GAMES AND GENERAL DISTRIBUTIVE LAWS IN BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS

Σχετικά έγγραφα
Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit

2 Composition. Invertible Mappings

Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set

ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER

Example Sheet 3 Solutions

Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers

Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in

ω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω

4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1)

Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor

C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions

Homomorphism in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Automata

The challenges of non-stable predicates

Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2

EE512: Error Control Coding

On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions.

SCITECH Volume 13, Issue 2 RESEARCH ORGANISATION Published online: March 29, 2018

Lecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic

Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees

MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS

Tridiagonal matrices. Gérard MEURANT. October, 2008

1. Introduction and Preliminaries.

Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016

ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II

Homomorphism of Intuitionistic Fuzzy Groups

A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation

SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS

Homework 3 Solutions

Phys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required)

Intuitionistic Fuzzy Ideals of Near Rings

Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests

Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests

Cardinals. Y = n Y n. Define h: X Y by f(x) if x X n X n+1 and n is even h(x) = g

Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs

Section 8.3 Trigonometric Equations

derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates

Some new generalized topologies via hereditary classes. Key Words:hereditary generalized topological space, A κ(h,µ)-sets, κµ -topology.

Generating Set of the Complete Semigroups of Binary Relations

THE SECOND ISOMORPHISM THEOREM ON ORDERED SET UNDER ANTIORDERS. Daniel A. Romano

On a four-dimensional hyperbolic manifold with finite volume

NOTES ON SQUARES, SCALES, AND REFLECTION

SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES G11LMA Linear Mathematics Examination Solutions

Abstract Storage Devices

Fourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

Splitting stationary sets from weak forms of Choice

DIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANSFORMATION SEMIGROUPS

5. Choice under Uncertainty

Matrices and Determinants

A General Note on δ-quasi Monotone and Increasing Sequence

Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3

Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics

Knaster-Reichbach Theorem for 2 κ

Finite Field Problems: Solutions

SOLVING CUBICS AND QUARTICS BY RADICALS

Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets

k A = [k, k]( )[a 1, a 2 ] = [ka 1,ka 2 ] 4For the division of two intervals of confidence in R +

CHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS

Lecture 21: Properties and robustness of LSE

3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β

Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequality for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x, y, z X.

Coefficient Inequalities for a New Subclass of K-uniformly Convex Functions

6.1. Dirac Equation. Hamiltonian. Dirac Eq.

2. Let H 1 and H 2 be Hilbert spaces and let T : H 1 H 2 be a bounded linear operator. Prove that [T (H 1 )] = N (T ). (6p)

Second Order Partial Differential Equations

Main source: "Discrete-time systems and computer control" by Α. ΣΚΟΔΡΑΣ ΨΗΦΙΑΚΟΣ ΕΛΕΓΧΟΣ ΔΙΑΛΕΞΗ 4 ΔΙΑΦΑΝΕΙΑ 1

forms This gives Remark 1. How to remember the above formulas: Substituting these into the equation we obtain with

Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude

Solution Series 9. i=1 x i and i=1 x i.

Reminders: linear functions

Solutions to Exercise Sheet 5

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 19/5/2007

The Simply Typed Lambda Calculus

Econ 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1

Problem Set 3: Solutions

Section 9.2 Polar Equations and Graphs

Math221: HW# 1 solutions

THE GENERAL INDUCTIVE ARGUMENT FOR MEASURE ANALYSES WITH ADDITIVE ORDINAL ALGEBRAS

HOMEWORK 4 = G. In order to plot the stress versus the stretch we define a normalized stretch:

Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations

A Conception of Inductive Logic: Example

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 6/5/2006

New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines

6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes

3.2 Simple Roots and Weyl Group

Physical DB Design. B-Trees Index files can become quite large for large main files Indices on index files are possible.

SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM

Απόκριση σε Μοναδιαία Ωστική Δύναμη (Unit Impulse) Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο. Απόστολος Σ.

( y) Partial Differential Equations

Space-Time Symmetries

Models for Probabilistic Programs with an Adversary

Jesse Maassen and Mark Lundstrom Purdue University November 25, 2013

Strukturalna poprawność argumentu.

SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM

Partial Differential Equations in Biology The boundary element method. March 26, 2013

Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5. Luca Alberucci, University of Berne. Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008

P-IDEAL DICHOTOMY AND WEAK SQUARES

Second Order RLC Filters

Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II

F A S C I C U L I M A T H E M A T I C I

Transcript:

PROCEEDINGS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 131, Number 1, Pages 309 318 S 0002-9939(02)06501-2 Article electronically published on May 13, 2002 GAMES AND GENERAL DISTRIBUTIVE LAWS IN BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS NATASHA DOBRINEN (Communicated by Carl G. Jockusch, Jr.) Abstract. The games G η 1 (κ) andgη <λ (κ) are played by two players in η+ - complete and max(η +,λ)-complete Boolean algebras, respectively. For cardinals η, κ such that κ <η = η or κ <η = κ, the(η, κ)-distributive law holds in a Boolean algebra B iff Player 1 does not have a winning strategy in G η 1 (κ). Furthermore, for all cardinals κ, the(η, )-distributive law holds in B iff Player 1 does not have a winning strategy in G η 1 ( ). More generally, for cardinals η, λ, κ such that (κ <λ ) <η = η, the (η, < λ, κ)-distributive law holds in B iff Player 1 does not have a winning strategy in G η <λ (κ). For η regular and λ min(η, κ), η + implies the existence of a Suslin algebra in which G η <λ (κ) is undetermined. 0. Introduction Games between two players arise naturally in the study of distributive laws in Boolean algebras. Jech [3] obtained a game-theoretic characterization of the (ω, )- distributive law using the game G which is played by two players in a complete Boolean algebra B as follows: Player 1 begins the game by choosing some a 0 B + (where B + = B\{0}); then Player 2 chooses some b 0 B + such that b 0 a 0. The two players take turns choosing elements a n,b n B + to form a descending sequence (1) a 0 b 0 a 1 b 1 a n b n. Player 1 wins the play (1) iff the sequence (1) has no lower bound in B +. Jech showed that the (ω, )-distributive law holds in B iff Player 1 does not have a winning strategy in G. A few years later, Foreman [1] obtained a game-theoretic characterization of the (η, )-distributive law for successor cardinals η. Fora partial ordering P, Fuchino, Mildenberger, Shelah, and Vojtáš [2] defined the game G(P,η), which is played just like G,exceptthatitisplayedinη-many rounds, where Player 1 plays first at each limit ordinal. They showed that if P is separative, then for all cardinals η the (η, )-distributive law holds in r.o.(p) (the regular open algebra of P) iff Player 1 does not have a winning strategy in G(P,η). Interested in the second parameter of the (ω, κ)-distributive law, Jech [4] defined the game G 1 (κ) to be played in a complete Boolean algebra. At the beginning of the game, Player 1 chooses some a B + which is then fixed throughout the ω-many Received by the editors November 17, 2000 and, in revised form, August 23, 2001. 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary 03G05, 06E25; Secondary 03E40. Key words and phrases. Boolean algebra, distributivity, games. 309 c 2002 American Mathematical Society

310 NATASHA DOBRINEN rounds. On the n-th round, Player 1 chooses W n B +, a partition of a such that W n κ; thenplayer2choosessomeb n W n. Player 1 wins the play (2) a, W 0,b 0,W 1,b 1,...,W n,b n,... iff n<ω b n = 0. Jechshowedthat,forallcardinalsκ, the(ω, κ)-distributive law holds in B iff Player 1 does not have a winning strategy in G 1 (κ). In 1, we present the game G η 1 (κ) which generalizes G 1(κ) to plays of uncountable length. We show that, for cardinals η, κ such that κ <η = η or κ <η = κ, the (η, κ)-distributive law is characterized by the non-existence of a winning strategy for Player 1 in G η 1 (κ). It immediately follows that the (η, )-distributive law holds in B iff Player 1 does not have a winning strategy in G η 1 ( ). This yields a characterization of (η, )-distributivity different than the characterization obtained by Fuchino, Mildenberger, Shelah and Vojtáš in [2]. Moreover, it shows the equivalence of the existence of a winning strategy for Player 1 in the games G(B +,η)and G η 1 ( ). In 2, we present the game G η <λ (κ), played similarly to Gη 1 (κ), except that now Player 2 chooses less than λ-many pieces from each of Player 1 s partitions. We show that, for cardinals η, κ, λ such that (κ <λ ) <η = η, the(η, < λ, κ)-distributive law holds iff Player 1 does not have a winning strategy in G η <λ (κ). Since the (η, < ω, κ)- distributive law is the same as the weak (η, κ)-distributive law, this yields a gametheoretic characterization of the weak (η, κ)-distributive law for cardinals η, κ such that κ <η = η. Moreover, for regular infinite cardinals η and cardinals λ, κ with λ min(η, κ), we use η + to construct an η + -Suslin algebra in which G η 1 (κ) and (κ) are undetermined. G η <λ 1. The (η, κ)-distributive law and the game G η 1 (κ) We begin by reviewing the following basic distributive law. Throughout this paper, let B denote a Boolean algebra. Definition 1.1 ([7]). B satisfies the (η, κ)-distributive law ((η, κ)-d.l.) if for each I η, J κ, and family (b ij ) i I,j J of elements of B, b ij = (3) b if(i), i I j J f:i J provided that j J b ij for each i I, i I j J b ij, and i I b if(i) for each f : I J exist in B. WesaythatB is (η, )-distributive if it satisfies the (η, κ)-d.l. for all cardinals κ. Jech showed that the (η, κ)-d.l. is equivalent to the following forcing property. Proposition 1.1 ([5]). If B is complete, then B is (η, κ)-distributive if and only if every function from η to κ in the generic extension V [G] belongs to the ground model V. B is (η, )-distributive if and only if every function f : η V in V [G] is in V. The following generalizes Jech s game G 1 (κ) to plays of uncountable length. Definition 1.2. Let κ be any cardinal and η be any infinite cardinal. The game G η 1 (κ) is played between two players in an η+ -complete Boolean algebra B as follows: At the beginning of the game, Player 1 (P1) chooses some a B + which is fixed throughout the η-many rounds. For, the α-th round is played as follows: P1 i I

GAMES IN BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS 311 chooses a partition W α of a such that W α κ; then Player 2 (P2) chooses some b α W α. In this manner, the two players construct a sequence of length η (4) a, W 0,b 0,W 1,b 1,...,W α,b α,... : called a play of the game. P1 wins the play (4) if and only if (5) b α = 0. A strategy for P1 is a function σ : {0} (B + ) <η [B + ] κ such that σ(0) ={a} and for each b α : α<β (B + ) <η, σ( b α : α<β ) is a partition of a. σ is a winning strategy if P1 wins every time P1 follows σ. A strategy for P2 is a function τ :([B + ] κ ) <η B + such that for each W α : α β ([B + ] κ ) <η, τ( W α : α β ) W β. τ is a winning strategy if whenever P2 plays by τ, P2wins. G η 1 = Gη 1 ( ) is the game played as above, except now P1 can choose partitions of any size. We note that Jech s game G 1 (κ) is the same as our game G1 ω (κ). Remark. G η 1 can be played in a partial ordering P in the natural way: At the beginning of the game, P1 chooses some fixed p P. On the α-th round, P1 chooses a maximal incompatible subset M α P below p; then P2 chooses one element p α M α. This constructs the sequence (6) p, M 0,p 0,M 1,p 1,...,M α,p α,... :. P1 wins the play (6) if and only if q P, α <ηsuch that q p α. If P is separative, then the existence of a winning strategy for P1 (P2) is invariant when passing to r.o.(p). One can easily show that if P2 has a winning strategy in G η 1 (κ) (Gη 1 ), then the (η, κ)-d.l. ((η, )-d.l.) holds. Jech obtained the following characterization of the (ω, κ)-d.l. Theorem 1.2 ([4]). If B is complete, then the (ω, κ)-d.l. holds in B if and only if P1 does not have a winning strategy in G ω 1 (κ). The if direction easily generalizes to all pairs of cardinals η, κ. Theorem 1.3. If B is η + -complete and the (η, κ)-d.l. fails in B, then P1 has a winning strategy in G η 1 (κ). Proof. Follows from Theorem 2.2. We have obtained the following partial converse to Theorem 1.3. Theorem 1.4. If B is η + -complete and P1 has a winning strategy in G η 1 (κ), then (1) the (κ <η,κ)-d.l. fails; (2) the (η, κ <η )-d.l. fails. Proof. (1) follows from Theorem 2.3. The proof of (2) uses ideas from Jech s proof of Theorem 1.2, the main difference being that here, limit ordinals must be treated with care, as in Case 1, below. Let σ beawinningstrategyforp1ing η 1 (κ). Let {a} = σ(0)andp 0 = σ( ). For each x 0 P 0,letW 1 ( x 0 )={x 0 z : z σ( x 0 )}. Let P 1 = {W 1 ( x 0 ):x 0 σ( )}. For each x 1 σ( x 0 ), let W 2 ( x 0,x 1 )= {x 0 x 1 z : z σ( x 0,x 1 )}. LetP 2 = {W 2 ( x 0,x 1 ):x 0 σ( ),x 1 σ( x 0 )}.

312 NATASHA DOBRINEN In general, given and a sequence x β : β<α (B + ) α such that β <α x β σ( x γ : γ<β ), let (7) W α ( x β : β<α ) ={( x β ) z : z σ( x β : β<α )}, and let (8) β<α P α = {W α ( x β : β<α ) : β <α, x β σ( x γ : γ<β )}. Note that (a) α <η, P α B + is pairwise disjoint and P α κ α+1 κ <η. (b) If β<,then x P α y P β such that y x. (c) If and β <α, x β σ( x γ : γ<β ), then W α ( x β : β<α ) = β<α x β. (d) α <η, P α+1 = P α. (e) If (i) β γ<η; (ii) x ζ : ζ<β, y ζ : ζ<γ are sequences such that ζ<β, x ζ σ( x θ : θ<ζ ) and y ζ σ( y θ : θ<ζ ); and (iii) δ β such that x δ y δ ; then ζ<β x ζ ζ<γ y ζ = 0. (a)-(d) are clear. For (e), if δ β is least such that x δ y δ,thenx δ,y δ σ( x ζ : ζ<δ ), a partition of a, sox δ y δ = 0. Claim. The (η, κ <η )-d.l. fails for the collection P α,(). By (a), we can index the elements of P α using the index set κ <η so that P α = {b α,γ : γ<κ <η }, allowing repetitions. Case 1. α <ηfor which P α <a. Let α be least such that P α <a. (d) implies α is a limit ordinal. We will show that the (α, κ <η )-d.l. fails for the partitions P β (β<α)ofa. Since β<α Pβ = a, it suffices to show that (9) b β,f(β) P α. f:α κ <η β<α Let f : α κ <η be given. β <α, there is a sequence x β ζ : ζ β such that b β,f(β) = ζ β xβ ζ and ζ β xβ ζ σ( xβ γ : γ<ζ ). Suppose ζ β<γ<α, x β ζ = xγ ζ. β <α,letx β denote x β β. Then β <α, x β σ( x ζ : ζ<β ), so (c) implies β<α x β = W α ( x β : β<α ). Therefore, b β,f(β) = (10) x β ζ = x β = W α ( x β : β<α ) P α. β<α β<α ζ β Otherwise, δ β<γ<αsuch that x β δ xγ δ. In this case, (e) implies (11) b ζ,f(ζ) b β,f(β) b γ,f(γ) = x β ζ x γ ζ = 0. ζ<α β<α Since (10) and (11) hold for all f : α κ <η, (9) holds. Therefore, the (α, κ <η )- d.l. fails. Case 2. For each, P α = a. (b) implies β <, P α is a refinement of P β.letf : η κ <η be given. We will show that b α,f(α) = 0. If α <ηsuch that b α,f(α) = 0, then we are done; so assume α <η, b α,f(α) 0. ζ β ζ γ

GAMES IN BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS 313 Suppose β <such that b β,f(β) b α,f(α). Then, b β,f(β) b α,f(α) = 0, since P α is a refinement of P β. Hence, b α,f(α) = 0. Otherwise, β <, b β,f(β) b α,f(α) > 0. Again, β <αlet x β ζ : ζ<β be the sequence such that b β,f(β) = ζ β xβ ζ and ζ βxβ ζ σ( xβ γ : γ<ζ ). We claim that (12) ζ β<, x β ζ = xα ζ. If (12) fails, then δ, β, α with δ β < α < η such that x β δ x α δ. Then b β,f(β) b α,f(α) = 0, by (e). But this implies b α,f(α) = 0, sinceb α,f(α) b β,f(β). Contradiction. Thus, (12) holds. α <ηlet x α denote x α α.then (13) a, σ( ),x 0,σ( x 0 ),x 1,...,σ( x β : β<α ),x α,... : is a play in G η 1 (κ) in which P1 follows σ. So, b α,f(α) = (14) x α ζ = x α = 0. Since f : η κ <η was arbitrary, (15) f:η κ <η ζ α b α,f(α) = 0 < a. Thus, the (η, κ <η )-d.l. fails for the partitions P α ()ofa. Whether the full converse of Theorem 1.4 holds is unknown. However, for certain pairs of cardinals η, κ we have the following: Corollary 1.5. If B is η + -complete and κ <η = η or κ <η = κ, then the (η, κ)-d.l. holds in B if and only if P1 does not have a winning strategy in G η 1 (κ). From Corollary 1.5, we obtain a characterization of the (η, )-d.l. which differs from the one given in [2]. Corollary 1.6. If B is η + -complete, then the (η, )-d.l. holds if and only if P1 does not have a winning strategy in G η 1. Corollary 1.6 implies that the existence of a winning strategy for P1 in G η 1 is equivalent to the existence of a winning strategy for P1 in the game G(B +,η)in [2]. Assuming GCH, Corollary 1.5 gives a characterization of the (η, κ)-d.l. for all κ<ηand for certain κ η. Corollary 1.7 (GCH). If B is η + -complete, then κ <ηand κ with cf(κ) η, the (η, κ)-d.l. holds if and only if P1 does not have a winning strategy in G η 1 (κ). Example 1. If η is regular and η + holds, then there is an η + -Suslin algebra in which neither player has a winning strategy in G η 1 (κ). (This follows from Example 2withλ =2.) Remark. η regular and η + imply that the existence of a winning strategy for P2 in G η 1 (κ) is strictly stronger than the (η, κ)-d.l. Example 2 in 2 will shed more light on the difference between their relative strengths.

314 NATASHA DOBRINEN 2. The (η, < λ, κ)-distributive law and the game G η <λ (κ) Three-parameter distributivity is the natural generalization of weak distributivity and is defined as follows. Definition 2.1 ([5]). B satisfies the (η, < λ, κ)-distributive law ((η, < λ, κ)-d.l.) if for each I η, J κ, and family (b ij ) i I,j J of elements of B, (16) b ij = b ij, i I j J f:i [J] <λ i I j f(i) j J b ij, and i I j f(i) b ij for each provided that j J b ij for each i I, i I f : I [J] <λ exist in B. WesaythatB is (η, < λ, )-distributive if it satisfies the (η, < λ, κ)-d.l. for all cardinals κ. Note. The (η, κ)-d.l. is the same as the (η, < 2,κ)-d.l., and the weak (η, κ)-d.l. is the same as the (η, < ω, κ)-d.l. (η, < λ, κ)-distributivity is equivalent to the following forcing property. Proposition 2.1. If B is complete, then B is (η, < λ, κ)-distributive if and only if for every function g : η κ in V [G] there is a function f : η [κ] <λ in V such that α <η, g(α) f(α). B is (η, < λ, )-distributive if and only if for every function g : η V in V [G] thereissomefunctionf : η [V ] <λ such that α <η, g(α) f(α). The following game corresponds naturally to the (η, < λ, κ)-d.l. Definition 2.2. Let η, κ be infinite cardinals and λ be a cardinal such that 2 λ κ. The game G η <λ (κ) is played between two players in a max(η+,λ)-complete Boolean algebra B as follows: At the beginning of the game, P1 chooses some a B +.For,theα-th round is played as follows: P1 chooses a partition W α of a such that W α κ; then P2 chooses some F α [W α ] <λ. In this manner, the two players construct a sequence of length η (17) a, W 0,F 0,W 1,F 1,...,W α,f α,... :, called a play of the game. P1 wins the play (17) if and only if (18) Fα = 0. A strategy for P1 is a function σ : {0} ([B + ] <λ ) <η [B + ] κ such that σ(0) ={a} and for each F α : α<β ([B + ] <λ ) <η, σ( F α : α<β ) is a partition of a. σ is a winning strategy if P1 wins every time P1 follows σ. A strategy for P2 is a function τ :([B + ] κ ) <η [B + ] <λ such that for each W α : α β ([B + ] κ ) <η, τ( W α : α β ) [W β ] <λ. τ is a winning strategy if whenever P2 follows τ, P2wins. G η <λ = Gη <λ ( ) is the game played just as Gη <λ (κ), except now P1 can choose partitions of any size. Let G η fin (κ) denotegη <ω(κ). Jech s game G fin (κ) in[4]isthe same as Gfin ω (κ). Note that Gη <2 (κ) =Gη 1 (κ). Remark. G η <λ can be played in a partial ordering in the natural way. As before, if P is separative, the existence of a winning strategy for P1 (P2) in G η <λ is invariant under the completion of P.

GAMES IN BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS 315 Note. In a max(η +,λ)-complete Boolean algebra, the following hold: For η 0 η 1, κ 0 κ 1,andλ 0 λ 1, a winning strategy for P1 in G η0 <λ 0 (κ 0 ) is a winning strategy for P1 in G η1 <λ 1 (κ 1 ); conversely, a winning strategy for P2 in G η1 <λ 1 (κ 1 )isa winning strategy for P2 in G η0 <λ 0 (κ 0 ). If P2 has a winning strategy in G η <λ (κ) (Gη <λ ), then the (η, < λ, κ)-d.l. ((η, < λ, )-d.l.) holds. Theorems 1.3 and 1.4 (1) are consequences of the following two theorems. Theorem 2.2 is a generalization of a result of Jech [4] which states that the failure of the weak (ω, κ)-d.l. implies the existence of a winning strategy for P1 in G ω fin (κ). Theorem 2.2. If B is max(η +,λ)-complete, λ κ, andthe(η, < λ, κ)-d.l. fails, then P1 has a winning strategy in G η <λ (κ). Proof. If the (η, < λ, κ)-d.l. fails, then there is a family W α = {b αβ : β<κ} B +, (α <η), such that f:η [κ] <λ β f(α) b α,β = 0 < β<κ b α,β. Let a = β<κ b αβ. P1winsifP1choosesa at the beginning of the game, and α <η,p1playsw α. Theorem 2.3. If B is max(η +,λ)-complete, λ κ, and P1 has a winning strategy in G η <λ (κ), then the ((κ<λ ) <η,<λ,κ)-d.l. fails in B. Proof. Suppose σ is a winning strategy for P1. Let {a} = σ(0) andw = σ( ). Index the elements of [W ] <λ using s(0) κ <λ so that [W ] <λ = {F s(0) : s(0) κ <λ }.LetW s(0) = σ( F s(0) ) be the partition of a which P1 chooses according to σ if P2 has just chosen F s(0) [W ] <λ. In general, for and s (κ <λ ) α, given a sequence F s 1,F s 2,...,F s (β+1),... : β<α of P2 s moves, let (19) W s = σ( F s (β+1) : β<α ) be the partition of a which P1 chooses according to σ. Index the elements of [W s ] <λ using s(α) κ <λ so that (20) [W s ] <λ = {F s s(α) : s(α) κ <λ }. Note that {W s : s (κ <λ ) <η } is a listing of all the possible choices for P1 under σ, and{f s : s (κ <λ ) <η and dom(s) is a successor ordinal} is a listing of all the possible choices for P2 when P1 follows σ. Claim. The ((κ <λ ) <η,< λ,κ)-d.l. fails for the partitions W s (s (κ <λ ) <η )ofa. For each s (κ <λ ) <η,useκto index the elements of W s so that W s = {b s,j : j<κ}. It suffices to show that for every f :(κ <λ ) <η [κ] <λ, (21) b s,j = 0. s (κ <λ ) <η j f(s) Let f : (κ <λ ) <η [κ] <λ be given. To show (21), we construct a sequence t (κ <λ ) η with the following two properties: (a), F t (α+1) = {b t α,j : j f(t α)}; (b) a W t α,f t (α+1) : is a play of G η <λ (κ) in which P1 follows σ. Let t(0) be the unique element of κ <λ for which F t(0) = {b,j : j f( )}. In general, for and given t(β) :β<α, lett(α) be the unique element of κ <λ for which (22) F t(β):β<α t(α) = {b t(β):β<α,j : j f( t(β) :β<α )}.

316 NATASHA DOBRINEN Let (23) t = t(α) : (κ <λ ) η. It follows from (19), (20), (22), and (23) that t satisfies properties (a) and (b). Thus, (24) Ft (α+1) = 0, b s,j s (κ <λ ) <η j f(s) since property (a) implies the inequality and property (b) implies the equality in (24). Thus, (21) holds. Since f was arbitrary, the ((κ <λ ) <η,< λ,κ)-d.l. fails for the partitions W s (s (κ <λ ) <η )ofa. Corollary 2.4. If B is max(η +,λ)-complete and (κ <λ ) <η = η, then the (η, < λ, κ)- d.l. holds in B if and only if P1 does not have a winning strategy in G η <λ (κ). Corollary 2.5 (GCH). Suppose B is max(η +,λ)-complete, λ κ, and either (a) κ + η, or(b)κ = η and η is regular. Then the (η, < λ, κ)-d.l. holds in B if and only if P1 does not have a winning strategy in G η <λ (κ). It is not immediately clear whether the existence of a winning strategy for P2 is equivalent to the non-existence of a winning strategy for P1 in G η <λ (κ). For η regular and λ min(κ, η), I have constructed the following Suslin algebra in which they are not equivalent. Example 2. If η is regular, λ min(κ, η), and η + holds, then there exists an η + -Suslin algebra in which the game G η <λ (κ) is undetermined. We construct a Suslin tree (T, ) = (η +, ) such that neither player has a winning strategy in G η <λ (κ) played in r.o.(t ), where (T, )=(T, ). In light of the natural correspondence between partitions of r.o.(t ) and partitions of levels of T, we need only work with partitions of levels of T. Since T will satisfy the η + -c.c. and P1 must choose partitions of levels of T of cardinality κ, we need only consider partitions of levels of T of size µ = min(η, κ). Every partition of some level of T into µ-many pieces will be an element of the set ([η + ] η ) µ. η + implies ([η + ] η ) µ = η +, so we can index the elements of ([η + ] η ) µ by (25) ([η + ] η ) µ = {W α : + } = { F α,β : β<µ : + }, where each F α,β [η + ] η. It will be useful later that α <η +, the elements of W α are ordered. The collection {W α : + } will include all partitions of levels of T. The functions f :(η + ) <η µ <λ include all the strategies for P2. η µ λ and η + imply (η + ) <η µ <λ = η +,soletφ:(η + ) <η µ <λ η + be a bijection. For each +, we will construct Lev(α) =η (α +1)\η α and a partition P α of Lev(α). {P α : + } will be used later to show that P2 does not have a winning strategy. Construction of (T, ) and{p α : + }: Let Lev(0) = η. Let P 0 = P 0,β : β<µ be a partition of Lev(0) into µ-many non-empty subsets. Let and suppose Lev(α) andp α have been constructed. Let s : η µ η (α +2)\η (α + 1) be a bijection. γ <ηlet S γ = {s(γ,β) :β<µ}. For each γ<η, let the immediate successors of η α + γ Lev(α) be the elements of S γ. This constructs Lev(α +1). For β<µ,letp α+1,β = {s(γ,β) :γ<η}, andlet P α+1 = P α+1,β : β<µ. P α+1 is a partition of Lev(α +1)into µ-many disjoint subsets, each of size η.

GAMES IN BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS 317 Now consider a limit ordinal + and suppose that β < α,lev(β) and P β have been constructed. Let T α = β<α Lev(β). Let (a) be the statement, T α = α, {P β : β<α} {W β : β<α}, andφ (α <η µ <λ )=α. If (a) does not hold, then for each t T α,pickoneα-branch B t T α which contains t and put one element of η (α +1)\η α on top of B t at level α. Do this in such a way that Lev(α) =η (α +1)\η α. Suppose (a) holds. Let A α : + be a η +-sequence fixed throughout the construction of T. Let (b) be the statement, A α is a maximal antichain in T α, and let (c) be the statement, A α = φ(f) α for some f :(η + ) <η µ <λ. Let t T α. If (b) holds, then u A α such that t u or t u; letr T α such that r t, u. If (b) does not hold, then let r = t. If (c) does not hold, then pick B t T α an α-branch containing r and put one element of η (α +1)\η α above B t at level α. Otherwise, (c) holds. Let δ =ht(r) andletg : δ +2 η + be the function such that γ δ +1, W g(γ) = P γ. If P1 plays the sequence P γ : γ δ +1 and P2 follows f, then on the δ + 1-st round, P2 chooses (26) {F g(δ+1),β : β f( g(γ) :γ δ +1 )} = {P δ+1,β : β f( g(γ) :γ δ +1 )}. Let ζ<µbe such that ζ / f( g(γ) :γ δ +1 ). By construction, there exists exactly one successor of r in P δ+1,ζ,says. Choose an α-branch B t T α which contains s and put one element of η (α +1)\η α above B t at level α. Do this for each t T α in such a manner that Lev(α) =η (α +1)\η α. Now that Lev(α) has been constructed, choose a partition P α = P α,β : β<µ of Lev(α) into µ-many non-empty, disjoint subsets. Let T = + Lev(α). Let C L = {α < η + : α is a limit ordinal}, C T = {α <η + : T α = α}, C P = {α <η + : {P γ : γ < α} {W γ : γ < α}}, and C φ = {α <η + : φ (α <η µ <λ )=α}. It is not hard to show that C L,C T,C P, and C φ are c.u.b. subsets of η +. (Regularity of η is necessary to ensure that C φ is c.u.b.) By the usual argument, T is an η + -Suslin tree. r.o.(t ) satisfies the (η, )-d.l., so P1 does not have a winning strategy in G η 1 (κ), by Theorem 1.4 (2). Since Gη 1 (κ) is easier for P1 to win than G η <λ (κ), P1 does not have a winning strategy in Gη <λ (κ). Claim. P2 does not have a winning strategy in G η <λ (κ) played in r.o.(t ). f :(η + ) <η µ <λ be a strategy for P2, and let Let (27) α C L C T C P C φ {β<η + : φ(f) β = A β }. Let p Lev(α), t T α such that p is placed above B t in the construction of Lev(α), δ =ht(t), and s B t Lev(δ +1). Letg : δ +2 η + be the function such that β δ +1,W g(β) = P β. Statements (a) and (c) hold for α, so the construction of Lev(α) ensures that s P δ+1,ζ for some ζ / f( g(γ) :γ δ +1 ). Thus, s does not get chosen by f when P1 plays the sequence P β : β<α ; thatis, (28) s/ {P δ+1,θ : θ f( g(γ) :γ δ +1 )}. p s implies there is no α-branch in β<α {Pβ,θ : θ f( g(γ) : γ β )} below p. Since this holds for all p Lev(α), f is not a winning strategy for P2 in r.o.(t ).

318 NATASHA DOBRINEN 3. Open problems Example 2 reveals a curious fact: For η regular, (η, )-distributivity does not imply P2 has a winning strategy in the game G η <λ (κ), for any κ and any ω<λ min(η, κ), even though it is much easier for P2 to win G η <λ (κ) thangη 1. Problem 1. Show within ZFC that the existence of a winning strategy for P2 in G η <λ (κ) is stronger than the (η, < λ, κ)-d.l.; or else find a model of ZFC in which they are equivalent. Kamburelis showed that P1 does not have a winning strategy in Gfin ω (κ) iffthe weak (ω, κ)-d.l. holds and V B =[κ] ω V is stationary [6]. Problem 2. Find a complete characterization of the non-existence of a winning strategy for P1 in G η <λ (κ) intermsofthe(η, < λ, κ)-d.l. and an extra condition similar to that of Kamburelis. References 1. M. Foreman, Games played on Boolean algebras, J. Symbolic Logic 48 (3) (1983), 714-723. MR 85h:03064 2. S. Fuchino, H. Mildenberger, S. Shelah and P. Vojtáš, On absolutely divergent series, Fund. Math. 160 (3) (1999), 255-268. MR 2000g:03107 3. T. Jech, A game theoretic property of Boolean algebras, Logic Colloquium 77 (1978), 135-144. MR 80c:90184 4., More game-theoretic properties of Boolean algebras, Ann. Pure and Appl. Logic 26 (1984), 11-29. MR 85j:03110 5., Distributive Laws, Handbook of Boolean Algebra, Vol. 2, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1989, pp. 317-331. CMP 21:10 6. A. Kamburelis, On the weak distributivity game, Ann. Pure and Appl. Logic 66 (1994), 19-26. MR 95d:04004 7. S. Koppelberg, Handbook of Boolean Algebra, Vol. 1, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1989. MR 90k:06002 Department of Mathematics, The Pennsylvania State University, 218 McAllister Building, University Park, Pennsylvania 16802 E-mail address: dobrinen@math.psu.edu