NOTES ON SQUARES, SCALES, AND REFLECTION

Σχετικά έγγραφα
Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit

Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set

2 Composition. Invertible Mappings

ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II

ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER

SINGULAR CARDINALS AND SQUARE PROPERTIES

Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers

On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions.

Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees

C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions

Example Sheet 3 Solutions

Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in

EE512: Error Control Coding

2. Let H 1 and H 2 be Hilbert spaces and let T : H 1 H 2 be a bounded linear operator. Prove that [T (H 1 )] = N (T ). (6p)

Splitting stationary sets from weak forms of Choice

Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor

Cardinals. Y = n Y n. Define h: X Y by f(x) if x X n X n+1 and n is even h(x) = g

Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs

Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequality for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x, y, z X.

A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation

Finite Field Problems: Solutions

HOMEWORK 4 = G. In order to plot the stress versus the stretch we define a normalized stretch:

Reminders: linear functions

Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests

3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β

Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests

Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics

Chapter 2. Ordinals, well-founded relations.

Math221: HW# 1 solutions

Section 8.3 Trigonometric Equations

ω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω

Matrices and Determinants

5. Choice under Uncertainty

Practice Exam 2. Conceptual Questions. 1. State a Basic identity and then verify it. (a) Identity: Solution: One identity is csc(θ) = 1

Second Order Partial Differential Equations

Homework 3 Solutions

Απόκριση σε Μοναδιαία Ωστική Δύναμη (Unit Impulse) Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο. Απόστολος Σ.

Section 9.2 Polar Equations and Graphs

Lecture 34 Bootstrap confidence intervals

ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC = DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION #2. h 0 h h 0 h h 0 ( ) g k = g 0 + g 1 + g g 2009 =?

MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS

4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1)

Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude

12. Radon-Nikodym Theorem

F A S C I C U L I M A T H E M A T I C I

SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS

Phys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required)

1. Introduction and Preliminaries.

Econ 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1

Lecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic

SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES G11LMA Linear Mathematics Examination Solutions

A Two-Sided Laplace Inversion Algorithm with Computable Error Bounds and Its Applications in Financial Engineering

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

Partial Differential Equations in Biology The boundary element method. March 26, 2013

derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates

Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

Knaster-Reichbach Theorem for 2 κ

SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

Online Appendix I. 1 1+r ]}, Bψ = {ψ : Y E A S S}, B W = +(1 s)[1 m (1,0) (b, e, a, ψ (0,a ) (e, a, s); q, ψ, W )]}, (29) exp( U(d,a ) (i, x; q)

Lecture 21: Properties and robustness of LSE

Homework 8 Model Solution Section

Numerical Analysis FMN011

P-IDEAL DICHOTOMY AND WEAK SQUARES

( y) Partial Differential Equations

Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3

Tridiagonal matrices. Gérard MEURANT. October, 2008

Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5. Luca Alberucci, University of Berne. Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008

w o = R 1 p. (1) R = p =. = 1

On a four-dimensional hyperbolic manifold with finite volume

Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II

Problem Set 3: Solutions

6.1. Dirac Equation. Hamiltonian. Dirac Eq.

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 19/5/2007

Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations

Iterated trilinear fourier integrals with arbitrary symbols

Intuitionistic Fuzzy Ideals of Near Rings

Physical DB Design. B-Trees Index files can become quite large for large main files Indices on index files are possible.

3.2 Simple Roots and Weyl Group

The challenges of non-stable predicates

DIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANSFORMATION SEMIGROUPS

THE GENERAL INDUCTIVE ARGUMENT FOR MEASURE ANALYSES WITH ADDITIVE ORDINAL ALGEBRAS

Solutions to Exercise Sheet 5

Quadratic Expressions

The Simply Typed Lambda Calculus

6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes

Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2

Section 7.6 Double and Half Angle Formulas

THE SECOND ISOMORPHISM THEOREM ON ORDERED SET UNDER ANTIORDERS. Daniel A. Romano

Fourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics

Srednicki Chapter 55

Arithmetical applications of lagrangian interpolation. Tanguy Rivoal. Institut Fourier CNRS and Université de Grenoble 1

Some new generalized topologies via hereditary classes. Key Words:hereditary generalized topological space, A κ(h,µ)-sets, κµ -topology.

New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines

de Rham Theorem May 10, 2016

CHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS

Cyclic or elementary abelian Covers of K 4

DESIGN OF MACHINERY SOLUTION MANUAL h in h 4 0.

Second Order RLC Filters

Transcript:

NOTES ON SQUARES, SCALES, AND REFLECTION MAXWELL LEVINE 1. Some Basic Facts Proposition 1. If κ <κ = κ, then κ holds. Proof. We define C α : α < κ + by considering the cases of cf α < κ and cf α = κ separately. If cf α < κ, then let C α = {C α : C club in α, C < κ, cf β < κ β C}. Since α κ and κ <κ = κ, we have C α κ as required (the C α s are also clearly nonempty). We can t use the same trick in the cf α = κ case because κ κ > κ. Instead we choose a club C in α of order type κ and let C α = {C}. Observe that if β lim C for C C α, then C β C β : If cf α < κ, then this is immediate since we guarantee that cf β < κ. If cf α = κ and β lim(c) for C C α, then o. t.(c β) < κ, so C β C β. Proposition 2. If SCH κ fails (where κ is a singular strong limit such that 2 κ > κ + ) then Refl(cf κ, κ + ) fails. Proof. Assume without loss of generality that cf κ = ω, and suppose for contradiction that Refl(ω, κ + ) holds while SCH κ fails. Decompose κ + into κ-many disjoint stationary sets S α : α < κ. This can be done by appealing to Solovay s Theorem or using the canonical stationary sets for regular cardinals less than κ. Let f : κ ω κ + by given by mapping α n : n < ω to the point below κ + where S αn : n < ω simultaneously reflects. There is a set X κ ω of cardinality at least κ ++ on which f is constant with value γ: this follows from regularity of κ ++ and the fact that κ ω = 2 κ κ ++. We claim that there is a sequence S βi : i < κ of stationary sets in γ. This suffices for our proof because if C γ is a club and o. t. C = cf γ < κ (noting that κ is singular, so any ordinal below κ + has cofinality strictly less than κ), then C cannot possibly meet all of the S βi s and thus we obtain a contradiction. Define β i : i < κ as follows: Pick an arbitrary sequence in X and let β 0 be its first element. If we have already defined β i : i < δ, then observe that P ({β i : i < δ}) < κ because κ X and κ is a strong limit. Hence there is a sequence s X \ P ({β i : i < δ}), so we can pick β δ s \ {β i : i < δ}. The S βi s are disjoint by construction, and S βi γ is stationary for all i < κ because β i s X. Proposition 3. κ κ + I[κ + ], i.e. AP κ + holds. Proof. Let C = C α : α < κ + be a weak square sequence such that α < κ +, C C α such that o. t. C = cf α (this property is equivalent to the usual weak square) and let M = H θ,, < θ, C for θ large enough. We claim that all points in the club (κ, κ + ) are approachable with regard to M. Say α (κ, κ + ) and N = Sk M (α). Since M contains an enumeration of C α and κ N, we can assume C α N by elementarity. Pick C C α with o. t. C = cf α, 1

2 MAXWELL LEVINE which will witness approachability of α: For all β < α, C β C β by definition of the square sequence and so C β N. 2. Forcing and Approachability Theorem 1. If P is countably closed and S κ cf(ω) is stationary in V, then S is stationary in V P. Proof. Let C V P be a club in κ and let p, Ċ witness this. Let M = H θ, p, P, Ċ, κ (where H θ is all sets with transitive closure of size less than θ, and θ is large enough for p, P, Ċ, κ H θ). It s easy enough to show that D = {x P κ (θ) : x = dom(n), N M} and D = {sup(x κ) : x D} are both clubs in P κ (θ) and κ respectively. Therefore there is N M with α = sup(n κ) S. Since α S cf(ω), we can write α = sup n<ω α n with α n : n < ω N by elementarily. Construct a decreasing sequence p n : n < ω N and an increasing β n : n < ω N as follows: Using that p Ċ is unbounded in κ and p n p, find p n+1, β n+1 N such that p n+1 β n+1 Ċ and β n+1 β n, α n (again, using elementarily). Note that β n+1 < α for all n since sup(n κ) = α. Use countable closure to find q p n for all n < ω. Then since sup β n = sup α n = α (by interleaving) and q Ċ unbounded, α n Ċ n < ω, we have q p with q α Ċ. We showed that {q p : q Ċ S } is dense, so we are done. Let I[κ] be the approachability ideal. Theorem 2. If P is µ + -closed, S κ cf(µ), and S I[κ], then V P = S is stationary. Proof. Let C V P be a club in κ with p Ċ club in κ. Since S I[κ], there is a = a β : β < κ and a club D such that every point in D S is approachable with regard to a. Let M = H θ, κ, µ, p, P, Ċ, a. Then E = {x H θ (κ) : x = dom(n), N M} and E = {sup(x κ) : x E} are both clubs. If γ E S D, then γ then there is some N M such that sup(n κ) = γ. Let A γ witness the approachability of γ with regard to a so o. t. A = µ and {A β : β < γ} {a β : β < γ}. Write A = {α ξ : ξ < µ}. Define an increasing p ξ : ξ < µ N and a decreasing β ξ : ξ < µ N as follows: For ξ = 0, just pick p 0 p and β 0 such that p 0 β 0 Ċ. For ξ > 0, since sup(n κ) = γ > α ξ, there is α ξ β < γ, β N. M = x a, sup x < β (because A β = a β for some β < γ), so N satisfies the same statement, witnessed by some α. Pick p ξ p ν ( η < ξ, using µ + -closure) such that p ξ β ξ Ċ, β ξ > α. Finally use µ + closure to find q p ξ for all ξ < µ. Then sup A = sup α ξ = sup β ξ = γ, and so q γ S Ċ. We showed {q p : q Ċ S } and so we are done by density. 3. Supercompactness versus Squares and Scales Let κ be supercompact, let λ κ, and let j : V M be a λ-supercompact embedding. Proposition 4. If s is a sequence of length less that κ then j(s) = j s. Proof. By elementarity, x s implies j(x) j(s); hence j s j(s). If s = x ξ : ξ < τ and τ < κ then j(s) = α ξ : ξ < j(τ) = τ. V = α ξ is the ξ th element

NOTES ON SQUARES, SCALES, AND REFLECTION 3 of s, so M = j(α ξ ) is the j(ξ) = ξ th element of s. Hence j(α ξ ) = αξ and so j(s) j s. Proposition 5. If ρ = sup j λ and C ρ is a club in M, then C = {α : j(α) C} is a < κ-club in λ. Proof. κ-closure: suppose s = α ξ : ξ < τ C and τ < κ and β = sup s. Then j(β) = j(sup s) = sup j(s) = sup j s C, so β C. unboundedness: Let α < λ. Pick β 0 C such that j(α) < β 0 < ρ and γ 0 < λ such that β 0 < j(γ 0 ). In general pick β n+1 C with j(γ n ) < β n+1 and γ n < λ with β n < j(γ n to define s = β n : n < ω and t = γ n : n < ω such that s and j t are interleaving. If γ = sup t then j(γ) = j(sup t) = sup j(t) = sup j t = sup s C, so γ C. Proposition 6. If ρ = sup j λ, then ρ < j(λ). Proof. This is because ρ = [x sup x] (if f : x sup x then (jf)(j λ) = f(j λ) = [f]) and j(λ) = [x λ]. Since sup x < λ for all x P κ (λ) the result follows from Los. Theorem 3. If κ is supercompact and λ κ then λ fails. Proof. Let j : V M be a λ + -supercompact embedding and C = C α : α < λ +, lim(α) be a λ sequence. Then j(c) = Cα : α < j(λ + ) is a j(λ) sequence by elementarity. Let C = {α : j(α) Cρ} where ρ = sup j λ +. C is a < κ-club in λ +. We will argue that o.t.(c α) < λ for α < λ +. This implies that C has no λ th element (for one) and therefore cannot be cofinal in λ +. Fix α < λ +. Pick β lim(c) such that α < β < λ + and cf β < κ. If γ C β then j(λ) < j(β) and j(γ) Cρ. Furthermore Cρ j(β) = Cj(β) = j(c β), and so j(γ) j(c β ), implying γ C β byi elementarity. We have demonstrated that C α C β C β. Because cf β < κ λ it follows that o.t.c β < λ and therefore that o.t.(c α) < λ. Proposition 7. Let f α : α < κ be a scale in a singular cardinal κ and suppose α < κ + and cf α > cf κ. Then the following are equivalent definitions of α being a good point: (1) There exists an unbounded A α, i < cf κ, such that β, γ A, j i, β < γ implies f β (j) < f γ (j). (2) There exists an exact upper bound h for f β : β < α and j < cf κ such that cf h(i) = cf(α) for j i < cf κ. (3) There exists a pointwise increasing sequence h γ : γ < cf α cofinally interleaved modulo I with f β : β < α. 1 2. Given A and i define h(j) = sup β A f β (j) for j i and 0 otherwise. Without loss of generality A = cf α, so cf h(j) cf α for j i. The fact that f β (j) : β A is strictly increasing tells us that cf h(j) cf α. To show that h is an upper bound for the sequence, suppose γ < α. There is some β A with γ < β. Since f γ < I f β, j such that i j implies f γ (i) < f β (i) < sup{f δ (i) : δ A} = h(i), i.e. f γ < I h. We must show that f β : β < α is cofinal in h before we are done. Suppose g < I h. There is j such that j i implies g(i) < h(i). Pick β i A such that g(i) < f βi (i), and let γ = sup i<cf κ β i < α (because cf α > cf κ). Then g < I f γ.

4 MAXWELL LEVINE 2 3. There is g i : cf α h(i) cofinal and increasing for all i < cf κ. Let h γ (i) = g i (γ) for every γ < cf α. There h γ s are pointwise increasing because the g i s are increasing. Since h γ < I h and since h is an exact upper bound for f β : β < α, there is β < α with h γ < I f β. We still need to show that for every β < α, there is γ < cf α such that f β < h γ. Fixing β, the fact that f β < I h implies there is a j such that f β (i) < h(i) for every i j. Suppose towards a contradiction that γ k i k such that h γ (k) f β (i). Then if k = j the assignment γ i is regressive for γ > cf κ (again because cf α > cf κ), so by Fodor s Theorem there is a stationary S cf α and i 0 j on which h γ (j) f β (i 0 ) for i 0 j and all γ S. Then g j (γ) f β (i 0 ) < h(j) for unboundedly many γ < cf α, contradicting the fact that g j is cofinal in h(j). It follows that there is some γ such that f β < I h γ. 3 1. Define β δ : δ < cf α and γ δ < cf α such that f βδ < I < h βδ < I f βδ+1, etc. For every δ < cf α there is i δ such that j i δ implies f βδ (j) < h βδ (j). The function δ iδ is regressive for δ > cf κ, so there is a stationary A cf α on which j i 0 implies f βδ (j) < h βδ (j). Since the h s are pointwise increasing, it follows that f γ (j) : γ A is strictly increasing for j i 0. Theorem 4. If κ is supercompact, κ < λ, and cf λ < κ, then every scale on λ is bad. Proof. Let j : V M be a λ + -supercompact embedding and λ, f be a scale on the ideal I cf λ where λ = λ i : i < cf λ and f = f α : α < λ +. Let ρ = sup j λ +. Note that j(f) = fα : α < j(λ + ). We claim that ρ is a bad point for j(f). It follows that if C λ + is a club then M = j(c) contains a bad point of j(f) (because ρ j(c)); thus V = {α < λ + : α is a bad point of f} is stationary. A key fact is that since M λ+ M it follows that (cf α) M = (cf α) V if cf α λ +. Hence ρ < j(λ + ) because cf ρ = λ +. By the above proposition it is enough to dispay an exact upper bound h for fα : α < ρ such that cf h(i) : i < cf λ is bounded below λ +. Let h be given by h(i) = sup j λ i. h is an upper bound of fα : α < ρ : for all α < ρ there is some β < λ + such that α < j(β), and so fα < j(i) fj(β) = j(f β) < h by elementarity and the fact that f(i) < λ i for all i < cf κ. Also, cf h(i) = λ i < λ + for all i. 4. Some Relevant Facts on Forcing Theorem 5. The following are equivalent definitions of a κ-distributive poset P (assuming that P is separative): (1) For all λ < κ, if D α : α < λ is a sequence of open dense sets in P, then α<λ D α is open dense. (2) If λ < κ, f : λ V, and f V P, then f V. (3) If λ < κ, f : λ ON, and f V P, then f V. 2 1. Let λ < κ and let D α : α < λ be a sequence of open sense sets. It s rather simple to see that α<λ D α is open, so our task is to show that the intersection is dense. For each α < λ let A α D α be a maximal antichain and let f = { α, ˇq, q : q A α }. Fix p P and take p G to be P-generic over V. By our hypothesis f G V, so there is some g V with g(α) = q α A α such that g = f G. Let r G be such that

NOTES ON SQUARES, SCALES, AND REFLECTION 5 r p and r f = ǧ. We claim that r q α for every α < λ and hence r D α for all α < λ using openness. Suppose s q α. Then by separativity there is some t s such that t q α. Let t G be generic. Then there is some q G A α such that q q α (because G must intersect every maximal antichain but cannot contain incompatible elements) and therefore f G (α) = q q α. Therefore s f = ǧ. It follows that r q α for all α. 1 2. Let f : λ V be in V [G] where G is P-generic. There is some p G and A V such that p f : λ A. Our goal is to show that D = {q p : g V, r ǧ = f} is dense below p. Then there is some q G D and so f = g V. The set D α = {q P : a A, q f(α) = a} = {q P : q f(α)} is open dense. Let q p, q α<λ D α. Then we claim that f(α) is the unique a A such that q f(α) = a. Since q D α, there is such an a, and moreover it is unique since q cannot force contradictory information. 2 3. This is immediate since ON V. 3 2. Let A ON be a code for im f. (That is, if B = tc(im f), and g : τ B is a bijection, and C = {(α, β) : g(α) g(β)}, and D = {g(α) : α B}, then A = Γ[D] where Γ is the canonical bijection ON ON ON.) Then h : λ A ON V, so f V. Theorem 6 (Easton). Let P be κ-c.c. and Q be κ-closed. Then Q is λ-distributive in V P. We first need two facts: Lemma 1. If Q is λ-distributive, H is Q-generic, and q ξ : ξ < µ is descending in Q for µ < λ, then there is q H such that q q ξ for all ξ < µ. Proof. Define D ξ = {p Q : p q ξ or p q ξ } which is open dense, so D := ξ<µ D ξ is open dense. Assume by induction that q ξ H for all ξ < µ and let q H Q. q q ξ because H is a filter, so it follows that q q ξ for all ξ < µ. Lemma 2. If P is κ-c.c. and Q is κ-closed, then V Q = P is κ-c.c. Proof. Suppose q Q and q f : κ A enumerates a maximal antichain. Then using κ-closure we can define a decreasing sequence q ξ : ξ < κ and p ξ : ξ < κ such that ξ < κ, q ξ f(ξ) = p ξ. All of the p ξ s are incomparible: if ξ < η < κ, then q ξ p ξ p η, which implies that V = p ξ p η. Hence p ξ : ξ < κ is an antichain of size κ in V. Proof of Easton s Theorem. Let G be P-generic and let H be Q-generic. Our goal is to show that if f V [G][H] and f : λ ON for λ < κ, then it follows that f V [G]. Without loss of generality assume that f is forced by the empty condition in P Q. Define D α = {p P : q H, (p, q) ϕ(α)} V [H], which is open dense (a fact that uses that we can define P Q-generic filter K in terms of G and H). Let A α D α be a maximal antichain for each α < λ. Note that P has the κ chain in V Q because Q does not add new κ-sized sets and an antichain A in V Q will remain

6 MAXWELL LEVINE an antichain in V. It follows that A α < κ and therefore A α V (again because of λ-closure) for all α. Let us then enumerate A α = {p α,β : β < κ α < κ}. Use the lemma to define a lexicographically ordered descending sequence q α,β : α < τ, β < κ α of conditions in H such that (p α,β, q α,β ) f(α). Let q q α,β for all indices. Then we claim that f(α) =!β s.t. p G, (p, q) f(α) = β. We know that p α,β G A α for some β and (p α,β, q) (p α,β, q α,β ), so such a p exists. Moreover, p won t force contradictory information. Since f is defined using G and q V, it follows that f V [G]. Definition 1. Given a poset P we define the game G α (P) for two players as follows: Suppose β α and we are given p ξ : ξ < β. If β is an even successor or a limit, then player I selects p β such that p β p ξ for ξ < β. If β is an oddtheorem successor then player II selects p β p ξ for ξ < β. P is κ-strategically closed if player II has a winning strategy for G α (P) for all α < κ. Theorem 7. If P is κ-strategically closed, then it is κ-distributive. Proof. Suppose λ < κ and f : λ ON is a function in V P. Define p ξ : ξ < λ as follows: If ξ+1 is an odd successor, then pick p ξ+1 p ξ such that p ξ+1 f(ξ), f(ξ+1). If ξ is an even successor or limit, than use the winning strategy of player II to select p ξ p η for η < ξ. Finally use the winning strategy of player II to choose q p ξ for all ξ < λ. Then if g : λ ON is defined such that g(ξ) is the unique β such that q f(ξ) = β, then g V and q g = f, so we are done by density.