Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers

Σχετικά έγγραφα
Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit

2 Composition. Invertible Mappings

ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER

Finite Field Problems: Solutions

Chapter 2. Ordinals, well-founded relations.

Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set

ω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω

A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation

EE512: Error Control Coding

Example Sheet 3 Solutions

C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions

Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs

Reminders: linear functions

2. Let H 1 and H 2 be Hilbert spaces and let T : H 1 H 2 be a bounded linear operator. Prove that [T (H 1 )] = N (T ). (6p)

Fourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics

Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in

5. Choice under Uncertainty

3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2

Cardinals. Y = n Y n. Define h: X Y by f(x) if x X n X n+1 and n is even h(x) = g

Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequality for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x, y, z X.

Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3

Section 8.3 Trigonometric Equations

Lecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic

derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates

SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS

Homework 3 Solutions

Homomorphism in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Automata

Abstract Storage Devices

Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations

CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS

Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5. Luca Alberucci, University of Berne. Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008

k A = [k, k]( )[a 1, a 2 ] = [ka 1,ka 2 ] 4For the division of two intervals of confidence in R +

ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II

Matrices and Determinants

THE SECOND ISOMORPHISM THEOREM ON ORDERED SET UNDER ANTIORDERS. Daniel A. Romano

SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES G11LMA Linear Mathematics Examination Solutions

12. Radon-Nikodym Theorem

DIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANSFORMATION SEMIGROUPS

4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1)

Tridiagonal matrices. Gérard MEURANT. October, 2008

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 19/5/2007

Chap. 6 Pushdown Automata

Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets

THE GENERAL INDUCTIVE ARGUMENT FOR MEASURE ANALYSES WITH ADDITIVE ORDINAL ALGEBRAS

6.1. Dirac Equation. Hamiltonian. Dirac Eq.

Phys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required)

From the finite to the transfinite: Λµ-terms and streams

Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees

MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS

Section 9.2 Polar Equations and Graphs

Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor

ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC = DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION #2. h 0 h h 0 h h 0 ( ) g k = g 0 + g 1 + g g 2009 =?

Homomorphism of Intuitionistic Fuzzy Groups

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

Thus X is nonempty by supposition. By (i), let x be a minimal element of X. Then let

Εγχειρίδια Μαθηµατικών και Χταποδάκι στα Κάρβουνα

Completeness Theorem for System AS1

Overview. Transition Semantics. Configurations and the transition relation. Executions and computation

Solutions for exercises in chapter 1 = 2, 3, 1, 4 ; = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2 1 S 1 1 S 0 = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2, 1, 4,1,3. 1, 1,..., 1, S 0

Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests

Problem Set 3: Solutions

CHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS

TMA4115 Matematikk 3

Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II

Srednicki Chapter 55

Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests

Solution Series 9. i=1 x i and i=1 x i.

F19MC2 Solutions 9 Complex Analysis

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics

The Simply Typed Lambda Calculus

Practice Exam 2. Conceptual Questions. 1. State a Basic identity and then verify it. (a) Identity: Solution: One identity is csc(θ) = 1

Cyclic or elementary abelian Covers of K 4

Solutions to Selected Homework Problems 1.26 Claim: α : S S which is 1-1 but not onto β : S S which is onto but not 1-1. y z = z y y, z S.

Jordan Form of a Square Matrix

Trigonometric Formula Sheet

Knaster-Reichbach Theorem for 2 κ

Main source: "Discrete-time systems and computer control" by Α. ΣΚΟΔΡΑΣ ΨΗΦΙΑΚΟΣ ΕΛΕΓΧΟΣ ΔΙΑΛΕΞΗ 4 ΔΙΑΦΑΝΕΙΑ 1

PARTIAL NOTES for 6.1 Trigonometric Identities

( ) 2 and compare to M.

Σχολή Εφαρμοσμένων Μαθηματικών και Φυσικών Επιστημών. Εθνικό Μετσόβιο Πολυτεχνείο. Thales Workshop, 1-3 July 2015.

6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes

Econ 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1

Section 7.6 Double and Half Angle Formulas

1. Introduction and Preliminaries.

On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions.

Second Order Partial Differential Equations

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016

( y) Partial Differential Equations

The challenges of non-stable predicates

Math 6 SL Probability Distributions Practice Test Mark Scheme

About these lecture notes. Simply Typed λ-calculus. Types

Pg The perimeter is P = 3x The area of a triangle is. where b is the base, h is the height. In our case b = x, then the area is

Math221: HW# 1 solutions

Numerical Analysis FMN011

New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines

Intuitionistic Fuzzy Ideals of Near Rings

Transcript:

Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers There are two kinds of number.. Ordinal numbers (0th), st, 2nd, 3rd, 4th, 5th,..., ω, ω +,... ω2, ω2+,... ω 2... answers to the question What position is... in a sequence? What position is... in an ordered set? 2. Cardinal numbers 0,, 2, 3, 4, 5,..., ℵ 0, ℵ, ℵ 2,... answers to the question How may... s are there? How many elements in a set? Finite ordinals correspond to finite cardinals, but the two notions differ in the transfinite. Ordinal numbers this chapter Cardinal numbers chapter 4 2 Ordinal numbers Cantor introduced them as labels for stages in a transfinite iteration. In 882 he became interested in them as numbers in their own right. How to represent them as sets? Finite ordinals = natural numbers 0 = = 0 {0}, 2 = {}, 3 = 2 {2},... n = {0,, 2,... n } Extend this into the transfinite: each ordinal number is the set of all its predecessors. ω = {0,, 2, 3,...} = N ω + = ω {ω} = {0,, 2, 3,..., ω} ω + 2 = (ω + ) {ω + } = {0,, 2, 3,..., ω, ω + } ω + ω (= ω2) = {0,, 2, 3,..., ω, ω +, ω + 2, ω + 3,...} Note: every ordinal is either 0, a successor ordinal, + = {}, a limit ordinal, e.g., ω = lim(0,, 2, 3, 4,...); ω ω = lim(ω, ω 2, ω 3, ω 4,...)

Ordering of ordinals: < iff iff. 3 CAUTION: this is not a proper definition of ordinal number. First step: examine the distinctive ordering that occurs in ordinals any non empty subset has a least element ( well ordered ). DEF n. A set A is well ordered by a binary relation iff () x A x x (irreflexive) (2) x, y, z A (x y y z x z) (transitive) (3) S A (S y S ( x S x y y x)) (any non empty subset S has a least element y) We also say (A, ) is a well ordered set (woset), or is a well ordering on A. If (A, ) merely satisfies () and (2), it is called a partially ordered set (poset). Note that () (2) x, y A (x y y x) (anti symmetry). 4 Examples of wosets. (N,<) is a woset. Proof of (3) by induction. 0 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0 2 2. (Z,<) is a poset but not a woset.... -5-4 -3-2 - 0 2 3 4 5 6...... 3. Likewise, Q and R are partially, but not well, ordered by <. 4. Ordinals are well ordered by < (can t prove it yet). E.g., take ω + 5:... 0 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 ω ω+ ω+2 ω+3 ω+4 Can prove it for ω + 5.

5. Order N by... 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0 2 5 m n { (m, n 2 m < n) (m, n > 2 m < n) (m > 2 n 2) 6. Order N by... 7 6 5 4 3 2 0 m n iff n < m 7. Order N N by 6 6 5 4 3 2 0 2 3 4 5 6 7 (m, n ) (m 2, n 2 ) iff n < n 2 (n = n 2 m < m 2 )

8. Order N N by 7 6 5 4 3 2 0 2 3 4 5 6 7 (m, n ) (m 2, n 2 ) iff m + n < m 2 + n 2 (m + n = m 2 + n 2 m < m 2 ) 9. Order N N by 8 6 5 4 3 2 0 2 3 4 5 6 7 (m, n ) (m 2, n 2 ) iff max{m, n } < max{m 2, n 2 } (m < n = m 2 > n 2 ) (m < m 2 n 2 = n ) (n 2 < n m = m 2 )

0. Order N N by 9. Order N by 6 5 4 3 2 0 2 4 6 8 0 2 3 4 5 6 7 (m, n ) (m 2, n 2 ) iff m < m 2 n < n 2 m n iff...... 0 3 5 7 9 { (m, n are even m < n) (m, n are odd m < n) (m is even n is odd) THEOREM 2. A woset (A, ) is linearly ordered, that is, x, y A (x y x = y y x). THEOREM 3. Any subset of a woset is also well ordered. 0 Similar orderings DEF n. Let (A, ) and (B, 2 ) be posets. (A, ) is similar to (B, 2 ), i.e., (A, ) (B, 2 ), iff there exists a function f: A B such that (a) f is a bijection (b) f preserves order: x, y A (x y f(x) 2 f(y)) (f is called a similarity or order isomorphism; we write f: (A, ) (B, 2 ) or just f: A B.) Note that is an equivalence relation on posets.

Examples 2. ( π 2, π 2 ) R (usual orderings on both). tan: ( π 2, π 2 ) R 3. ( π 2, π 2 ) (0, ). f: ( π 2, π 2 ) (0, ) defined by x ( π 2, π 2 ) f(x) = x π + 2. 4. Consequently, (0, ) R. tan f : (0, ) R. 5. [0, ] R. Assume f: [0, ] R and consider f (f(0) ). 6. Revisiting old examples: Ex 5 ω + 3 Ex 7 ω 2 Ex 8 ω Ex 9 ω Ex ω + ω THEOREM 4. Let (A, ) and (B, 2 ) be similar posets. Then (A, ) is a woset iff (B, 2 ) is. Conjecture. Every woset is similar to a unique ordinal. We need a rigorous definition of ordinal. Burali Forti s Paradox (897) 2 Let W be the set of all ordinals. CLAIM. W is an ordinal. Proof. (Recall that an ordinal is a set that is transitive and well ordered by.) W is transitive since if x W then x W (theorem 5). W is well ordered by since W / (theorem ),, W (since is transitive) any non empty set of ordinals has a least element (theorem 9). Therefore W W, i.e., W < W, contrary to theorem. Contradiction! Burali Forti s explanation: W is only partially ordered, not linearly ordered. Russell s explanation: W is linearly ordered but not well ordered. Jourdain, Russell and Zermelo subsequently decided there was no set W of all ordinals. This resolution is followed in modern set theory.

3 Morals () We need a clear definition of ordinal. (2) We need a clear notion of what a set is. We are about to give (). [See separate document.] Do we have (2)? 4 Ordinal Arithmetic What do + and mean? Let and be ordinals. Let S = { (0, x) x } { (, y) y } with order relation defined by (0, x ) (0, x 2 ) iff x < x 2 (, y ) (, y 2 ) iff y < y 2 (0, x) (, y) [Convenient notation: for any set C, C 0 = { (0, x) x C}, C = { (, x) x C}.] Thus S = 0. THEOREM 25. (S, ) is a woset. DEF n. + = the unique ordinal similar to (S, ) (by theorem 23). EXAMPLES. 7. ω + = ω {ω} > ω. Define f: (ω 0, ) (ω {ω},<) by n < ω f(0, n) = n f(, 0) = ω

In general, + = {} >. 5 8. +ω = ω. Define f: ( 0 ω, ) (ω,<) by f(0, 0) = 0 n < ω f(, n) = n+ Likewise 2+ω = ω: define f: (2 0 ω, ) (ω,<) by f(0, 0) = 0 f(0, ) = n < ω f(, n) = n+2 In general, n < ω n+ω = ω. 9. ω + ω = {0,, 2,..., ω, ω +, ω + 2,...} > ω. Define f: (ω 0 ω, ) ({0,, 2,..., ω, ω +, ω + 2,...},<) by n < ω f(0, n) = n n < ω f(, n) = ω + n Note that + +, in general. 6 THEOREM 26. For any ordinals,,, + ( + ) = ( + )+. Proof. The construction of + ( + ) gives us similarities f: 0 +, g: 0 ( + ) + ( + ) The construction of ( + )+ gives us similarities h: 0 +, i: ( + ) 0 ( + )+ 0 + f f 0 + ( + ) g ( + ) g ( + )+ ( + ) 0 i i + 0 h h

Define j: + ( + ) ( + )+ by 7 x j ( g(0, x) y j ( z j ( g(, f(0, y)) g(, f(, z)) ) = i(0, h(0, x)) ) = i(0, h(, y)) ) = i(, z) Then by theorem 20 + ( + ) = ( + )+. What about? Let P = (product of sets), ordered by (x, y ) (x 2, y 2 ) iff (y < y 2 ) (y = y 2 x < x 2 ) THEOREM 27. (P, ) is a woset. DEF n. (Ordinal multiplication) = the unique ordinal similar to (P, ). 2 =, n+ = n for n < ω. 8 EXAMPLES. 20. ω2 = ω + ω. Define f: (ω 2, ) (ω 0 ω, ) by n < ω f(n, 0) = (0, n) n < ω f(n, ) = (, n) Then (ω2,<) (ω 2, ) (ω 0 ω, ) (ω + ω,<) so by theorem 20 ω2 = ω + ω. 2. 2ω = ω. Define f: (2 ω, ) (ω,<) by n < ω f(0, n) = 2n n < ω f(, n) = 2n+ Thus, by definition, 2ω = ω. In general, n < ω nω = ω. Note: in general.

9 THEOREM 28. For any ordinals,,, () = (). Proof. The construction of () gives us similarities f: The construction of () gives us similarities h: g: () () i: () () g ( ) X X h X ( ) i ( ) ( ) f X Define j: () () by x y z j ( i(x, h(y, z)) ) = g(f(x, y), z) So by theorem 20 () = (). 20 THEOREM 29. For any ordinals,,, + = ( + ). Proof. The construction of + gives us similarities f:, g:, h: () 0 () +. The construction of ( + ) gives us similarities i: 0 +, j: ( + ) ( + ). X X g f ( ) ( ) 0 h h j X( + ) i + i 0 + ( + )

Define a similarity k: + ( + ) by x y k ( ) h(0, f(x, y)) = j(x, i(0, y)) x z k ( ) h(, g(x, z)) = j(x, i(, z)) 2 Then by theorem 20 + = ( + ). BEWARE: ( + ) + in general. THEOREM 30. (ω + )ω = ω 2. Proof. The construction of (ω + )ω gives us similarities f: ω 0 ω + g: (ω + ) ω (ω + )ω The construction of ω 2 gives us a similarity h: ω ω ω 2 22 ω ω ω ( +)X g h ω ω Xω ω ω 0 f ω+ f ( ω +) ω ω 2 ω Define a similarity i: (ω + )ω ω 2 by m i(g(f(0, m), 0)) = h(m, 0) m n i(g(f(0, m), n+)) = h(m+, n+) n i(g(f(, 0), n)) = h(0, n+) So by theorem 20 (ω + )ω = ω 2.

23 THEOREM 3. (ω + )ω < ω 2 + ω. Proof. Theorem 30 shows (ω + )ω = ω 2. We must just show ω 2 < ω 2 + ω. The construction of ω 2 + ω gives us a similarity f: (ω 2 ) 0 ω ω 2 + ω We can then define a function g: ω 2 ω 2 + ω by x ω 2 g(x) = f(0, x) This is a similarity from ω 2 to an initial segment of ω 2 + ω (i.e., everything below f(, 0)). So (ω + )ω < ω 2 + ω. THEOREM 32. n < ω (ω + n)ω = ω 2. Proof. As in theorem 30. THEOREM 33. m, n < ω (0 < m (ω + n)m = ωm+n). Proof. Similar to theorem 30. Or, (ω + n)m = (ω + n)(++ + ) 24 = (ω + n)+(ω + n)+ + (ω + n) = ω + (n+ω)+(n+ω)+ +(n+ω)+n = ω + ω + ω + +ω + n by theorem 29 by theorem 26 by example 8 = ω+ω+ω+ +ω+n = ω(+++ + )+n by theorem 29 = ωm+n. EXAMPLE. 22. Reduction to normal form. (Use associativity tacitly.) (ω + )(ω + 2)(ω + 3) = (ω + )(ω + 2)ω + (ω + )(ω + 2)3 = (ω + )ω 2 + (ω + )(ω3+2) = ω 3 + (ω + )ω3+(ω + )2 = ω 3 + ω 2 3+ω2+ by theorem 29 by theorems 32, 33 by theorems 30, 29 by theorems 30, 33