Completeness Theorem for System AS1

Σχετικά έγγραφα
Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set

2 Composition. Invertible Mappings

Lecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic

Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit

Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers

C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions

Homework 3 Solutions

MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS

Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs

Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor

A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation

ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II

ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

2. Let H 1 and H 2 be Hilbert spaces and let T : H 1 H 2 be a bounded linear operator. Prove that [T (H 1 )] = N (T ). (6p)

Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in

ω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω

Finite Field Problems: Solutions

EE512: Error Control Coding

Homomorphism in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Automata

Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequality for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x, y, z X.

Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests

Example Sheet 3 Solutions

CHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS

Section 8.3 Trigonometric Equations

derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates

Reminders: linear functions

3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β

4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1)

18 Completeness Theorem for Axiom System AS1+Q for CPL

Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests

Matrices and Determinants

On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions.

Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016

Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5. Luca Alberucci, University of Berne. Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008

Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics

Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees

Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3

HOMEWORK 4 = G. In order to plot the stress versus the stretch we define a normalized stretch:

Phys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required)

New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines

Fourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics

The Simply Typed Lambda Calculus

Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets

5. Choice under Uncertainty

About these lecture notes. Simply Typed λ-calculus. Types

Problem Set 3: Solutions

Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2

Generating Set of the Complete Semigroups of Binary Relations

SCITECH Volume 13, Issue 2 RESEARCH ORGANISATION Published online: March 29, 2018

Econ 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

The challenges of non-stable predicates

CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS

Solution Series 9. i=1 x i and i=1 x i.

Main source: "Discrete-time systems and computer control" by Α. ΣΚΟΔΡΑΣ ΨΗΦΙΑΚΟΣ ΕΛΕΓΧΟΣ ΔΙΑΛΕΞΗ 4 ΔΙΑΦΑΝΕΙΑ 1

Tridiagonal matrices. Gérard MEURANT. October, 2008

1. Introduction and Preliminaries.

Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II

Space-Time Symmetries

Chapter 2. Ordinals, well-founded relations.

DIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANSFORMATION SEMIGROUPS

Second Order Partial Differential Equations

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 6/5/2006

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 19/5/2007

Απόκριση σε Μοναδιαία Ωστική Δύναμη (Unit Impulse) Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο. Απόστολος Σ.

Overview. Transition Semantics. Configurations and the transition relation. Executions and computation

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations

Lecture 21: Properties and robustness of LSE

Cardinals. Y = n Y n. Define h: X Y by f(x) if x X n X n+1 and n is even h(x) = g

12. Radon-Nikodym Theorem

Solutions to Exercise Sheet 5

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

Math221: HW# 1 solutions

SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS

Second Order RLC Filters

A Bonus-Malus System as a Markov Set-Chain. Małgorzata Niemiec Warsaw School of Economics Institute of Econometrics

Srednicki Chapter 55

de Rham Theorem May 10, 2016

F A S C I C U L I M A T H E M A T I C I

Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude

SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES G11LMA Linear Mathematics Examination Solutions

Μηχανική Μάθηση Hypothesis Testing

A Conception of Inductive Logic: Example

Exercises to Statistics of Material Fatigue No. 5

TMA4115 Matematikk 3

The Semantic Characterization of Logic

SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM

Strukturalna poprawność argumentu.

Solutions to Selected Homework Problems 1.26 Claim: α : S S which is 1-1 but not onto β : S S which is onto but not 1-1. y z = z y y, z S.

SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM

ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC = DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION #2. h 0 h h 0 h h 0 ( ) g k = g 0 + g 1 + g g 2009 =?

Partial Differential Equations in Biology The boundary element method. March 26, 2013

Notes on the Open Economy

Coefficient Inequalities for a New Subclass of K-uniformly Convex Functions

3.2 Simple Roots and Weyl Group

Solutions for exercises in chapter 1 = 2, 3, 1, 4 ; = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2 1 S 1 1 S 0 = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2, 1, 4,1,3. 1, 1,..., 1, S 0

Example of the Baum-Welch Algorithm

Transcript:

11 The Completeness Theorem for System AS1 1. Introduction...2 2. Previous Definitions...2 3. Deductive Consistency...2 4. Maximal Consistent Sets...5 5. Lindenbaum s Lemma...6 6. Every Maximal Consistent Set is Verifiable...8 7. Every Deductively Consistent Set is Semantically Consistent...9 8. The Completeness Theorems...9 9. Appendix: Supporting Lemmas...10

2 Hardegree, MetaLogic 1. Introduction Having proved the soundness of system AS1 relative to the usual truth-functional semantics for CSL, we now turn to the converse problem of completeness. Unlike the way we handled soundness, we do not warm up by proving a weak completeness theorem; rather, we first prove the strong completeness theorem, then prove the weak completeness theorem as a special case. As usual, the supporting lemmas are included in the appendix. 2. Previous Definitions First, let us recall the relevant definitions. α = df v{v V v(α)=t} Γ α = df v{v V. x(x Γ v(x)=t) v(α)=t} α = df there is a proof of α in Γ α = df there is a derivation of α from Γ in Def Let V be a class of valuations, and let be an axiom system, both defined over a common language. Define and in the customary way. Then: is complete relative to V wrt formulas = df α{ α α}. is complete relative to V wrt arguments = df Γ α{γ α Γ α}. 3. Deductive Consistency Recall from a previous chapter the definition of deductive inconsistency, which is followed by the obvious correlated definition of deductive consistency.

11: Completeness Theorem for AS1 3 Def Γ is deductively inconsistent = df α[γ α] Γ is deductively consistent = df Γ is not deductively inconsistent, Γ = df Γ is deductively inconsistent Γ = df Γ is deductively consistent In regard to AS1, we can prove the following theorems about deductive (in)consistency. [Note carefully: since we use ambiguously, one must be careful in reading formulas. For example, α Γ means that the object language formula α ¹is an element of Γ, whereas [α Γ] means that α is not an element of Γ; the latter is more often expressed by the formula α Γ. In this connection, recall that two-place infix predicates officially include outer brackets.] (T38) Γ is deductively inconsistent there is a formula α such that Γ α & Γ α. Γ{Γ α(γ α & Γ α)} (C) Γ is deductively consistent there is no formula α such that Γ α & Γ α. Γ{Γ α(γ α & Γ α)} Proof: [ ] Suppose Γ, to show α(γ α & Γ α). By the definition of inconsistency, α[γ α], so by the relevant rules of formation, and QL, α(γ α & Γ α). [ ] Suppose α(γ α & Γ α), to show: Γ, which amounts to showing: β[γ β]. Consider any formula β. By T8+T10, Γ α (α β), so by T14 (twice), Γ β. Deductive consistency is contrasted with semantic consistency, which we have called verifiability; Γ is semantically consistent (verifiable) in V iff there is a valuation v in V that verifies every formula in Γ. As noted earlier, deductive consistency is not the exact counterpart of semantic consistency, at least in general. However, in special circumstances, including classical logic, they are very close counterparts, in the sense that the following is a theorem. [Note: In what follows, unless otherwise specified, we presume the usual truth-functional semantics for CSL, relative to which the various instances of are defined, and we presume axiom system AS1, relative to which the various instances of are defined; as usual, we also presume the usual quantifier and sortal conventions.] (T) Γ is deductively consistent Γ is semantically consistent. We first prove the if half of this theorem, by appealing to the Soundness Theorem (ST), and T38, above. The only if half, which is considerably harder, is proven later. (T39) Γ is semantically consistent Γ is deductively consistent

4 Hardegree, MetaLogic (i.e.) Every semantically consistent set is deductively consistent. Proof: Suppose Γ is semantically consistent, to show Γ is deductively consistent. Suppose, to the contrary, that Γ is deductively inconsistent, to show a contradiction. By T38, there is a formula, call it α, such that Γ α and Γ α. So, by the Soundness Theorem, Γ α and Γ α. By hypothesis, Γ is semantically consistent, so there is a valuation, call it v, that verifies every formula in Γ. But Γ semantically entails both α and α, so v verifies both α and α, which contradicts Lemma 1. Next, we prove two theorems, very similar to one another, about the relation between deductive consistency and deductive entailment (derivability). (T40) Γ { α} Γ α Proof: [ ] Suppose Γ { α}, to show Γ α. Then there is a formula, call it β, such that Γ { α} β, and Γ { α} β. So by DT, Γ α β, and Γ α β. But by T36, { α β, α β} α, so by Lemma 2, Γ α. [ ] Suppose Γ α, to show Γ { α}, which amounts to showing β[γ { α} β]. Since Γ α, by T18, Γ { α} α. By T8+T10, Γ α (α β), so by T17 (CDT), Γ { α} α β, so by T14, Γ { α} β. (T42) Γ {α} Γ α. Proof: This can be proved in a very similar manner to the previous one (exercise). However, for a little variety, we do it differently. In virtue of T40, Γ { α} iff Γ α, so in order to prove our theorem, we need merely prove the following lemma. (L) Γ { α} Γ {α} Proof: Given the definition of (third use), showing this amounts to showing: (1) β[γ { α} β] β[γ {α} β] But, given QL, in order to show (1), it is sufficient to show: (2) β{γ { α} β Γ {α} β} This follows from T20(c),T21(c), and the following lemma, which we now prove. (T41) {α} β & {β} α.. Γ {α} γ Γ {β} γ Proof: Suppose {α} β and {β} α, to show: Γ {α} γ iff Γ {β} γ. [ ] Suppose Γ {α} γ, to show: Γ {β} γ. By hyp, {β} α, so by T18, Γ {β} α. Also, by hyp, Γ {α} γ, so by T18, Γ {β} {α} γ; so, by T19, Γ {β} γ. The converse [ ] argument is obtained by symmetry.

11: Completeness Theorem for AS1 5 4. Maximal Consistent Sets In what follows, for the sake of brevity, we use consistent as shorthand for deductively consistent. An important step in proving the Completeness Theorem involves proving a lemma, known as Lindenbaum s Lemma, which claims that every (deductively) consistent set can be extended to a maximal (deductively) consistent set. In order to understand this lemma, we must understand the term maximal, which is a general set theoretic term, defined as follows. Def Let K a collection of sets. Then a K-maximal set is, by definition, a set M satisfying the following conditions. (1) M K (2) X{X K [M X]} i.e., (1*) M is a K-set (2*) M is not properly included in any K-set. The application of this concept to any particular situation involves identifying the relevant class K. In our particular case, K is the class of consistent sets of formulas, in which case we obtain the following instance. Def Let Γ be a set of formulas. Then Γ is a maximal consistent set if and only if: (1) Γ is consistent (2) Γ is not properly included in any consistent set. MC[Γ] = df Γ is a maximal consistent set One way to think of maximal consistent sets is as follows; if Γ is maximal consistent, then adding any formula α to Γ results in an inconsistent set. This is the content of the next theorem. (T43) MC[Γ] & α Γ. Γ {α} Proof: Suppose MC[Γ] and α Γ, to show Γ {α}. Since α Γ, Γ Γ {α}. But Γ is maximal consistent, so no proper superset of Γ is consistent, so Γ {α} is inconsistent (i.e. Γ {α} ). We next prove a important theorem, followed by an equally important corollary. (T44) Γ {α} β & Γ { α} β. Γ β

6 Hardegree, MetaLogic Proof: Suppose Γ {α} β and Γ { α} β, to show: Γ β. By a1, Γ {α} β, so by DT, Γ α β. By a2, Γ { α} β, so by DT, Γ α β. By T30+T10, Γ (α β) [( α β) β], so by T14 twice, Γ β. (C) (C) Γ {α} & Γ { α}. Γ Γ. Γ {α} or Γ { α} Proof: This follows from definition of and T44 by QL. With this lemma (and corollary) in hand, we can prove the following theorem. (T45) MC[Γ] α(α Γ α Γ) (i.e.) MC[Γ]. α(α Γ xor α Γ) Proof: Suppose Γ is MC. [ ] Suppose α Γ, to show α Γ. Suppose to the contrary that α Γ. Then, by T43, Γ {α}, and Γ { α}, so by T44(c), Γ, which contradicts the assumption that Γ is consistent. [ ] Suppose α Γ, to show α Γ. Suppose to the contrary that α Γ. Then by T12, Γ α, and Γ α, which by T38 entails that Γ is inconsistent, which contradicts the assumption that Γ is consistent. (T46) MC[Γ] α(γ α α Γ) Proof: Suppose MC[Γ], and suppose Γ α, to show α Γ. Suppose to the contrary that α Γ. Then, by T45, α Γ, and so by T12, Γ α. But, by T8+T10, Γ α (α β), for any β, so by T14 twice, Γ β, for any β, which contradicts the assumption that Γ is consistent. 5. Lindenbaum s Lemma In proving the Completeness Theorem, an important step involves proving a theorem known as Lindenbaum s Lemma, which is stated as follows. (T47) Every consistent set is a subset of a maximal consistent set. Γ{Γ is consistent (Γ & MC[ ])} Proof: Suppose Γ is consistent, to show that there is a maximal consistent set such that Γ. There are denumerably many formulas in the underlying language (Lemma 3), so the formulas can be enumerated. Let α 1, α 2, α 3,... be one such enumeration. Given this enumeration, form the infinite sequence of sets Γ 1, Γ 2,... ( Γ i for short), inductively defined as follows. Γ 1 = Γ; Γ n+1 = Γ n {α n }, if Γ n {α n } is consistent; = Γ n { α n }, otherwise. Let Ω = {Γ n : n =1,2,3,...}

11: Completeness Theorem for AS1 7 Claim: Γ Ω, and Ω is maximal consistent. Proof of claim: (1) show: Γ Ω; this follows from the fact that Γ=Γ 1, and Γ 1 Ω. The latter follows from the definition of Ω, together with set theory [including the ST theorem: X X ]. (2) show: Ω is maximal consistent; given (s2) [see below for subproofs], Ω is consistent, so all we have to show is that every proper superset of Ω is inconsistent. Suppose Ω Ω*; since Ω* properly includes Ω, there is a formula, call it α, such that α Ω*, but α Ω. By (s3), since α Ω, α Ω, so α Ω*, so by T12, Ω* α. Therefore, Ω* α, and Ω* α, which by T38 entails that Ω* is inconsistent. Subproofs of (2): (s0) show: n k(k n Γ k Γ n ); by induction [exercise]. (s1) show: n[γ n is consistent]; (by weak induction): (BC) show: Γ 1 is consistent; by hypothesis Γ is consistent, and by definition of Γ i, Γ 1 = Γ; (IH) assume: Γ n is consistent; (IS) show: Γ n+1 is consistent. By definition, Γ n+1 = Γ {α n } if the latter set is consistent, and Γ n+1 = Γ { α n }, otherwise. Suppose Γ n+1 is inconsistent (i.e., Γ n+1. Given the definition of Γ n+1, if Γ n+1, then Γ {α n } and Γ { α n }, but these, together with T44(c), entail Γ. The latter, however, contradicts IH. (s2) show: Ω is consistent; suppose Ω is inconsistent; then by T38, there is a formula, call it α, such that Ω α, and Ω α. Then there is a derivation, call it D 1, of α from Ω, and there is a derivation, call it D 2, of α from Ω. By definition, every derivation is a finite sequence; accordingly, at most finitely many premises (elements of Ω) are used in each derivation; call the two finite sets of used premises U 1 and U 2, respectively. Notice that U 1 α, and U 2 α. Let U = U 1 U 2 ; the union of any two finite sets is finite, so U is also finite. Also, by T18, U α, and U α. Since U is finite, the set {n: α n U} has a largest element; call it m. By (s2a), U Γ m+1, so by T18, Γ m+1 α, and Γ m+1 α, which, together with T38, entail that Γ m+1 is inconsistent, which contradicts (s1). (s2a) show: U Γ m+1 ; suppose α U; in virtue of the definition of m, α=α k for some k m, so α k U for some k m; it is sufficient to show α k Γ k+1, and to show Γ k+1 Γ m+1. The latter follows from (s0) and arithmetic [k m k+1 m+1]. So that leaves showing α k Γ k+1. By definition of Γ i, Γ k+1 = Γ k {α k }, if the latter is consistent; Γ k+1 = Γ k { α k }, otherwise. In the first case, clearly α k Γ k+1. In the second case, Γ k+1 = Γ k { α k }, so α k Ω, so α Ω. But by hyp, α Ω, so by (s2b), α Ω, and we have a contradiction. (s2b) show: α Ω α Ω; suppose α Ω, and α Ω, to show a contradiction. Given the definition of Ω [= {Γ 1,Γ 2,...}], α Γ i, and α Γ k, for some i,k. Without loss of generality, we may assume i k, so by (s0), α Γ k, but then Γ k α and Γ n α, which by T38 entail that Γ n is inconsistent, which contradicts (s1).

8 Hardegree, MetaLogic (s3) show: α[α Ω α Ω]; Consider an arbitrary formula α, α = α k, for some k. By definition of Γ i, Γ k+1 = Γ k {α k }, or Γ k+1 = Γ k { α k }. In the first case, α Γ k+1 ; in the second case α Γ k+1. But Γ k+1 Ω, so in either case, α Ω α Ω. 6. Every Maximal Consistent Set is Verifiable Having proven Lindenbaum s Lemma, we next prove that every maximal consistent set is verifiable. (T48) If Γ is maximal consistent, then Γ is verifiable. Proof: Suppose Γ is maximal consistent, to show that Γ is verifiable, which is to say that there is a valuation v in V that verifies every formula in Γ. Define v as follows. v(α)=t if α Γ; v(α)=f, otherwise. Claim: v is a valuation, and v verifies Γ. Given the definition of v, clearly v(α)=t for every α in Γ, so the remaining question is whether v is indeed a valuation. This amounts to the claim that v satisfies the following truth-functional requirements: (1) v( α) = v(α) (2) v(α β) = v(α) v(β) (1) case 1: α Γ, in which case v(α)=t. Also, by T45, α Γ, so v( α)=f= T= v(α); case 2: α Γ, in which case v(α)=f; Also, by T45, α Γ, so v( α)=t= F= v(α). (2) case 1: α Γ, in which case v(α)=f. Also, by T45, α Γ, so by T46, Γ α, but by T8+T10, Γ α (α β), so by T14, Γ α β, so by T46, α β Γ, so v(α β)=t = v(α) v(β); case 2: α Γ, in which case v(α)=t; c1: β Γ, in which case v(β)=t; also, by T46, Γ β; but, by T1+T10, Γ β (α β), so by T14, Γ α β, so by T46, α β Γ, so v(α β)=t = v(α) v(β); c2: β Γ, in which case v(β)=f; also, by T45, β Γ, so by T46, Γ β, and also Γ α; but by T25+T10, Γ α ( β (α β)), so by T14 (twice), Γ (α β), so by T46, (α β) Γ, so by T45, α β Γ, so v(α β)=f = v(α) v(β).

11: Completeness Theorem for AS1 9 7. Every Deductively Consistent Set is Semantically Consistent Having proven Lindenbaum s Lemma, and having proven that every maximal consistent set is verifiable, we are now in a position to prove our earlier claim that every deductively consistent set is semantically consistent. T49 Γ is deductively consistent Γ is semantically consistent. (i.e.) Every deductively consistent set is semantically consistent. Proof: Suppose Γ is deductively consistent, to show that Γ is semantically consistent, which is to say that there is a valuation v in V that verifies every formula in Γ. By Lindenbaum s Lemma, Γ is included in a maximal consistent set, call it Γ*. By T48, Γ* is verifiable. But, every subset of a verifiable set is itself verifiable, so Γ is verifiable, which is to say that Γ is semantically consistent. 8. The Completeness Theorems First, we prove the strong completeness theorem, after which we prove the weak completeness theorem, as a special case. (T50) Γ α Γ α Proof: Suppose [Γ α], to show: [Γ α]. Then, by T40, Γ { α) is consistent, so by T48, Γ { α} is verifiable, so by Lemma 4, [Γ α]. (C) α α Proof: Suppose α, to show: α. By Lemma 5, α, so by T50, α, so by Lemma 6, α.

10 Hardegree, MetaLogic 9. Appendix: Supporting Lemmas 1. Earlier Theorems (T1) α (β α) (T7) α α (T8) α (α β) (T10) α Γ α (T12) α Γ Γ α (T14) Γ α & Γ α β. Γ β (T16) Γ {α} β Γ α β (a.k.a. DT) (T17) Γ α β Γ {α} β (T18) Γ α & Γ. α (T19) Γ α & Γ {α} β. Γ β (T20) α α (c) { α} α (T21) α α (c) {α} α (T25) α ( β (α β)) (T30) (α β) [( α β) β] (T35) {α β, α β} α (c) (α β) [(α β) α] (T36) { α β, α β} α (c) ( α β) [( α β) α] (T37) Γ α Γ α (a.k.a. ST) (c) α α 2. New Theorems (T38) Γ{Γ α(γ α & Γ α)} (T39) Γ is semantically consistent Γ is deductively consistent (T40) Γ { α} Γ α (T41) {α} β & {β} α.. Γ {α} γ Γ {β} γ (T42) Γ {α} Γ α (T43) MC[Γ] & α Γ. Γ {α} (T44) Γ {α} β & Γ { α} β. Γ β (c) Γ {α} & Γ { α}. Γ (T45) MC[Γ] α(α Γ α Γ) (T46) MC[Γ] α(γ α α Γ) (T47) Γ{Γ is consistent (Γ & MC[ ])} (a.k.a. LL) (T48) Γ is maximal consistent Γ is verifiable (T49) Γ is deductively consistent Γ is semantically consistent (T50) Γ α Γ α (a.k.a. CT) (c) α α 3. Additional Lemmas (L1) v{v(α)=t & v( α)=t} (L2) (L3) there are denumerably-many formulas (L4) Γ α Γ { α} is unverifiable (L5) α α (L6) α α α(α Γ α) & β. Γ β