Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set

Σχετικά έγγραφα
Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit

ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II

2 Composition. Invertible Mappings

ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER

EE512: Error Control Coding

Lecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic

C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions

Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs

Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in

A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation

Example Sheet 3 Solutions

Finite Field Problems: Solutions

Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor

Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5. Luca Alberucci, University of Berne. Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008

Reminders: linear functions

Homomorphism in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Automata

ω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω

Phys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required)

Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees

5. Choice under Uncertainty

DIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANSFORMATION SEMIGROUPS

Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests

Fourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics

4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1)

Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequality for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x, y, z X.

MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS

SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS

On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions.

2. Let H 1 and H 2 be Hilbert spaces and let T : H 1 H 2 be a bounded linear operator. Prove that [T (H 1 )] = N (T ). (6p)

Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3

Matrices and Determinants

Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016

1. Introduction and Preliminaries.

The Simply Typed Lambda Calculus

Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations

derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates

Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2

6.1. Dirac Equation. Hamiltonian. Dirac Eq.

A Conception of Inductive Logic: Example

Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests

The challenges of non-stable predicates

Tridiagonal matrices. Gérard MEURANT. October, 2008

Econ 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1

3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude

Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets

Math221: HW# 1 solutions

Homework 3 Solutions

Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers

Section 8.3 Trigonometric Equations

Homework 8 Model Solution Section

HOMEWORK 4 = G. In order to plot the stress versus the stretch we define a normalized stretch:

Knaster-Reichbach Theorem for 2 κ

Cardinals. Y = n Y n. Define h: X Y by f(x) if x X n X n+1 and n is even h(x) = g

CHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS

12. Radon-Nikodym Theorem

Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II

Strukturalna poprawność argumentu.

Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics

Generating Set of the Complete Semigroups of Binary Relations

On a four-dimensional hyperbolic manifold with finite volume

Solutions to Exercise Sheet 5

Practice Exam 2. Conceptual Questions. 1. State a Basic identity and then verify it. (a) Identity: Solution: One identity is csc(θ) = 1

Solution Series 9. i=1 x i and i=1 x i.

THE SECOND ISOMORPHISM THEOREM ON ORDERED SET UNDER ANTIORDERS. Daniel A. Romano

F A S C I C U L I M A T H E M A T I C I

Completeness Theorem for System AS1

Coefficient Inequalities for a New Subclass of K-uniformly Convex Functions

New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines

forms This gives Remark 1. How to remember the above formulas: Substituting these into the equation we obtain with

Second Order Partial Differential Equations

ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC = DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION #2. h 0 h h 0 h h 0 ( ) g k = g 0 + g 1 + g g 2009 =?

SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES G11LMA Linear Mathematics Examination Solutions

Mean-Variance Analysis

( y) Partial Differential Equations

Partial Differential Equations in Biology The boundary element method. March 26, 2013

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

Iterated trilinear fourier integrals with arbitrary symbols

Μηχανική Μάθηση Hypothesis Testing

Proofs on expressing nested GR(1) properties in GR(1)

SOLUTIONS TO MATH38181 EXTREME VALUES AND FINANCIAL RISK EXAM

SCITECH Volume 13, Issue 2 RESEARCH ORGANISATION Published online: March 29, 2018

CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

THE GENERAL INDUCTIVE ARGUMENT FOR MEASURE ANALYSES WITH ADDITIVE ORDINAL ALGEBRAS

Jesse Maassen and Mark Lundstrom Purdue University November 25, 2013

Right Rear Door. Let's now finish the door hinge saga with the right rear door

de Rham Theorem May 10, 2016

LTL to Buchi. Overview. Buchi Model Checking LTL Translating LTL into Buchi. Ralf Huuck. Buchi Automata. Example

Main source: "Discrete-time systems and computer control" by Α. ΣΚΟΔΡΑΣ ΨΗΦΙΑΚΟΣ ΕΛΕΓΧΟΣ ΔΙΑΛΕΞΗ 4 ΔΙΑΦΑΝΕΙΑ 1

Εγχειρίδια Μαθηµατικών και Χταποδάκι στα Κάρβουνα

= {{D α, D α }, D α }. = [D α, 4iσ µ α α D α µ ] = 4iσ µ α α [Dα, D α ] µ.

Chap. 6 Pushdown Automata

A Two-Sided Laplace Inversion Algorithm with Computable Error Bounds and Its Applications in Financial Engineering

The Probabilistic Method - Probabilistic Techniques. Lecture 7: The Janson Inequality

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 6/5/2006

Partial Trace and Partial Transpose

3.2 Simple Roots and Weyl Group

Solutions to Selected Homework Problems 1.26 Claim: α : S S which is 1-1 but not onto β : S S which is onto but not 1-1. y z = z y y, z S.

Transcript:

Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set May 6, 2008 Abstract A set of first-order formulas, whatever the cardinality of the set of symbols, is equivalent to an independent set. In the following we work with classical (first-order) logic. The Axiom of Choice is assumed 1. Definition 1. Two sets of formulas are equivalent, if any formula of the one set is a consequence of the other and conversely. (Equiv. they have the same models). A set of formulas T is independent, if for all φ T, T \ {φ} φ. (Equiv. there is a model for (T \ {φ}) { φ}). Theorem 2. (Tarski) Every countable set of formulas is equivalent to an independent set. Proof. Let T = {φ 0, φ 1,...} a countable set of formulas. Without loss of generality there are no valid formulas in T. Define inductively ψ 0 = φ 0 and ψ n+1 = least φ m such that ψ 0,..., ψ n φ m. It is not hard to see that T is equivalent to the set {ψ n n ω}. If this set is finite, then T is equivalent to its conjunction. So, assume it is infinite and define ψ 0 = ψ 0 and ψ n+1 = m n ψ m ψ n+1. Since ψ 0,..., ψ n ψ n+1, there is a model M that satisfies ψ 0,..., ψ n and ψ n+1. Then M ψ n+1, while M = ψ m for m < n + 1. For m > n + 1, since M doesn t satisfy the antecedent of ψ m, it trivially satisfies ψ m. Therefore M = ψ m ψ n+1, m n+1 1 This article follows closely the arguments of Reznikoff in [1] (in French), but without being a word-by-word translation. 1

witnessing the fact that {ψ n n ω} is an independent set. Moreover, it is an easy induction to see that the sets {ψ n n ω} and {ψ n n ω} are equivalent, which finishes the proof. Lemma 3. Let C, D be two disjoint sets such that: D C and For all φ C, (C D) \ {φ} φ. Then C D is equivalent to an independent set. Proof. Let f be an injection from D to C. Then {ψ f(ψ) ψ D} (C \ f(d)) is an independent set equivalent to C D. Now, let T be a set of formulas and without loss of generality, there are no valid formulas in T (valid formulas are equivalent to the empty set). For a formula φ T, denote by S(φ) the set of symbols that appear in φ and let S = S(φ). φ T Without loss of generality S is infinite. Otherwise T would be at most countable and equivalent to an independent set by Theorem 2. If S is infinite, then S and T have the same cardinality and let S = T = κ ω. We partition T into sets T α, α < κ as follows: For α = 0, fix a formula φ 0 T and let T 0 = {ψ T S(ψ) S(φ 0)}. For 0 < α < κ, assume that we have defined φ β and T β, for all β < α. By a cardinality argument, S \ S(φ β ). Therefore, there exists a formula φ α that contains a symbols that doesn t appear in any of the φ β, β < α. Define N α = S(φ α) \ S(φ β ), the set of new symbols that appear in φ α. Then N α and define T α = {ψ T S(ψ) S(φ β ) and S(ψ) N α }, β α i.e. T α is the set of formulas in which appears one of the new symbols in N α. Then T = α<κ Tα and the different Tα s are disjoint. Definition 4. If ψ T α and S(ψ) N β, for β α, denote this by β ψ. In particular, for ψ T α, α ψ. If β φ α, with β < α, denote this by β φ α. 2

Observe here that the first definition is for any ψ T, while the second one is only for the φ α s. Also, for any ψ T, there are only finitely many β s with β ψ. Now let ψ α = β φ α φ β φ α, if there exists such a β. Otherwise, let ψ α = φ α. Denote by C the set of all the ψ α s. On the other hand, for φ φ α, all α < κ, let φ = β φ φ β φ. As we noted, there is always such a β. Denote D α = {φ = β φ φ β φ φ T α and x φ α} and let D = α Dα. (D may be empty. We can not exclude this possibility). Lemma 5. Suppose that T satisfies the following condition: ( ) If ψ, φ 1,..., φ n T and S(ψ) n S(φ i), then {φ 1,..., φ n} ψ. Then C and D as defined above, satisfy the conditions of Lemma 3 and T is equivalent to an independent set. Proof. First of all it is clear that C = κ D. It also follows easily by induction on α < κ that the set T β is equivalent to the set ({ψα} Dα). This implies that T is equivalent to C D and it suffices to verify that for ψ α C, ψ α is not a consequence of the other elements of C D: Let ψ α = β φ α φ β φ α. Then the elements of C D different than ψ α are of the form ψ γ = β φ γ φ β φ γ, with γ α, or of the form φ = β φ φ β φ, with φ ψ α, for all α < κ. Consider the implication = m n ψ α. α i α ψ αi Assume that all ψ α1,..., ψ αm are different than ψ α and that α φ αi, for i = 1,..., p, while α φ αi, for i = p + 1,..., m. Similarly, assume that φ 1,..., φ q are such that α φ j, j = 1,..., q, while for φ q+1,..., φ n, α φ j, j = q + 1,..., n. Then p q S(φ α) S(φ αi ) and S(φ α) S(φ j). j=1 φ j j=1 3

Also, by the definition of φ α, S(φ α) β φ α S(φ β ). By ( ), there is a model M in which φ α is false, while all of the φ α1,..., φ αp, φ 1,..., φ q and {φ β β φ α} are true. Then ψ α is false in M, while ψ α1,..., ψ αp, φ 1,..., φ q are true. In addition, for i = p + 1,..., m, φ α is among the φ γ s in the conjunction of ψ αi = γ φ αi φ γ φ αi and the same is true for the conjunction of φ j = γ φ j φ γ φ j, for j = q + 1,..., n. Since φ α is false in M, then ψ αp+1,..., ψ αm, φ q+1,..., φ n are trivially true. This proves that there is a model M that satisfies all the ψ α1,..., ψ αm, φ 1,..., φ n, but which does not satisfy ψ α. In other words, ψ α can not be a consequence of other elements of C D. What remains is to prove that T can be taken to satisfy ( ). We use Craig s Interpolation Theorem which me mention without proof. Theorem 6. (Craig) If ψ = φ, then there is a formula τ such that ψ = τ and τ = φ, and the non-logical symbols of τ appears in both ψ and φ. τ is called the interpolant between ψ and φ. Lemma 7. Every set of non-valid formulas T is equivalent to a set of formulas that satisfies ( ). Proof. Let and E 1 = {φ T = φ and S(φ) = 1} E n = {φ T = φ, m<n E m φ and S(φ) = n}. It is immediate that T = ne n is equivalent to T. Let ψ, φ 1,..., φ n T such that S(ψ) n S(φi). If we assume that {φ 1,..., φ n} = ψ, then by Craig s Interpolation Theorem, there is a τ such that {φ 1,..., φ n} = τ and τ = ψ, and S(τ) S(ψ) ( n S(φ i)). By the assumption on ψ, it must be S(τ) S(ψ) and ψ T would be a consequence of τ with T = τ and S(τ) < S(ψ), contradicting the definition of T. Therefore, T satisfies ( ). Putting all the previous lemmas together we conclude Theorem 8. (Reznikoff) Every set of formulas is equivalent to an independent set. 4

References [1] M. I. Reznikoff, Tout ensemble de formules de la logique classique est equivalent á un ensemble independant, C.R. Acad. Sc. Paris, 260, 2385-2388 (1965). 5