangle inequalit for norms:
SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES G11LMA Linear Mathematics Examination Solutions
SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES GLMA Linear Mathematics 00- Examination Solutions. (a) i. ( + 5i)( i) = (6 + 5) + (5 )i = + i. Real part is, imaginary part is. (b) ii. + 5i i ( + 5i)( + i) = ( i)( + i)
Homework 3 Solutions
Homework 3 Solutions Igor Yanovsky (Math 151A TA) Problem 1: Compute the absolute error and relative error in approximations of p by p. (Use calculator!) a) p π, p 22/7; b) p π, p 3.141. Solution: For
Solution Series 9. i=1 x i and i=1 x i.
Lecturer: Prof. Dr. Mete SONER Coordinator: Yilin WANG Solution Series 9 Q1. Let α, β >, the p.d.f. of a beta distribution with parameters α and β is { Γ(α+β) Γ(α)Γ(β) f(x α, β) xα 1 (1 x) β 1 for < x
Lecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic
Lecture 2 Soundness and completeness of propositional logic February 9, 2004 1 Overview Review of natural deduction. Soundness and completeness. Semantics of propositional formulas. Soundness proof. Completeness
Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations. ------------------ ----------------------------- -----------------
Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations. 1. Sin ( ) = a) b) c) d) Ans b. Solution : Method 1. Ans a: 17 > 1 a) is rejected. w.k.t Sin ( sin ) = d is rejected. If sin
Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics
Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics Nov 1, 01 In this lecture we examine root systems from an axiomatic point of view. 1 Reflections If v R n, then it determines a hyperplane, denoted P v, through the
Section 9.2 Polar Equations and Graphs
180 Section 9. Polar Equations and Graphs In this section, we will be graphing polar equations on a polar grid. In the first few examples, we will write the polar equation in rectangular form to help identify
Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees
Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees Thomas F. Kent Andrea Sorbi Università degli Studi di Siena Italia July 18, 2007 Goal: Introduce a form of Σ 0 2-permitting for the enumeration degrees. Till now,
5. Choice under Uncertainty
5. Choice under Uncertainty Daisuke Oyama Microeconomics I May 23, 2018 Formulations von Neumann-Morgenstern (1944/1947) X: Set of prizes Π: Set of probability distributions on X : Preference relation
Problem Set 3: Solutions
CMPSCI 69GG Applied Information Theory Fall 006 Problem Set 3: Solutions. [Cover and Thomas 7.] a Define the following notation, C I p xx; Y max X; Y C I p xx; Ỹ max I X; Ỹ We would like to show that C
MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS
MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS FUMIE NAKAOKA AND NOBUYUKI ODA Received 20 December 2005; Revised 28 May 2006; Accepted 6 August 2006 Some properties of minimal closed sets and maximal closed
CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS
CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS Shiah-Sen Wang The graphs are prepared by Chien-Lun Lai Based on : Precalculus: Mathematics for Calculus by J. Stuwart, L. Redin & S. Watson, 6th edition, 01, Brooks/Cole Chapter
Solutions to Exercise Sheet 5
Solutions to Eercise Sheet 5 jacques@ucsd.edu. Let X and Y be random variables with joint pdf f(, y) = 3y( + y) where and y. Determine each of the following probabilities. Solutions. a. P (X ). b. P (X
Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval
Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential Equations Let a (t), a 2 (t),..., a nn (t), b (t), b 2 (t),..., b n (t) be continuous functions on the interval I. The system of n first-order differential equations
ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 19/5/2007
Οδηγίες: Να απαντηθούν όλες οι ερωτήσεις. Αν κάπου κάνετε κάποιες υποθέσεις να αναφερθούν στη σχετική ερώτηση. Όλα τα αρχεία που αναφέρονται στα προβλήματα βρίσκονται στον ίδιο φάκελο με το εκτελέσιμο
Μηχανική Μάθηση Hypothesis Testing
ΕΛΛΗΝΙΚΗ ΔΗΜΟΚΡΑΤΙΑ ΠΑΝΕΠΙΣΤΗΜΙΟ ΚΡΗΤΗΣ Μηχανική Μάθηση Hypothesis Testing Γιώργος Μπορμπουδάκης Τμήμα Επιστήμης Υπολογιστών Procedure 1. Form the null (H 0 ) and alternative (H 1 ) hypothesis 2. Consider
12. Radon-Nikodym Theorem
Tutorial 12: Radon-Nikodym Theorem 1 12. Radon-Nikodym Theorem In the following, (Ω, F) is an arbitrary measurable space. Definition 96 Let μ and ν be two (possibly complex) measures on (Ω, F). We say
Phys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required)
Phys460.nb 81 ψ n (t) is still the (same) eigenstate of H But for tdependent H. The answer is NO. 5.5.5. Solution for the tdependent Schrodinger s equation If we assume that at time t 0, the electron starts
A Two-Sided Laplace Inversion Algorithm with Computable Error Bounds and Its Applications in Financial Engineering
Electronic Companion A Two-Sie Laplace Inversion Algorithm with Computable Error Bouns an Its Applications in Financial Engineering Ning Cai, S. G. Kou, Zongjian Liu HKUST an Columbia University Appenix
6.1. Dirac Equation. Hamiltonian. Dirac Eq.
6.1. Dirac Equation Ref: M.Kaku, Quantum Field Theory, Oxford Univ Press (1993) η μν = η μν = diag(1, -1, -1, -1) p 0 = p 0 p = p i = -p i p μ p μ = p 0 p 0 + p i p i = E c 2 - p 2 = (m c) 2 H = c p 2
Knaster-Reichbach Theorem for 2 κ
Knaster-Reichbach Theorem for 2 κ Micha l Korch February 9, 2018 In the recent years the theory of the generalized Cantor and Baire spaces was extensively developed (see, e.g. [1], [2], [6], [4] and many
The Simply Typed Lambda Calculus
Type Inference Instead of writing type annotations, can we use an algorithm to infer what the type annotations should be? That depends on the type system. For simple type systems the answer is yes, and
THE GENERAL INDUCTIVE ARGUMENT FOR MEASURE ANALYSES WITH ADDITIVE ORDINAL ALGEBRAS
THE GENERAL INDUCTIVE ARGUMENT FOR MEASURE ANALYSES WITH ADDITIVE ORDINAL ALGEBRAS STEFAN BOLD, BENEDIKT LÖWE In [BoLö ] we gave a survey of measure analyses under AD, discussed the general theory of order
Section 8.3 Trigonometric Equations
99 Section 8. Trigonometric Equations Objective 1: Solve Equations Involving One Trigonometric Function. In this section and the next, we will exple how to solving equations involving trigonometric functions.
Second Order RLC Filters
ECEN 60 Circuits/Electronics Spring 007-0-07 P. Mathys Second Order RLC Filters RLC Lowpass Filter A passive RLC lowpass filter (LPF) circuit is shown in the following schematic. R L C v O (t) Using phasor
Tridiagonal matrices. Gérard MEURANT. October, 2008
Tridiagonal matrices Gérard MEURANT October, 2008 1 Similarity 2 Cholesy factorizations 3 Eigenvalues 4 Inverse Similarity Let α 1 ω 1 β 1 α 2 ω 2 T =......... β 2 α 1 ω 1 β 1 α and β i ω i, i = 1,...,
HOMEWORK 4 = G. In order to plot the stress versus the stretch we define a normalized stretch:
HOMEWORK 4 Problem a For the fast loading case, we want to derive the relationship between P zz and λ z. We know that the nominal stress is expressed as: P zz = ψ λ z where λ z = λ λ z. Therefore, applying
Lecture 21: Properties and robustness of LSE
Lecture 21: Properties and robustness of LSE BLUE: Robustness of LSE against normality We now study properties of l τ β and σ 2 under assumption A2, i.e., without the normality assumption on ε. From Theorem
ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC = DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION #2. h 0 h h 0 h h 0 ( ) g k = g 0 + g 1 + g g 2009 =?
Teko Classes IITJEE/AIEEE Maths by SUHAAG SIR, Bhopal, Ph (0755) 3 00 000 www.tekoclasses.com ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION # Question Type A.Single Correct Type Q. (A) Sol least
de Rham Theorem May 10, 2016
de Rham Theorem May 10, 2016 Stokes formula and the integration morphism: Let M = σ Σ σ be a smooth triangulated manifold. Fact: Stokes formula σ ω = σ dω holds, e.g. for simplices. It can be used to define
SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS
Sahand Communications in Mathematical Analysis (SCMA) Vol. 3 No. 1 (2016), 21-27 http://scma.maragheh.ac.ir SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS BAYAZ DARABY 1 AND JAVAD JAFARI 2 Abstract. In the mathematical
P-IDEAL DICHOTOMY AND WEAK SQUARES
P-IDEAL DICHOTOMY AND WEAK SQUARES DILIP RAGHAVAN Abstract. We answer a question of Cummings and Magidor by proving that the P-ideal dichotomy of Todorčević refutes κ,ω for any uncountable κ. We also show
( y) Partial Differential Equations
Partial Dierential Equations Linear P.D.Es. contains no owers roducts o the deendent variables / an o its derivatives can occasionall be solved. Consider eamle ( ) a (sometimes written as a ) we can integrate
Iterated trilinear fourier integrals with arbitrary symbols
Cornell University ICM 04, Satellite Conference in Harmonic Analysis, Chosun University, Gwangju, Korea August 6, 04 Motivation the Coifman-Meyer theorem with classical paraproduct(979) B(f, f )(x) :=
Main source: "Discrete-time systems and computer control" by Α. ΣΚΟΔΡΑΣ ΨΗΦΙΑΚΟΣ ΕΛΕΓΧΟΣ ΔΙΑΛΕΞΗ 4 ΔΙΑΦΑΝΕΙΑ 1
Main source: "Discrete-time systems and computer control" by Α. ΣΚΟΔΡΑΣ ΨΗΦΙΑΚΟΣ ΕΛΕΓΧΟΣ ΔΙΑΛΕΞΗ 4 ΔΙΑΦΑΝΕΙΑ 1 A Brief History of Sampling Research 1915 - Edmund Taylor Whittaker (1873-1956) devised a
Απόκριση σε Μοναδιαία Ωστική Δύναμη (Unit Impulse) Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο. Απόστολος Σ.
Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο The time integral of a force is referred to as impulse, is determined by and is obtained from: Newton s 2 nd Law of motion states that the action
SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM
SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM Solutions to Question 1 a) The cumulative distribution function of T conditional on N n is Pr T t N n) Pr max X 1,..., X N ) t N n) Pr max
Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II
Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II October 18, 2012 1 Review First let us recall the situation. Let g be a simple algebra, with maximal toral subalgebra h (which we are calling a CSA, or Cartan Subalgebra).
Fourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics
Fourier Series MATH 211, Calculus II J. Robert Buchanan Department of Mathematics Spring 2018 Introduction Not all functions can be represented by Taylor series. f (k) (c) A Taylor series f (x) = (x c)
= λ 1 1 e. = λ 1 =12. has the properties e 1. e 3,V(Y
Stat 50 Homework Solutions Spring 005. (a λ λ λ 44 (b trace( λ + λ + λ 0 (c V (e x e e λ e e λ e (λ e by definition, the eigenvector e has the properties e λ e and e e. (d λ e e + λ e e + λ e e 8 6 4 4
Online Appendix I. 1 1+r ]}, Bψ = {ψ : Y E A S S}, B W = +(1 s)[1 m (1,0) (b, e, a, ψ (0,a ) (e, a, s); q, ψ, W )]}, (29) exp( U(d,a ) (i, x; q)
Online Appendix I Appendix D Additional Existence Proofs Denote B q = {q : A E A S [0, +r ]}, Bψ = {ψ : Y E A S S}, B W = {W : I E A S R}. I slightly abuse the notation by defining B q (L q ) the subset
forms This gives Remark 1. How to remember the above formulas: Substituting these into the equation we obtain with
Week 03: C lassification of S econd- Order L inear Equations In last week s lectures we have illustrated how to obtain the general solutions of first order PDEs using the method of characteristics. We
9.09. # 1. Area inside the oval limaçon r = cos θ. To graph, start with θ = 0 so r = 6. Compute dr
9.9 #. Area inside the oval limaçon r = + cos. To graph, start with = so r =. Compute d = sin. Interesting points are where d vanishes, or at =,,, etc. For these values of we compute r:,,, and the values
CHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS
CHAPTER 5 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS EXERCISE 104 Page 8 1. Find the positive root of the equation x + 3x 5 = 0, correct to 3 significant figures, using the method of bisection. Let f(x) =
Lecture 34 Bootstrap confidence intervals
Lecture 34 Bootstrap confidence intervals Confidence Intervals θ: an unknown parameter of interest We want to find limits θ and θ such that Gt = P nˆθ θ t If G 1 1 α is known, then P θ θ = P θ θ = 1 α
Homomorphism in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Automata
International Journal of Fuzzy Mathematics Systems. ISSN 2248-9940 Volume 3, Number 1 (2013), pp. 39-45 Research India Publications http://www.ripublication.com/ijfms.htm Homomorphism in Intuitionistic
Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets
Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets S K Mala #1, Dr. MM Shanmugapriya *2 1 PhD Scholar in Mathematics, Karpagam University, Coimbatore, Tamilnadu- 641021 Assistant Professor of Mathematics,
Completeness Theorem for System AS1
11 The Completeness Theorem for System AS1 1. Introduction...2 2. Previous Definitions...2 3. Deductive Consistency...2 4. Maximal Consistent Sets...5 5. Lindenbaum s Lemma...6 6. Every Maximal Consistent
Theorem 8 Let φ be the most powerful size α test of H
Testing composite hypotheses Θ = Θ 0 Θ c 0 H 0 : θ Θ 0 H 1 : θ Θ c 0 Definition 16 A test φ is a uniformly most powerful (UMP) level α test for H 0 vs. H 1 if φ has level α and for any other level α test
Some new generalized topologies via hereditary classes. Key Words:hereditary generalized topological space, A κ(h,µ)-sets, κµ -topology.
Bol. Soc. Paran. Mat. (3s.) v. 30 2 (2012): 71 77. c SPM ISSN-2175-1188 on line ISSN-00378712 in press SPM: www.spm.uem.br/bspm doi:10.5269/bspm.v30i2.13793 Some new generalized topologies via hereditary
Generating Set of the Complete Semigroups of Binary Relations
Applied Mathematics 06 7 98-07 Published Online January 06 in SciRes http://wwwscirporg/journal/am http://dxdoiorg/036/am067009 Generating Set of the Complete Semigroups of Binary Relations Yasha iasamidze
SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM
SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM Solutions to Question 1 a) The cumulative distribution function of T conditional on N n is Pr (T t N n) Pr (max (X 1,..., X N ) t N n) Pr (max
Reminders: linear functions
Reminders: linear functions Let U and V be vector spaces over the same field F. Definition A function f : U V is linear if for every u 1, u 2 U, f (u 1 + u 2 ) = f (u 1 ) + f (u 2 ), and for every u U
6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes
122 CHAPTER 6. ARMA MODELS 6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes The purpose of forecasting is to predict future values of a TS based on the data collected to the present. In this section we will discuss a linear
STAT200C: Hypothesis Testing
STAT200C: Hypothesis Testing Zhaoxia Yu Spring 2017 Some Definitions A hypothesis is a statement about a population parameter. The two complementary hypotheses in a hypothesis testing are the null hypothesis
Homework 8 Model Solution Section
MATH 004 Homework Solution Homework 8 Model Solution Section 14.5 14.6. 14.5. Use the Chain Rule to find dz where z cosx + 4y), x 5t 4, y 1 t. dz dx + dy y sinx + 4y)0t + 4) sinx + 4y) 1t ) 0t + 4t ) sinx
w o = R 1 p. (1) R = p =. = 1
Πανεπιστήµιο Κρήτης - Τµήµα Επιστήµης Υπολογιστών ΗΥ-570: Στατιστική Επεξεργασία Σήµατος 205 ιδάσκων : Α. Μουχτάρης Τριτη Σειρά Ασκήσεων Λύσεις Ασκηση 3. 5.2 (a) From the Wiener-Hopf equation we have:
New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines
New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines Michigan State University Oct 8-31, 016 Anhui University Definition If X = {x 1, x,, x N } S n 1 (unit sphere in R n ) and x i, x j = a
1. Introduction and Preliminaries.
Faculty of Sciences and Mathematics, University of Niš, Serbia Available at: http://www.pmf.ni.ac.yu/filomat Filomat 22:1 (2008), 97 106 ON δ SETS IN γ SPACES V. Renuka Devi and D. Sivaraj Abstract We
Math221: HW# 1 solutions
Math: HW# solutions Andy Royston October, 5 7.5.7, 3 rd Ed. We have a n = b n = a = fxdx = xdx =, x cos nxdx = x sin nx n sin nxdx n = cos nx n = n n, x sin nxdx = x cos nx n + cos nxdx n cos n = + sin
ON NICE EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS ON λ 2 SH724
ON NICE EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS ON λ 2 SH724 Saharon Shelah The Hebrew University of Jerusalem Einstein Institute of Mathematics Edmond J. Safra Campus, Givat Ram Jerusalem 91904, Israel Department of Mathematics