Thus X is nonempty by supposition. By (i), let x be a minimal element of X. Then let

Μέγεθος: px
Εμφάνιση ξεκινά από τη σελίδα:

Download "Thus X is nonempty by supposition. By (i), let x be a minimal element of X. Then let"

Transcript

1 4. Ordinals July 26, 2011 In this chapter we introduce the ordinals, prove a general recursion theorem, and develop some elementary ordinal arithmetic. A set A is transitive iff x A y x(y A); in other words, iff every element of A is a subset of A. This is a very important notion in the foundations of set theory, and it is essential in our definition of ordinals. An ordinal number, or simply an ordinal, is a transitive set of transitive sets. We use the first few Greek letters to denote ordinals. Note that for any set x, x / x by the foundation axiom. If α, β, γ are ordinals and α β γ, then α γ since γ is transitive. These two facts justify writing α < β instead of α β when α and β are ordinals. This helps the intuition in thinking of the ordinals as kinds of numbers. We also define α β iff α < β or α = β. It is useful in what follows to introduce some of the terminology of ordered sets and prove a lemma before proceeding with our development of ordinals. A poset or partially ordered set is an ordered pair (A, <) such that < is a binary relation contained in A A, it is irreflexive (there is no x such that x < x), and it is transitive (x < y and y < z imply that x < y). Frequently we will simply write A for the poset, with the relation < understood. Then we define x y iff x < y or x = y. Given a subset X of A, a minimal element of X is an element x X such that there is no y X such that y < x. Elements x, y of A are comparable iff x < y, y < x, or x = y. A poset is a simple ordered set or linearly ordered set iff any two of its elements are comparable. Lemma 4.1. Suppose that (A, <) is a poset satisfying the following conditions: (i) Any nonempty subset of A has a minimal element. (ii) If x, y A, x y, and for all z A, z < y implies that z < x, then there is a z < x such that z y. Then (A, <) is linearly ordered. Proof. Suppose not; so there are incomparable elements in A. Let X = {x A : there is a b A which is not comparable with x}. Thus X is nonempty by supposition. By (i), let x be a minimal element of X. Then let Y = {y A : x and y are not comparable}. Hence Y is nonempty by the fact that x X. By (i), let y be a minimal element of Y. Suppose that z < y. Then z / Y, and so x and z are comparable. If x z, then x < y, contradicting the fact that y Y. It follows that z < x. Thus we have shown that z < y implies that z < x. Hence by (ii) there is a z < x such that z y. By the choice of x we thus have that z / X, and so in particular z is comparable with y. So y z, hence y < x, contradiction. This lemma will be used shortly. Now we return to the discussion of ordinals; The following properties of ordinals are easy to prove: 14

2 is an ordinal. Because of this fact, the empty set is a number; it will turn out to be the first nonnegative integer, and the first cardinal number. For this reason, we will use 0 and interchangably, trying to use 0 when numbers are involved, and when they are not. If α is an ordinal, then so is α {α}. We denote α {α} by α + 1. After introducing addition of ordinals, it will turn out that α + 1 = α + 1 for every ordinal α, so that the prime can be dropped. This ordinal α + 1 is the successor of α. We define 1 = 0 + 1, 2 = 1 + 1, etc. (up through 9; no further since we do not want to try to justify decimal notation). If A is a set of ordinals, then A is an ordinal. We sometimes write sup(a) for A. In fact, A is the least ordinal each member of A. We prove this shortly. Every member of an ordinal is an ordinal. There does not exist a set which has every ordinal as a member. In fact, suppose to the contrary that A is such a set. Let B = {x A : x is an ordinal}. Then B is a set of transitive sets and B itself is transitive. Hence B is an ordinal. So B A, and even B B, contradicting the foundation axiom. This fact is what happens in our axiomatic framework to the Burali-Forti paradox. Now we can prove that the ordinals are simply ordered. More precisely, any set of ordinals is linearly ordered. Theorem 4.2. If α and β are ordinals, then α = β, α β, or β α. Proof. Let α and β be ordinals. Let A = (α+ 1) (β + 1). So (A, <) is a poset. We are going to verify the conditions of Lemma 4.1. Suppose that X is a nonempty subset of A. By the regularity axiom, choose γ X such that γ X =. Thus for any δ < γ we have δ / X, since < is the same as among ordinals. So γ is a minimal element of X, as desired in 4.1(i). For 4.1(ii), suppose that δ, ε A, δ ε, and θ < δ implies that θ < ε. Then δ ε since < is. Since δ ε, choose τ ε\δ. Thus τ < ε but τ δ, as desired in 4.1(ii). So we apply 4.1 and infer that (A, <) is a linear order. Since α, β A, they are comparable. We give some more simple properties of ordinals. For some of them, it is convenient to use Theorem 4.2 to check them. α β iff α β. α < β iff α β. α < β iff α + 1 β. These facts can be used to check the implicit statement above that A is the least upper bound of A, for any set A of ordinals. In fact, if α A, then α A, so α A. If α β for all α A, then α β for each α A, hence A β, hence A β. 15

3 The following theorem is also fundamental. Theorem 4.3. If Γ is a nonempty set of ordinals, then Γ is an ordinal, Γ Γ, and Γ α for every α Γ. Proof. The members of Γ are clearly ordinals, so for the first statement it suffices to show that Γ is transitive. Suppose that α β Γ; and suppose that γ Γ. Then β γ, and hence α γ since γ is transitive. This argument shows that α Γ. Since α is arbitrary, it follows that Γ is transitive, and hence is an ordinal. For every α Γ we have Γ α, and hence Γ α by a previous fact. Suppose that Γ / Γ. For any α Γ we have Γ α, hence Γ α, hence Γ < α since α Γ but we are assuming that Γ / Γ. But this means that α Γ[ Γ α]. So Γ Γ, contradiction. A linearly ordered set (A, <) is a well-ordered set iff every nonempty subset X of A has a least element, i.e., an element x X such that x y for all y X. So 4.3 says that for any ordinal α, (α, <) is a well-ordered set. Later in this chapter we will show that every well-ordered set is isomorphic to an ordinal; this is the fundamental theorem about ordinals. Ordinals are divided into three classes as follows. First there is 0, the empty set. An ordinal α is a successor ordinal if α = β + 1 for some β. Finally, α is a limit ordinal if it is nonzero and is not a successor ordinal. Thus 1, 2, etc. are successor ordinals. To prove the existence of limit ordinals, we need the infinity axiom. Let x be as in the statement of the infinity axiom. Thus 0 x, and y {y} x for all y x. We define ω = {z x : 0 z and y {y} z for all y z}. This definition does not depend on the choice of x. The members of ω are natural numbers, and the usual induction principle is built into the definition. It is easy to check that ω is an ordinal, and in fact is the least limit ordinal. Proposition 4.4. The following conditions are equivalent: (i) α is a limit ordinal; (ii) α 0, and for every β < α there is a γ such that β < γ < α. (iii) α = α 0. Proof. (i) (ii): suppose that α is a limit ordinal. So α 0, by definition. Suppose that β < α. Then β + 1 < α, since α is not a successor ordinal. Thus γ = β + 1 works as indicated. (ii) (iii): if β α, choose γ α such that β γ. Then β α since α is an ordinal. If β α, choose γ with β < γ < α. Thus β α. This proves that α = α, and α 0 is given. (iii) (i): suppose that α = β + 1. Then β α = α, so choose γ α such that β γ. Thus β < γ β, so β < β, contradiction. Also note that if α = β + 1, then α = β. 16

4 Classes and sets Although expressions like {x : x = x} and {α : α is an ordinal} are natural, they cannot be put into the framework of our logic for set theory. These collections are too big. It is intuitively indispensible to continue using such expressions. One should understand that when this is done, there is a rigorous way of reformulating what is said. These big collections are called classes; their rigorous counterparts are simply formulas of our set theoretic language. We can also talk about class functions, class relations, the domain of class functions, etc. Most of the notions that we have introduced so far in our sketch of a development from the axioms have class counterparts. In particular, we have the important classes V, the class of all sets, and On, the class of all ordinals. They correspond to the formulas x = x and α is an ordinal. We attempt to use bold face letters for classes; in some cases the classes in question are actually sets. A class which is not a set is called a proper class. Sequences of ordinals We say that F is an ordinal class function iff F is a class function whose domain is an ordinal, or the whole class On, and whose range is contained in On. If its domain is an ordinal, then of course it is a set. We consider three properties of an ordinal class function F with domain A: F is strictly increasing iff for any ordinals α, β A, if α < β then F(α) < F(β). F is continuous iff for every limit ordinal α A, F(α) = β<α F(β). F is normal iff it is continuous and strictly increasing. Proposition 4.5. If F is a strictly increasing ordinal class function with domain A, then α F(α) for every ordinal α A. Proof. Suppose not, and let α be the least member of A such that F(α) < α. Then F(F(α)) < F(α), so that F(α) is an ordinal β smaller than α such that F(β) < β, contradiction. Proposition 4.6. If F is a continuous ordinal class function with domain A, and F(α) < F(α + 1) for every ordinal α such that α + 1 A, then F is strictly increasing. Proof. Fix an ordinal γ A, and suppose that there is an ordinal δ A with γ < δ and F(δ) F(γ); we want to get a contradiction. Take the least such δ. Case 1. δ = θ + 1 for some θ. Thus γ θ. If γ = θ, then F(γ) < F(δ) by the hypothesis of the proposition, contradicting our supposition. Hence γ < θ. Hence F(γ) < F(θ) by the minimality of δ, and F(θ) < F(δ) by the assumption of the proposition, so F(γ) < F(δ), contradiction. Case 2. δ is a limit ordinal. Then there is a θ < δ with γ < θ, and so by the minimality of δ we have F(γ) < F(θ) ε<δf(ε) = F(δ), contradiction. 17

5 Proposition 4.7. Suppose that F is a normal ordinal class function with domain A, and ξ A is a limit ordinal. Then F(ξ) is a limit ordinal too. Proof. Suppose that γ < F(ξ). Thus γ η<ξ F(η), so there is a η < ξ such that γ < F(η). Now F(η) < F(ξ). Hence F(ξ) is a limit ordinal. Proposition 4.8. Suppose that F and G are normal ordinal class functions, with domains A, B respectively, and the range of F is contained in B. Then also G F is also normal. Proof. Clearly G F is strictly increasing. Now suppose that ξ A is a limit ordinal. Then F(ξ) is a limit ordinal by 4.7. Suppose that ρ < ξ. Then F(ρ) < F(ξ), so G(F(ρ)) η<f(ξ) G(η) = G(F(ξ)). Thus ( ) G(F(ρ)) G(F(ξ)). ρ<ξ Now if η < F(ξ), then by the continuity of F, η < ρ<ξ F(ρ), and hence there is a ρ < ξ such that η < F(ρ); so G(η) < G(F(ρ)). So for any η < F(ξ) we have G(η) G(F(ρ)). Hence ρ<ξ G(F(ξ)) = η<f(ξ)g(η) G(F(ρ)); ρ<ξ together with ( ) this gives the continuity of G F. Transfinite induction and recursion The following theorem generalizes the familiar principle of complete induction for natural numbers. Theorem 4.9. (Complete transfinite induction) Suppose that A is an ordinal, or is On, B A, and ( ) For all β A, if γ B for all γ < β, then β B. Then B = A. Proof. Suppose not. Then A\B is nonempty, and we let β be the least element of it. Thus γ B for all γ < β, so by the assumption ( ), also β B, contradiction. There is also an ordinary principle of transfinite induction, in which the argument goes step-by-step, except for limit ordinals, where we have to do complete induction again. This generalizes the usual induction principle for ω, which as we stated is really built in to the definition of ω. Theorem (Ordinary transfinite induction) Suppose that A is an ordinal or is On, B A, and the following three conditions hold: (i) If 0 A, then 0 B. 18

6 (ii) If β + 1 A and β B, then β + 1 B. (iii) If β A is a limit ordinal, and if γ B for all γ < β, then β B. Under these assumptions, B = A. Proof. Again, suppose not, and let β be the least element of A\B. Then β 0 by (i). Suppose that β is a successor ordinal γ + 1. Then γ B, and (ii) is contradicted. Finally, if β is a limit ordinal, then (iii) is contradicted. We need the following lemma before formulating and proving the transfinite recursion principle. Lemma Suppose that F is a ordinal class function with domain On, and α is a particular ordinal. Then there is a unique function f with domain α such that f(ξ) = F(ξ) for every ξ < α. Note that f here is a set. More formally, Lemma 4.11 looks like this: For any formula ϕ(x, y), we can prove the following in ZFC: [ x[ yϕ(x, y) x is an ordinal] and x[x is an ordinal!yϕ(x, y)]] x[x is an ordinal!f[f is a function and dmn(f) = x and y z[ y, z f ϕ(y, z)]]. Proof. By the axiom of replacement, the set A def = {x : F(ξ) = x for some ξ < α} exists. Let f = {(ξ, η) α A : F(ξ) = η}. Clearly f is as desired, and it is unique. The function f asserted to exist in this lemma will be denoted by F α. Theorem (Class version of the transfinite recursion principle) Suppose that G is a class function with domain the class of all (ordinary) functions. Then there is a unique class function F with domain On such that for every ordinal α we have F(α) = G(F α). Before beginning the proof it may clarify things to formulate the theorem more precisely. The existence part of the theorem says that for any formula ϕ(x, y) there is another formula ψ(x, y) such that it is provable that if ϕ(x, y) represents a function G defined for all (ordinary) functions, then ψ(x, y) represents a function F as indicated. The uniqueness part says that if ψ (x, y) is any other formula that works as indicated, then one can prove x y[ψ(x, y) ψ (x, y)]. Proof of We consider the following condition: 19

7 (*) f is a function with domain α, and for every ξ < α we have f(ξ) = G(f ξ). First we show (1) If f, α satisfy (*) and g, β satisfy (*) and α β, then f = g α. To prove this, we prove by transfinite induction on ξ that if ξ < α then f(ξ) = g(ξ). Suppose that this is true for all η < ξ, where ξ < α. Then f ξ = g ξ, so f(ξ) = G(f ξ) = G(g ξ) = g(ξ), finishing the inductive proof. (2) For every ordinal α there is a function f such that (*) holds. We prove this by transfinite induction. It trivially holds for α = 0. Assume that it holds for α, and f is a function such that (*) holds for α. Let h = f {(α,g(f))}. Clearly (*) holds for h and α + 1. Finally, suppose that α is a limit ordinal, and (*) holds for every β < α. By (1), for each β < α there is a unique f satisfying (1); we denote it by f β (the replacement axiom is being used). Let g = β<α f β. Then g is a function by (1), and its domain is clearly α. (3) For any β < α we have f β = g β, and g(β) = G(g β). In fact, the first condition is clear. For the second, g(β) = f β+ 1(β) = G(f β+ 1 β) = G(g β). So, (3) holds; hence (*) holds for α. This finishes the inductive proof of (2). Now for any ordinal α we let F(α) = f(α), where f is chosen so that (*) holds for α + 1 and f. This definition is unambiguous by (1). Also by (1), we have F α = f α. Hence F(α) = f(α) = G(f α) = G(F α). This finishes the proof of existence. For uniqueness, suppose that H also satisfies the conditions of the theorem. We prove that F(α) = H(α) for every ordinal α by induction. Suppose that this is true for all β < α. Then F α = H α, and hence F(α) = G(F α) = G(H α) = H(α). This finishes the inductive proof. More on well-ordered sets Now we prove some more facts about well-ordered sets, leading up to the fundamental fact that each such set is similar to an ordinal, in a certain well-defined sense. Let (A, <) be a well-ordered set. An initial segment of A under < is a subset B of A such that a A b B(a < b a B). An initial segment is proper iff it is different from A itself. If a A, then the initial segment determined by a under < is the set {b A : b < a}. Clearly this really is an initial segment of A under <. Then ({b A : b < a}, <) is a well-ordered set which we denote by (A a, <). Note here the slight sloppiness: we really should talk about {(b, c) : b, c < a and b < c} instead of < here. Sometimes we omit the phrase under < when talking about initial segments, if the < involved is clear. 20

8 Proposition A proper initial segment of a well-ordered set is determined by one of its elements. Proof. Suppose that B is a proper initial segment of the well-ordered set (A, <). Let a be the least element of A\B. We claim that B is determined by a. For, if b B, then it cannot happen that a b, since this would imply that a B; so b < a. And if b < a, then b B by the minimality of a. Suppose that (A, <) and (B, ) are linearly ordered sets. A function f : A B is strictly increasing iff a 0, a 1 A[a 0 < a 1 f(a 0 ) f(a 1 )]. Note that such a function is necessarily one-one. The following easy fact will be useful. Proposition If (A, <) and (B, ) are linearly ordered sets and f : A B is strictly increasing, then a 0, a 1 A[a 0 < a 1 f(a 0 ) f(a 1 )]. Proof. The direction is given by the definition. Now suppose that it is not true that a 0 < a 1. Then a 1 a 0, so f(a 1 ) f(a 0 ). So f(a 0 ) < f(a 1 ) is not true. We already know the following fact for ordinals, but now we need it for arbitrary wellordered sets. Proposition If (A, <) is a well-ordered set and f : A A is strictly increasing, then x f(x) for all x A. Proof. Suppose not. Then then set B def = {x A : f(x) < x} is nonempty. Let b be the least element of B. Thus f(b) < b. Hence by the choice of b, we have f(b) f(f(b)). Hence by 4.14, b f(b), contradiction. Proposition If (A, <) is a well-ordered set, then there does not exist a strictly increasing function from A onto a proper initial segment of A. Proof. Suppose that f is such a function. By 4.13, the proper initial segment is determined by some element x. By 4.15, x f(x), contradicting the assumption that f maps into the given proper initial segment. Let (A, <) and (B, ) be linearly ordered sets. We say that they are similar if there is a a strictly increasing function f mapping A onto B. We call f a similarity mapping, or an order-isomorphism. Proposition If (A, <) and (B, ) are similar well-ordered sets, then there is a unique strictly increasing function f mapping A onto B. Proof. The existence of f follows from the definition. Suppose that both f and g are strictly increasing functions mapping A onto B. Then f 1 g is a strictly increasing function from A into A, so by 4.15 we get x (f 1 g)(x) for every x A; so f(x) g(x) for every x A. Similarly, g(x) f(x) for every x A, so f = g. Corollary If α β, then α and β are not similar. Proof. Suppose to the contrary that f is a similarity mapping from α onto β, with β < α. This contradicts

9 Proposition Suppose that f is a one-one function mapping an ordinal α onto a set X. Define R = {(f(β), f(γ)) : β < γ < α}. Then (X, R) is a well-ordered set. Proof. Completely straightforward. The following theorem is fundamental. The proof is also of general interest; it can be followed in outline form in many other situations. Theorem Every well-ordered set is similar to an ordinal. Proof. Let (A, ) be a well-ordered set. We may assume that A. We define a class function G whose domain is the class of all functions. For any function h, { G(h) = -least element of A\rng(h) if this set is nonempty, A otherwise. Now by the recursion theorem let F be a ordinal class function with domain On such that F(β) = G(F β) for each ordinal β. (1) If β < γ and F(β) = A, then F(γ) = A. For, A\rng(F γ) A\rng(F β), so (1) is clear. (2) if β < γ α and F(γ) A, then F(β) A and F(β) F(γ). The first assertion follows from (1). For the second assertion, note that A\rng(F γ) A\rng(F β), hence F(γ) A\rng(F β), so F(β) F(γ) by definition. Also F(β) rng(f γ), and F(γ) / rng(f γ), so F(β) F(γ), as desired in (2). By (2), F(γ) cannot be A for all γ, because then F would be a one-one function mapping On into A, contradicting the replacement axiom. Choose γ minimum such that F(γ) = A. (Note that F(0) A, since A is nonempty and so has a least element.) By (2), F γ is one-one and maps onto A. So γ is similar to A. By 4.17 and 4.20, every well-ordered set (A, ) is similar to a unique ordinal. This ordinal is called the order type of (A, ), and is denoted by o.t.(a, ). Ordinal addition We define ordinal addition by transfinite recursion: α + 0 = α; α + (β + 1) = (α + β) + 1; α + β = (α + γ) for β limit. γ<β Proposition α + 1 = α + 1 for any ordinal α. Proof. α + 1 = α + (0 + 1) = (α + 0) + 1 = α + 1. Now we can stop using the notation α

10 We state the simplest properties of ordinal addition in the following theorem, but only prove a couple of representative parts of it. Weakly increasing means that a < b implies that F(a) F(b). An ordinal α is infinite iff ω α. Theorem (i) If m, n ω, then m + n ω. (ii) For any ordinal α, the class function F which takes each ordinal β to α + β is a normal function. (iii) For any ordinal β, the class function F which takes each ordinal α to α + β is continuous and weakly increasing. (iv) α + (β + γ) = (α + β) + γ. (v) β α + β. (vi) 0 + α = α. (vii) α β iff there is a δ such that α + δ = β. (viii) α < β iff there is a δ > 0 such that α + δ = β. (ix) α is infinite iff 1 + α = α. Proof. (i) is easily proved by ordinary induction on n; this is the induction given by the very definition of ω. We prove (iv) by fixing α and β and proceeding by induction on γ. The case γ = 0 is obvious. Assume that α + (β + γ) = (α + β) + γ. Then α + (β + (γ + 1)) = α + ((β + γ) + 1) = (α + (β + γ)) + 1 = ((α + β) + γ) + 1 = (α + β) + (γ + 1). Finally, suppose that γ is a limit ordinal and we know our result for all δ < γ. Let F,G,H be the ordinal class functions such that, for any ordinal δ, F(δ) = α + δ; G(δ) = (α + β) + δ; H(δ) = β + δ. Thus according to (i), all three of these functions are normal. Hence, using 4.8, α + (β + γ) = F(H(γ)) = δ<γ F(H(δ)) = δ<γ(α + (β + δ)) = δ<γ((α + β) + δ = G(δ) δ<γ = G(γ) = (α + β) + γ. 23

11 Note, with reference to 4.22(i), that addition, restricted to natural numbers, is ordinary addition familiar to the reader. Also note that ordinal addition is not commutative in general. For example, ω = 1 + ω ω + 1. There is an equivalent definition of ordinal addition which is more intuitive and direct: Theorem For any ordinals α, β let α β = (α {0}) (β {1}). We define a relation on α β as follows. For any x, y α β, x y iff one of the following three conditions holds: (i) There are ξ, η < α such that x = (ξ, 0), y = (η, 0), and ξ < η. (ii) There are ξ, η < β such that x = (ξ, 1), y = (η, 1), and ξ < η. (ii) There are ξ < α and η < β such that x = (ξ, 0) and y = (η, 1). Then (α β, ) is a well-order which is order-isomorphic to α + β. A simple picture helps to explain the construction in this theorem: α α β β Thus a copy of β is put to the right of a copy of α. The purpose of the definition of α β is to make the copies of α and β disjoint. Proof. Clearly is a well-order. We show by transfinite induction on β, with α fixed, that (α β, ) is order isomorphic to α + β. For β = 0 we have α + β = α + 0 = α, while α β = α 0 = α {0}. Clearly ξ (ξ, 0) defines an order-isomorphism from α onto (α {0}, ). So our result holds for β = 0. Assume it for β, and suppose that f is an order-isomorphism from α + β onto (α β, ). Now the last element of α (β + 1) is (β, 1), and the last element of α + (β + 1) is α + β, so the function f {(α + β, (β, 1))} is an order-isomorphism from α + (β + 1) onto α (β + 1). Now assume that β is a limit ordinal, and for each γ < β, the ordinal α + γ is isomorphic to α γ. For each such γ let f γ be the unique isomorphism from α + γ onto α γ. Note that if γ < δ < β, then f δ γ is an isomorphism from α +γ onto α γ; hence f δ γ = f γ. It follows that is an isomorphism from α + β onto α β, finishing the inductive proof. γ<β f γ 24

12 Ordinal multiplication We define ordinal multiplication by recursion: α 0 = 0; α (β + 1) = α β + α; α β = (α γ) for β limit. γ<β Here are some basic properties of ordinal multiplication: Theorem (i) If m, n ω, then m n ω. (ii) If α 0, then α β < α (β + 1); (iii) If α 0, then the class function assigning to each ordinal β the product α β is normal. (iv) 0 α = 0; (v) If α, β 0, then α β 0; (vi) α (β + γ) = (α β) + (α γ); (vii) α (β γ) = (α β) γ; (viii) If α 0, then β α β; (ix) If α < β then α γ β γ; (x) α 1 = 1 α = α. (xi) α 2 = α + α. Proof. We only give the proof of (vi). Fix α and β. By (iv) we may assume that α 0; we then proceed by induction on γ. We define some ordinal class functions F,F,G: for any γ, F(γ) = β + γ; F (γ) = α β + γ; G(γ) = α γ. These are normal functions. First of all, α (β + 0) = α β = (α β) + 0 = (α β) + (α 0), so (v) holds for γ = 0. Now assume that (v) holds for γ. Then α (β + (γ + 1)) = α ((β + γ) + 1) = α (β + γ) + α = (α β) + (α γ) + α = (α β) + (α (γ + 1)), as desired. 25

13 Finally, suppose that δ is a limit ordinal and we know (v) for all γ < δ. Then α (β + δ) = G(F(δ)) = (G F)(δ) = γ<δ(g F)(γ) = γ<δ(α (β + γ)) = γ<δ((α β) + (α γ)) = γ<δ F (G(γ)) as desired. This completes the proof of (v). = γ<δ(f G)(γ) = (F G)(δ) = (α β) + (α δ), The following is a generalization of the division algorithm for natural numbers. That algorithm is very useful for the arithmetic of natural numbers, and the ordinal version is a basic result for more advanced arithmetic of ordinals. Theorem (Division algorithm) Suppose that α and β are ordinals, with β 0. Then there are unique ordinals ξ, η such that α = β ξ + η with η < β. Proof. First we prove the existence. Note that α < α + 1 β (α + 1). Thus there is an ordinal number ρ such that α < β ρ; take the least such ρ. Obviously ρ 0. If ρ is a limit ordinal, then because β ρ = σ<ρ (β σ), it follows that there is a σ < ρ such that α < β σ, contradicting the minimality of ρ. Thus ρ is a successor ordinal ξ + 1. By the definition of ρ we have β ξ α. Hence there is an ordinal η such that β ξ + η = α. We claim that η < β. Otherwise, α = β ξ + η β ξ + β = β (ξ + 1) = β ρ, contradicting the definition of ρ. This finishes the proof of existence. For uniqueness, suppose that also α = β ξ + η with η < β. Suppose that ξ ξ. By symmetry, say ξ < ξ. Then α = β ξ + η < β ξ + β = β (ξ + 1) β ξ β ξ + η = α, contradiction. Hence ξ = ξ. Hence also η = η. We now give, similarly to the case of ordinal addition, an equivalent definition of ordinal multiplication which is somewhat more intuitive than the definition above. Given ordinals α, β, we define the following relation on α β: (ξ, η) (ξ, η ) iff ((ξ, η) and (ξ, η ) are in α β and: η < η, or (η = η and ξ < ξ ). 26

14 We may say that this is the anti-dictionary or anti-lexicographic order. Theorem For any two ordinals α, β, the set α β under the anti-lexicographic order is a well-ordering which is isomorphic to α β. Proof. We may assume that α 0. It is straightforward to check that is a well-order. Now we define, for any (ξ, η) α β, f(ξ, η) = α η + ξ. We claim that f is the desired order-isomorphism from α β onto α β. If (ξ, η) α β, then f(ξ, η) = α η + ξ < α η + α = α (η + 1) α β. Thus f maps into α β. To show that f is one-one, suppose that (ξ, η), (ξ, η ) α β and f(ξ, η) = f(ξ, η ). Then by Theorem 4.25, (ξ, η) = (ξ, η ). So f is one-one. To show that f maps onto α β, let γ < α β. Choose ξ and η so that γ = α η + ξ with ξ < α. Now η < β, as otherwise γ = α η + ξ α η α β. It follows that f(ξ, η) = (α η) + ξ = γ. so f is onto. Finally, we show that the order is preserved. Suppose that (ξ, η) (ξ, η ). Then one of these cases holds: Case 1. η < η. Then f(ξ, η) = α η + ξ < α η + α = α (η + 1) α η α η + ξ = f(ξ, η ), as desired. Case 4. η = η and ξ < ξ. Then f(ξ, η) < f(ξ, η ). Now it follows that f is the desired isomorphism. Ordinal exponentiaton We define exponentiation of ordinals by recursion: α 0 = 1; α β+1 = α β α; α β = α γ γ<β for β limit. Now we give the simplest properties of exponentiation. Theorem (i) If m, n ω, then m n ω. (ii) 0 0 = 1; 27

15 (iii) 0 β+1 = 0; (iv) 0 β = 1 for β a limit ordinal; (v) 1 β = 1; (vi) If α 0, then α β 0; (vii) If α > 1 then α β < α β+1 ; (viii) If α > 1, then the ordinal class function assigning to each ordinal β the value α β is normal; (ix) If α > 1, then β α β ; (x) If 0 < α < β, then α γ β γ ; (xi) For α 0, α β+γ = α β α γ ; (xii) For α 0, (α β ) γ = α β γ. The following is another kind of division algorithm for ordinals. Theorem (Extended division algorithm) Let α and β be ordinals, with α 0 and 1 < β. Then there exist unique ordinals γ, δ, ε such that the following conditions hold: (i) α = β γ δ + ε. (ii) γ α. (iii) 0 < δ < β, (iv) ε < β γ. Proof. We have α < α + 1 β α+1 ; so there is an ordinal ϕ such that α < β ϕ. We take the least such ϕ. Clearly ϕ is a successor ordinal γ + 1. So we have β γ α < β γ+1. Now β γ 0, since β > 1. Hence by the division algorithm there are ordinals δ, ε such that α = β γ δ + ε, with ε < β γ. Now δ < β; for if β δ, then α = β γ δ + ε β γ β = β γ+1 > α, contradiction. We have δ 0, as otherwise α = ε < β γ, contradiction.. Also, γ α, since α = β γ δ + ε β γ γ. This proves the existence of γ, δ, ε as called for in the theorem. Suppose that γ, δ, ε also satisfy the indicated conditions; thus (1) α = β γ δ + ε, (2) γ α, (3) 0 < δ < β, (4) ε < β γ. Suppose that γ γ ; by symmetry, say that γ < γ. Then α = β γ δ + ε < β γ δ + β γ = β γ (δ + 1) β γ β = β γ+1 β γ α, contradiction. Hence γ = γ. Hence by the ordinary division algorithm we also have δ = δ and ε = ε. 28

16 We can obtain an interesting normal form for ordinals by re-applying 4.28 to the remainder ε over and over again. That is the purpose of the following definitions and results. This generalizes the ordinary decimal and binary systems of notation, by taking β = 10 or β = 2 and restricting to natural numbers. For infinite ordinals it is useful to take β = ω; this gives the Cantor normal form. To abbreviate some long expressions, we let N(β, m, γ, δ) stand for the following statement: β is an ordinal > 1, m is a positive integer, γ and δ are sequences of ordinals each of length m, and: (1) γ(0) > γ(1) > > γ(m 1); (2) 0 < δ(i) < β for each i < m. If N(β, m, γ, δ), then we define k(β, m, γ, δ) = β γ(0) δ(0) + β γ(1) δ(1) + + β γ(m 1) δ(m 1). Lemma Assume that N(β, m, γ, δ) and N(β, n, γ, δ ). Then (i) k(β, m, γ, δ) γ(0). (ii) k(β, m, γ, δ) < β γ(0) (δ(0) + 1) β γ(0)+1. (iii) If γ(0) γ (0), then k(β, m, γ, δ) < k(β, n, γ, δ ) iff γ(0) < γ (0). (iv) If γ(0) = γ (0) and δ(0) δ (0), then k(β, m, γ, δ) < k(β, n, γ, δ ) iff δ(0) < δ (0). (v) If γ(j) = γ (j) and δ(j) = δ (j) for all j < i, while γ(i) γ (i), then k(β, m, γ, δ) < k(β, n, γ, δ ) iff γ(i) < γ (i). (vi) If γ(j) = γ (j) and δ(j) = δ (j) for all j < i, while γ(i) = γ (i) and δ(i) δ (i), then k(β, m, γ, δ) < k(β, n, γ, δ ) iff δ(i) < δ (i). (vii) If γ γ, δ δ, and m < n, then k(β, m, γ, δ) < k(β, n, γ, δ ) Proof. (i): k(β, m, γ, δ) β γ(0) γ(0). (ii): We prove this by induction on m. It is clear for m = 1. Now assume that it holds for m 1, where m > 1. Then β γ(0) δ(0) + β γ(1) δ(1) + + β γ(m 1) δ(m 1) < β γ(0) δ(0) + β γ(1)+1 β γ(0) δ(0) + β γ(0) = β γ(0) (δ(0) + 1) β γ(0) β = β γ(0)+1, finishing the inductive proof. For (iii), assume the hypothesis, and suppose that γ(0) < γ (0). Then k(β, m, γ, δ) < β γ(0) (δ(0) + 1) β γ(0)+1 29 β γ (0) by (ii) k(β, n, γ, δ ) by (i).

17 By symmetry (iii) now follows. For (iv), assume the hypothesis, and suppose that δ(0) < δ (0). Then k(β, m, γ, δ) < β γ(0) (δ(0) + 1) β γ (0) (δ(0) + 1) by (ii) β γ (0) δ (0) k(β, n, γ, δ ) By symmetry (iv) now follows. (v) is clear from (iii), by deleting the first i summands of the sums. (vi) is clear from (iv), by deleting the first i summands of the sums. (vii) is clear. Theorem Let α and β be ordinals, with α 0 and 1 < β. Then there exist a unique m ω and finite sequences γ(i) : i < m and δ(i) : i < m of ordinals such that the following conditions hold: (i) α = β γ(0) δ(0) + β γ(1) δ(1) + + β γ(m 1) δ(m 1). (ii) α γ(0) > γ(1) > > γ(m 1). (iii) 0 < δ(i) < β for each i < m. Proof. For the existence, with β > 1 fixed we proceed by induction on α. Assume that the theorem holds for every α < α such that α 0, and suppose that α 0. By Theorem 4.28, let ϕ, ψ, θ be such that (1) α = β ϕ ψ + θ, (2) ϕ α, (3) 0 < ψ < β, (4) θ < β ϕ. If θ = 0, then we can take our sequences to be γ(0) and δ(0), with γ(0) = ϕ and δ(0) = ψ. Now assume that θ > 0. Then θ < β ϕ β ϕ ψ + θ = α; so θ < α. Hence by the inductive assumption we can write with θ = β γ(0) δ(0) + β γ(1) δ(1) + + β γ(m 1) δ(m 1) (5) θ γ(0) > γ(1) > > γ(m 1). (6) 0 < δ(i) < β for each i < m. Then our desired sequences for α are ϕ, γ(0), γ(1),..., γ(m 1) and ψ, δ(0), δ(1),..., δ(m 1). 30

18 To prove this, we just need to show that ϕ > γ(0). If ϕ γ(0), then β ϕ β γ(0) θ, contradiction. This finishes the existence part of the proof. For the uniqueness, we use the notation introduced above, and proceed by induction on α. Suppose the uniqueness statement holds for all nonzero α < α, and now we have N(β, m, γ, δ), N(β, n, γ, δ ), and α = k(β, m, γ, δ) = k(β, n, γ, δ ). We suppose that the uniqueness fails. Say m n. Then there is an i < m such that γ(i) γ (i) or δ(i) δ (i); we take the least such i. Then we have a contradiction of Lemma Now we give an equivalent definition of exponentiation similar to those given above for addition and multiplication. A set X is finite iff there is a bijection from some natural number m onto X. Theorem Suppose that α and β are ordinals, with β 0. We define α β w = {f α β : {ξ < α : f(ξ) 0} is finite}. For f, g α β w we write f g iff f g and f(ξ) < g(ξ) for the greatest ξ < α for which f(ξ) g(ξ). Then ( α β w, ) is a well-order which is order-isomorphic to the ordinal exponent β α. Proof. If α = 0, then β α = 1, and α β w also has only one element, the empty function (= the emptyset). So, assume that α 0. If β = 1, then α β w has only one member, namely the function with domain α whose value is always 0. This is clearly order-isomorphic to 1, as desired. So, suppose that β > 1. Now we define a function f mapping β α into α β w. Let f(0) be the member of α β w which takes only the value 0. Now suppose that 0 < ε < β α. By 4.30 write ε = β γ(0) δ(0) + β γ(1) δ(1) + + β γ(m 1) δ(m 1), where ε γ(0) > γ(1) > > γ(m 1) and 0 < δ(i) < β for each i < m. Note that β γ(0) ε < β α, so γ(0) < α. Then we define, for any ζ < α, (f(ε))(ζ) = { 0 if ζ / {γ(0),..., γ(m 1)}, δ(i) if ζ = γ(i) with i < m. Clearly f(ε) α β w. To see that f maps onto α β w, suppose that x α β w. If x takes only the value 0, then f(0) = x. Suppose that x takes on some nonzero value. Let {ξ < α : x(ξ) 0} = {γ(0), γ(1),..., γ(m 1)}, 31

19 where γ(0) > γ(1) > > γ(m 1). Let δ(i) = x(γ(i)) for each i < m, and let ε = β γ(0) δ(0) + β γ(1) δ(1) + + β γ(m 1) δ(m 1). Clearly then f(ε) = x. Now we complete the proof by showing that for any ε, θ < β α, ε < θ iff f(ε) < f(θ). This equivalence is clear if one of ε, θ is 0, so suppose that both are nonzero. Write ε = β γ(0) δ(0) + β γ(1) δ(1) + + β γ(m 1) δ(m 1), where α γ(0) > γ(1) > > γ(m 1) and 0 < δ(i) < β for each i < m, and θ = β γ (0) δ (0) + β γ (1) δ (1) + + β γ (n 1) δ (n 1), where α γ (0) > γ (1) > > γ (n 1) and 0 < δ (i) < β for each i < n. By symmetry we may suppose that m n. Note that N(β, m, γ, δ), k(β, m, γ, δ) = ε, N(β, n, γ, δ ), and k(β, n, γ, δ ) = θ. We now consider several possibilities. Case 1. ε = θ. Then clearly f(ε) = f(θ). Case 4. γ γ, δ δ, and m < n. Thus ε < θ. Also, γ (m) is the largest ξ < α such that (f(ε))(ξ) (f(θ))(ξ), and (f(ε))(ξ) = 0 < δ (m) = (f(θ))(γ (m)), so f(ε) < f(θ). Case 3. There is an i < m such that γ(j) = γ (j) and δ(j) = δ (j) for all j < i, while γ(i) γ (i). By symmetry, say that γ(i) < γ (i). Then we have ε < θ. Since γ (i) is the largest ξ < α such that (f(ε))(ξ) (f(θ))(ξ), and (f(ε))(γ (i)) = 0 < δ (i) = (f(θ))(γ (i)), we also have f(ε) < f(θ). Case 4. There is an i < m such that γ(j) = γ (j) and δ(j) = δ (j) for all j < i, while γ(i) = γ (i) and δ(i) δ (i). By symmetry, say that δ(i) < δ (i). Then we have ε < θ. Since γ(i) is the largest ξ < α such that (f(ε))(ξ) (f(θ))(ξ), and (f(ε))(γ (i)) = δ(i) < δ (i) = (f(θ))(γ (i)), we also have f(ε) < f(θ). We finish this chapter with two important characterizations of absorption properties of ordinals. Lemma If α < ω β, then α + ω β = ω β. Proof. First we prove (1) If γ < β, then ω γ + ω β = ω β. In fact, suppose that γ < β. Then there is a nonzero δ such that γ + δ = β. Then ω γ + ω β = ω γ + ω γ+δ = ω γ + ω γ ω δ = ω γ (1 + ω δ ) = ω γ ω δ = ω β. By an easy ordinary induction, we obtain from (1) (2) If γ < β and m ω, then ω γ m + ω β = ω β. Now we turn to the general case. If β = 0 or α < ω, the desired conclusion is clear. So suppose that ω α and β > 0. Then we can write α = ω γ m+δ with m ω and δ < ω γ. Then ω β α + ω β = ω γ m + δ + ω β ω γ (m + 1) + ω β = ω β 32

20 Now we have the following characterization of absorption under addition: Theorem The following conditions are equivalent, for any ordinal α: (i) β + α = α for all β < α. (Absorption under addition) (ii) For all β, γ < α, also β + γ < α. (iii) α = 0, or α = ω β for some β. Proof. (i) (ii): Assuming (i), if β, γ < α, then β + γ < β + α = α. (ii) (iii): Assume (ii). If α = 0 or α = 1, condition (iii) holds, so suppose that 2 α. Then clearly (ii) implies that α ω. Choose β, m, γ such that m ω, α = ω β m + γ, and γ < ω β. If γ 0, then ω β m < ω β m + γ = α, and also γ < ω β < α, so that (ii) is contradicted. So γ = 0. If m > 1, write m = n + 1 with n 0. Then α = ω β m = ω β (n + 1) = ω β n + ω β, and ω β n, ω β < α, again contradicting (ii). Hence m = 1, as desired in (iii). Finally, (iii) (i) by Lemma Theorem For any ordinal α the following conditions are equivalent: (i) For all β, if 0 < β < α then β α = α. (ii) For all β, γ < α, also β γ < α. (iii) α {0, 1, 2} or there is a β such that α = ω (ωβ). Proof. (i) (ii): Assume (i), and suppose that β, γ < α. If β = 0, then β γ = 0 < α. If β 0, then β γ < β α = α. (ii) (iii): Assume (ii), and suppose that α / {0, 1, 2}. Clearly then ω α. Now if β, γ < α, then β + γ < α. In fact, if β γ, then β + γ γ + γ = γ 2 < α by (ii); and if γ < β then β + γ < β + β = β 2 < α. Hence by 4.33 there is a γ such that α = ω γ. Now if δ, ε < γ, then ω δ, ω ε < ω γ = α, and hence ω δ+ε = ω δ ω ε < α = ω γ, so that δ + ε < γ. Hence by 4.33, γ = ω β for some β. (iii) (i): Assume (iii). Clearly 0, 1, 2 satisfy (i), so assume that α = ω (ωβ). Take any γ < α with γ 0. If γ < ω, clearly γ α = α. So assume that ω γ. Write γ = ω δ m + ε with m ω and ε < ω δ. Then δ < β, and so α = ω (ωβ) γ ω (ωβ) = (ω δ m + ε) ω (ωβ ) (ω δ m + ω δ ) ω (ωβ ) = ω δ (m + 1) ω (ωβ ) ω δ+1 ω (ωβ ) = ω δ+1+ωβ = ω (ωβ ) = α 33

21 EXERCISES E4.1. Prove that the following conditions are equivalent: (i) x is an ordinal; (ii) x is transitive, and for all y, z x, either y z, y = z, or z y; (iii) x is transitive, and for all y, if y x and y is transitive, then y x; (iv) for all y x, either y {y} = x or y {y} x; and for all y x, either y = x or y x; (v) x is transitive and {(y, z) x x : y z} well-orders x. Hint: prove this in the following order: (i) (v) [easy]; (v) (ii) [obvious]; (ii) (iii) [Assume that y x, y transitive; apply the foundation axiom to x\y]; (iii) (i) [Let y = {z x : z is an ordinal}, and get a contradiction from assuming that y x]; (i) (iv) [easy]; (iv) (i) [Let α be an ordinal not in x, and take the least ordinal β α {α} such that β / x. Work with β to show that x is an ordinal. E4.2. Show that (2 2) ω 2 ω 2 ω. E4.3. Use the transfinite recursion principle to justify the definition of ordinal addition. E4.4. Use the transfinite recursion principle to justify the definition of ordinal multiplication. E4.5. Use the transfinite recursion principle to justify the definition of ordinal exponentiation. E4.6. Formulate and prove a set version of the transfinite recursion principle. E4.7. Suppose that α, β, γ are ordinal numbers with α < ω γ. Prove that α + β + ω γ = β + ω γ. E4.8. Show that for every nonzero ordinal α there are only finitely many ordinals β such that α = γ β for some γ. E4.9. Prove that n (ωω) = ω (ωω) for every natural number n > 1. E4.10. Assume that γ 0, 0 < m < ω, and β < ω γ. Prove that β + ω γ m = ω γ m. E4.11. Suppose that 0 < k ω and α 0. Then k ω α = ω α. E4.12. Suppose that 0 < k ω, α 0, and 0 < m ω. Then k ω α m = ω α m. E4.13. Suppose that α = ω δ k + ε with δ 0, k ω, and ε < ω δ, β < ω δ, and m ω\1. Show that (α + β) m = α m + β. E4.14. Suppose that α = ω δ k + ε with δ 0, k ω, and ε < ω δ, and β < ω δ. Show that (α + β) ω = α ω. E4.15. Show that (α + β) γ α γ + β γ for any ordinals α, β, γ.hint: write α and β using Theorem 4.28 and γ using Theorem E4.16. Show that the following conditions are equivalent for any ordinals α, β: (i) α + β = β + α. 34

22 (ii) There exist an ordinal γ and natural numbers k, l such that α = γ k and β = γ l. References Sierpiński, W. Cardinal and ordinal numbers. Pań. Wyd. Naukowe, 1958, 487 pp. 35

Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit

Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit Ordinal Arithmetic: Addition, Multiplication, Exponentiation and Limit Ting Zhang Stanford May 11, 2001 Stanford, 5/11/2001 1 Outline Ordinal Classification Ordinal Addition Ordinal Multiplication Ordinal

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers

Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers Chapter 3: Ordinal Numbers There are two kinds of number.. Ordinal numbers (0th), st, 2nd, 3rd, 4th, 5th,..., ω, ω +,... ω2, ω2+,... ω 2... answers to the question What position is... in a sequence? What

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

2 Composition. Invertible Mappings

2 Composition. Invertible Mappings Arkansas Tech University MATH 4033: Elementary Modern Algebra Dr. Marcel B. Finan Composition. Invertible Mappings In this section we discuss two procedures for creating new mappings from old ones, namely,

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set

Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set Every set of first-order formulas is equivalent to an independent set May 6, 2008 Abstract A set of first-order formulas, whatever the cardinality of the set of symbols, is equivalent to an independent

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER

ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER ORDINAL ARITHMETIC JULIAN J. SCHLÖDER Abstract. We define ordinal arithmetic and show laws of Left- Monotonicity, Associativity, Distributivity, some minor related properties and the Cantor Normal Form.

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

EE512: Error Control Coding

EE512: Error Control Coding EE512: Error Control Coding Solution for Assignment on Finite Fields February 16, 2007 1. (a) Addition and Multiplication tables for GF (5) and GF (7) are shown in Tables 1 and 2. + 0 1 2 3 4 0 0 1 2 3

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

ω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω

ω ω ω ω ω ω+2 ω ω+2 + ω ω ω ω+2 + ω ω+1 ω ω+2 2 ω ω ω ω ω ω ω ω+1 ω ω2 ω ω2 + ω ω ω2 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω ω+1 ω ω2 + ω ω+1 + ω ω ω ω2 + ω 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 ω ω + 1 ω + 2 ω + 3 ω + 4 ω2 ω2 + 1 ω2 + 2 ω2 + 3 ω3 ω3 + 1 ω3 + 2 ω4 ω4 + 1 ω5 ω 2 ω 2 + 1 ω 2 + 2 ω 2 + ω ω 2 + ω + 1 ω 2 + ω2 ω 2 2 ω 2 2 + 1 ω 2 2 + ω ω 2 3 ω 3 ω 3 + 1 ω 3 + ω ω 3 +

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor

Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor Uniform Convergence of Fourier Series Michael Taylor Given f L 1 T 1 ), we consider the partial sums of the Fourier series of f: N 1) S N fθ) = ˆfk)e ikθ. k= N A calculation gives the Dirichlet formula

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Chapter 2. Ordinals, well-founded relations.

Chapter 2. Ordinals, well-founded relations. Chapter 2. Ordinals, well-founded relations. 2.1. Well-founded Relations. We start with some definitions and rapidly reach the notion of a well-ordered set. Definition. For any X and any binary relation

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions

C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions C.S. 430 Assignment 6, Sample Solutions Paul Liu November 15, 2007 Note that these are sample solutions only; in many cases there were many acceptable answers. 1 Reynolds Problem 10.1 1.1 Normal-order

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation

A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy. Equivalence Relation International Mathematical Forum, 5, 2010, no. 67, 3301-3307 A Note on Intuitionistic Fuzzy Equivalence Relation D. K. Basnet Dept. of Mathematics, Assam University Silchar-788011, Assam, India dkbasnet@rediffmail.com

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in

Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in Nowhere-zero flows Let be a digraph, Abelian group. A Γ-circulation in is a mapping : such that, where, and : tail in X, head in : tail in X, head in A nowhere-zero Γ-flow is a Γ-circulation such that

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Cardinals. Y = n Y n. Define h: X Y by f(x) if x X n X n+1 and n is even h(x) = g

Cardinals. Y = n Y n. Define h: X Y by f(x) if x X n X n+1 and n is even h(x) = g Cardinals 1. Introduction to Cardinals We work in the base theory ZF. The definitions and many (but not all) of the basic theorems do not require AC; we will indicate explicitly when we are using choice.

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Example Sheet 3 Solutions

Example Sheet 3 Solutions Example Sheet 3 Solutions. i Regular Sturm-Liouville. ii Singular Sturm-Liouville mixed boundary conditions. iii Not Sturm-Liouville ODE is not in Sturm-Liouville form. iv Regular Sturm-Liouville note

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1)

4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(1,1) 84 CHAPTER 4. STATIONARY TS MODELS 4.6 Autoregressive Moving Average Model ARMA(,) This section is an introduction to a wide class of models ARMA(p,q) which we will consider in more detail later in this

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Homework 3 Solutions

Homework 3 Solutions Homework 3 Solutions Igor Yanovsky (Math 151A TA) Problem 1: Compute the absolute error and relative error in approximations of p by p. (Use calculator!) a) p π, p 22/7; b) p π, p 3.141. Solution: For

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Solutions for exercises in chapter 1 = 2, 3, 1, 4 ; = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2 1 S 1 1 S 0 = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2, 1, 4,1,3. 1, 1,..., 1, S 0

Solutions for exercises in chapter 1 = 2, 3, 1, 4 ; = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2 1 S 1 1 S 0 = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2, 1, 4,1,3. 1, 1,..., 1, S 0 E1.1 Verify that and Solutions for exercises in chapter 1 S 0 S 1 = 2, 3, 1, 4 (S 0 S 1 ) ( S 1 S 0 ) = 2, 2, 3, 4, 2, 1, 4, 1,3. S 0 S 1 = 2 S 0 S 1 = 2 3 1 S 1 = 2, 3, 1, 4 ; (S 0 S 1 ) ( S 1 S 0 ) =

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

k A = [k, k]( )[a 1, a 2 ] = [ka 1,ka 2 ] 4For the division of two intervals of confidence in R +

k A = [k, k]( )[a 1, a 2 ] = [ka 1,ka 2 ] 4For the division of two intervals of confidence in R + Chapter 3. Fuzzy Arithmetic 3- Fuzzy arithmetic: ~Addition(+) and subtraction (-): Let A = [a and B = [b, b in R If x [a and y [b, b than x+y [a +b +b Symbolically,we write A(+)B = [a (+)[b, b = [a +b

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016

Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016 Concrete Mathematics Exercises from 30 September 2016 Silvio Capobianco Exercise 1.7 Let H(n) = J(n + 1) J(n). Equation (1.8) tells us that H(2n) = 2, and H(2n+1) = J(2n+2) J(2n+1) = (2J(n+1) 1) (2J(n)+1)

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

2. Let H 1 and H 2 be Hilbert spaces and let T : H 1 H 2 be a bounded linear operator. Prove that [T (H 1 )] = N (T ). (6p)

2. Let H 1 and H 2 be Hilbert spaces and let T : H 1 H 2 be a bounded linear operator. Prove that [T (H 1 )] = N (T ). (6p) Uppsala Universitet Matematiska Institutionen Andreas Strömbergsson Prov i matematik Funktionalanalys Kurs: F3B, F4Sy, NVP 2005-03-08 Skrivtid: 9 14 Tillåtna hjälpmedel: Manuella skrivdon, Kreyszigs bok

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests

Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests Other Test Constructions: Likelihood Ratio & Bayes Tests Side-Note: So far we have seen a few approaches for creating tests such as Neyman-Pearson Lemma ( most powerful tests of H 0 : θ = θ 0 vs H 1 :

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs

Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs Fractional Colorings and Zykov Products of graphs Who? Nichole Schimanski When? July 27, 2011 Graphs A graph, G, consists of a vertex set, V (G), and an edge set, E(G). V (G) is any finite set E(G) is

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3

Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3 Lecture 2: Dirac notation and a review of linear algebra Read Sakurai chapter 1, Baym chatper 3 1 State vector space and the dual space Space of wavefunctions The space of wavefunctions is the set of all

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes

6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes 122 CHAPTER 6. ARMA MODELS 6.3 Forecasting ARMA processes The purpose of forecasting is to predict future values of a TS based on the data collected to the present. In this section we will discuss a linear

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Lecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic

Lecture 2. Soundness and completeness of propositional logic Lecture 2 Soundness and completeness of propositional logic February 9, 2004 1 Overview Review of natural deduction. Soundness and completeness. Semantics of propositional formulas. Soundness proof. Completeness

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II

ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II ST5224: Advanced Statistical Theory II 2014/2015: Semester II Tutorial 7 1. Let X be a sample from a population P and consider testing hypotheses H 0 : P = P 0 versus H 1 : P = P 1, where P j is a known

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Finite Field Problems: Solutions

Finite Field Problems: Solutions Finite Field Problems: Solutions 1. Let f = x 2 +1 Z 11 [x] and let F = Z 11 [x]/(f), a field. Let Solution: F =11 2 = 121, so F = 121 1 = 120. The possible orders are the divisors of 120. Solution: The

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Tridiagonal matrices. Gérard MEURANT. October, 2008

Tridiagonal matrices. Gérard MEURANT. October, 2008 Tridiagonal matrices Gérard MEURANT October, 2008 1 Similarity 2 Cholesy factorizations 3 Eigenvalues 4 Inverse Similarity Let α 1 ω 1 β 1 α 2 ω 2 T =......... β 2 α 1 ω 1 β 1 α and β i ω i, i = 1,...,

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequality for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x, y, z X.

Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequality for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x, y, z X. Math 446 Homework 3 Solutions. (1). (i): Reverse triangle inequalit for metrics: Let (X, d) be a metric space and let x,, z X. Prove that d(x, z) d(, z) d(x, ). (ii): Reverse triangle inequalit for norms:

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

5. Choice under Uncertainty

5. Choice under Uncertainty 5. Choice under Uncertainty Daisuke Oyama Microeconomics I May 23, 2018 Formulations von Neumann-Morgenstern (1944/1947) X: Set of prizes Π: Set of probability distributions on X : Preference relation

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS

MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS MINIMAL CLOSED SETS AND MAXIMAL CLOSED SETS FUMIE NAKAOKA AND NOBUYUKI ODA Received 20 December 2005; Revised 28 May 2006; Accepted 6 August 2006 Some properties of minimal closed sets and maximal closed

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Reminders: linear functions

Reminders: linear functions Reminders: linear functions Let U and V be vector spaces over the same field F. Definition A function f : U V is linear if for every u 1, u 2 U, f (u 1 + u 2 ) = f (u 1 ) + f (u 2 ), and for every u U

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics

Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics Lecture 15 - Root System Axiomatics Nov 1, 01 In this lecture we examine root systems from an axiomatic point of view. 1 Reflections If v R n, then it determines a hyperplane, denoted P v, through the

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates

derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates derivation of the Laplacian from rectangular to spherical coordinates swapnizzle 03-03- :5:43 We begin by recognizing the familiar conversion from rectangular to spherical coordinates (note that φ is used

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β

3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS. NOTE: cos(α+β) cos α + cos β cos(α-β) cos α -cos β 3.4 SUM AND DIFFERENCE FORMULAS Page Theorem cos(αβ cos α cos β -sin α cos(α-β cos α cos β sin α NOTE: cos(αβ cos α cos β cos(α-β cos α -cos β Proof of cos(α-β cos α cos β sin α Let s use a unit circle

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Phys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required)

Phys460.nb Solution for the t-dependent Schrodinger s equation How did we find the solution? (not required) Phys460.nb 81 ψ n (t) is still the (same) eigenstate of H But for tdependent H. The answer is NO. 5.5.5. Solution for the tdependent Schrodinger s equation If we assume that at time t 0, the electron starts

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Math221: HW# 1 solutions

Math221: HW# 1 solutions Math: HW# solutions Andy Royston October, 5 7.5.7, 3 rd Ed. We have a n = b n = a = fxdx = xdx =, x cos nxdx = x sin nx n sin nxdx n = cos nx n = n n, x sin nxdx = x cos nx n + cos nxdx n cos n = + sin

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential Equations Let a (t), a 2 (t),..., a nn (t), b (t), b 2 (t),..., b n (t) be continuous functions on the interval I. The system of n first-order differential equations

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations. ------------------ ----------------------------- -----------------

Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations. ------------------ ----------------------------- ----------------- Inverse trigonometric functions & General Solution of Trigonometric Equations. 1. Sin ( ) = a) b) c) d) Ans b. Solution : Method 1. Ans a: 17 > 1 a) is rejected. w.k.t Sin ( sin ) = d is rejected. If sin

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

The Simply Typed Lambda Calculus

The Simply Typed Lambda Calculus Type Inference Instead of writing type annotations, can we use an algorithm to infer what the type annotations should be? That depends on the type system. For simple type systems the answer is yes, and

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

THE SECOND ISOMORPHISM THEOREM ON ORDERED SET UNDER ANTIORDERS. Daniel A. Romano

THE SECOND ISOMORPHISM THEOREM ON ORDERED SET UNDER ANTIORDERS. Daniel A. Romano 235 Kragujevac J. Math. 30 (2007) 235 242. THE SECOND ISOMORPHISM THEOREM ON ORDERED SET UNDER ANTIORDERS Daniel A. Romano Department of Mathematics and Informatics, Banja Luka University, Mladena Stojanovića

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS

SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS Sahand Communications in Mathematical Analysis (SCMA) Vol. 3 No. 1 (2016), 21-27 http://scma.maragheh.ac.ir SOME PROPERTIES OF FUZZY REAL NUMBERS BAYAZ DARABY 1 AND JAVAD JAFARI 2 Abstract. In the mathematical

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

DIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANSFORMATION SEMIGROUPS

DIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANSFORMATION SEMIGROUPS GANIT J. Bangladesh Math. oc. IN 606-694) 0) -7 DIRECT PRODUCT AND WREATH PRODUCT OF TRANFORMATION EMIGROUP ubrata Majumdar, * Kalyan Kumar Dey and Mohd. Altab Hossain Department of Mathematics University

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Section 8.3 Trigonometric Equations

Section 8.3 Trigonometric Equations 99 Section 8. Trigonometric Equations Objective 1: Solve Equations Involving One Trigonometric Function. In this section and the next, we will exple how to solving equations involving trigonometric functions.

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

HOMEWORK 4 = G. In order to plot the stress versus the stretch we define a normalized stretch:

HOMEWORK 4 = G. In order to plot the stress versus the stretch we define a normalized stretch: HOMEWORK 4 Problem a For the fast loading case, we want to derive the relationship between P zz and λ z. We know that the nominal stress is expressed as: P zz = ψ λ z where λ z = λ λ z. Therefore, applying

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Problem Set 3: Solutions

Problem Set 3: Solutions CMPSCI 69GG Applied Information Theory Fall 006 Problem Set 3: Solutions. [Cover and Thomas 7.] a Define the following notation, C I p xx; Y max X; Y C I p xx; Ỹ max I X; Ỹ We would like to show that C

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2

Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2 International Journal of Algebra, Vol. 8, 24, no. 5, 239-246 HIKARI Ltd, www.m-hikari.com http://dx.doi.org/.2988/ija.24.422 Congruence Classes of Invertible Matrices of Order 3 over F 2 Ligong An and

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Homomorphism in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Automata

Homomorphism in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Automata International Journal of Fuzzy Mathematics Systems. ISSN 2248-9940 Volume 3, Number 1 (2013), pp. 39-45 Research India Publications http://www.ripublication.com/ijfms.htm Homomorphism in Intuitionistic

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets

Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets Commutative Monoids in Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets S K Mala #1, Dr. MM Shanmugapriya *2 1 PhD Scholar in Mathematics, Karpagam University, Coimbatore, Tamilnadu- 641021 Assistant Professor of Mathematics,

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests

Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests Statistical Inference I Locally most powerful tests Shirsendu Mukherjee Department of Statistics, Asutosh College, Kolkata, India. shirsendu st@yahoo.co.in So far we have treated the testing of one-sided

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Απόκριση σε Μοναδιαία Ωστική Δύναμη (Unit Impulse) Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο. Απόστολος Σ.

Απόκριση σε Μοναδιαία Ωστική Δύναμη (Unit Impulse) Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο. Απόστολος Σ. Απόκριση σε Δυνάμεις Αυθαίρετα Μεταβαλλόμενες με το Χρόνο The time integral of a force is referred to as impulse, is determined by and is obtained from: Newton s 2 nd Law of motion states that the action

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC = DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION #2. h 0 h h 0 h h 0 ( ) g k = g 0 + g 1 + g g 2009 =?

ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC = DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION #2. h 0 h h 0 h h 0 ( ) g k = g 0 + g 1 + g g 2009 =? Teko Classes IITJEE/AIEEE Maths by SUHAAG SIR, Bhopal, Ph (0755) 3 00 000 www.tekoclasses.com ANSWERSHEET (TOPIC DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS) COLLECTION # Question Type A.Single Correct Type Q. (A) Sol least

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees

Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees Bounding Nonsplitting Enumeration Degrees Thomas F. Kent Andrea Sorbi Università degli Studi di Siena Italia July 18, 2007 Goal: Introduce a form of Σ 0 2-permitting for the enumeration degrees. Till now,

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

6.1. Dirac Equation. Hamiltonian. Dirac Eq.

6.1. Dirac Equation. Hamiltonian. Dirac Eq. 6.1. Dirac Equation Ref: M.Kaku, Quantum Field Theory, Oxford Univ Press (1993) η μν = η μν = diag(1, -1, -1, -1) p 0 = p 0 p = p i = -p i p μ p μ = p 0 p 0 + p i p i = E c 2 - p 2 = (m c) 2 H = c p 2

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

A Conception of Inductive Logic: Example

A Conception of Inductive Logic: Example A Conception of Inductive Logic: Example Patrick Maher Department of Philosophy, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign This paper presents a simple example of inductive logic done according to the

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

MA 342N Assignment 1 Due 24 February 2016

MA 342N Assignment 1 Due 24 February 2016 M 342N ssignment Due 24 February 206 Id: 342N-s206-.m4,v. 206/02/5 2:25:36 john Exp john. Suppose that q, in addition to satisfying the assumptions from lecture, is an even function. Prove that η(λ = 0,

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES G11LMA Linear Mathematics Examination Solutions

SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES G11LMA Linear Mathematics Examination Solutions SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES GLMA Linear Mathematics 00- Examination Solutions. (a) i. ( + 5i)( i) = (6 + 5) + (5 )i = + i. Real part is, imaginary part is. (b) ii. + 5i i ( + 5i)( + i) = ( i)( + i)

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5. Luca Alberucci, University of Berne. Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008

Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5. Luca Alberucci, University of Berne. Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008 Sequent Calculi for the Modal µ-calculus over S5 Luca Alberucci, University of Berne Logic Colloquium Berne, July 4th 2008 Introduction Koz: Axiomatisation for the modal µ-calculus over K Axioms: All classical

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Some new generalized topologies via hereditary classes. Key Words:hereditary generalized topological space, A κ(h,µ)-sets, κµ -topology.

Some new generalized topologies via hereditary classes. Key Words:hereditary generalized topological space, A κ(h,µ)-sets, κµ -topology. Bol. Soc. Paran. Mat. (3s.) v. 30 2 (2012): 71 77. c SPM ISSN-2175-1188 on line ISSN-00378712 in press SPM: www.spm.uem.br/bspm doi:10.5269/bspm.v30i2.13793 Some new generalized topologies via hereditary

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Second Order Partial Differential Equations

Second Order Partial Differential Equations Chapter 7 Second Order Partial Differential Equations 7.1 Introduction A second order linear PDE in two independent variables (x, y Ω can be written as A(x, y u x + B(x, y u xy + C(x, y u u u + D(x, y

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS

CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS CRASH COURSE IN PRECALCULUS Shiah-Sen Wang The graphs are prepared by Chien-Lun Lai Based on : Precalculus: Mathematics for Calculus by J. Stuwart, L. Redin & S. Watson, 6th edition, 01, Brooks/Cole Chapter

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

1. Introduction and Preliminaries.

1. Introduction and Preliminaries. Faculty of Sciences and Mathematics, University of Niš, Serbia Available at: http://www.pmf.ni.ac.yu/filomat Filomat 22:1 (2008), 97 106 ON δ SETS IN γ SPACES V. Renuka Devi and D. Sivaraj Abstract We

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

forms This gives Remark 1. How to remember the above formulas: Substituting these into the equation we obtain with

forms This gives Remark 1. How to remember the above formulas: Substituting these into the equation we obtain with Week 03: C lassification of S econd- Order L inear Equations In last week s lectures we have illustrated how to obtain the general solutions of first order PDEs using the method of characteristics. We

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates Kiryl Tsishchanka Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates In this section we develop the formula for the area of a region whose boundary is given by a polar equation. We need to use the formula for the

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Matrices and Determinants

Matrices and Determinants Matrices and Determinants SUBJECTIVE PROBLEMS: Q 1. For what value of k do the following system of equations possess a non-trivial (i.e., not all zero) solution over the set of rationals Q? x + ky + 3z

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Coefficient Inequalities for a New Subclass of K-uniformly Convex Functions

Coefficient Inequalities for a New Subclass of K-uniformly Convex Functions International Journal of Computational Science and Mathematics. ISSN 0974-89 Volume, Number (00), pp. 67--75 International Research Publication House http://www.irphouse.com Coefficient Inequalities for

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 6/5/2006

ΚΥΠΡΙΑΚΗ ΕΤΑΙΡΕΙΑ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ CYPRUS COMPUTER SOCIETY ΠΑΓΚΥΠΡΙΟΣ ΜΑΘΗΤΙΚΟΣ ΔΙΑΓΩΝΙΣΜΟΣ ΠΛΗΡΟΦΟΡΙΚΗΣ 6/5/2006 Οδηγίες: Να απαντηθούν όλες οι ερωτήσεις. Ολοι οι αριθμοί που αναφέρονται σε όλα τα ερωτήματα είναι μικρότεροι το 1000 εκτός αν ορίζεται διαφορετικά στη διατύπωση του προβλήματος. Διάρκεια: 3,5 ώρες Καλή

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

3.2 Simple Roots and Weyl Group

3.2 Simple Roots and Weyl Group 44 CHAPTER 3. ROOT SYSTEMS 3.2 Simple Roots and Weyl Group In this section, we fix a root system Φ of rank l in a euclidean space E, with Weyl group W. 3.2.1 Bases and Weyl chambers Def. A subset of Φ

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Arithmetical applications of lagrangian interpolation. Tanguy Rivoal. Institut Fourier CNRS and Université de Grenoble 1

Arithmetical applications of lagrangian interpolation. Tanguy Rivoal. Institut Fourier CNRS and Université de Grenoble 1 Arithmetical applications of lagrangian interpolation Tanguy Rivoal Institut Fourier CNRS and Université de Grenoble Conference Diophantine and Analytic Problems in Number Theory, The 00th anniversary

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Generating Set of the Complete Semigroups of Binary Relations

Generating Set of the Complete Semigroups of Binary Relations Applied Mathematics 06 7 98-07 Published Online January 06 in SciRes http://wwwscirporg/journal/am http://dxdoiorg/036/am067009 Generating Set of the Complete Semigroups of Binary Relations Yasha iasamidze

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

CHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS

CHAPTER 25 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS CHAPTER 5 SOLVING EQUATIONS BY ITERATIVE METHODS EXERCISE 104 Page 8 1. Find the positive root of the equation x + 3x 5 = 0, correct to 3 significant figures, using the method of bisection. Let f(x) =

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

THE GENERAL INDUCTIVE ARGUMENT FOR MEASURE ANALYSES WITH ADDITIVE ORDINAL ALGEBRAS

THE GENERAL INDUCTIVE ARGUMENT FOR MEASURE ANALYSES WITH ADDITIVE ORDINAL ALGEBRAS THE GENERAL INDUCTIVE ARGUMENT FOR MEASURE ANALYSES WITH ADDITIVE ORDINAL ALGEBRAS STEFAN BOLD, BENEDIKT LÖWE In [BoLö ] we gave a survey of measure analyses under AD, discussed the general theory of order

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Solutions to Exercise Sheet 5

Solutions to Exercise Sheet 5 Solutions to Eercise Sheet 5 jacques@ucsd.edu. Let X and Y be random variables with joint pdf f(, y) = 3y( + y) where and y. Determine each of the following probabilities. Solutions. a. P (X ). b. P (X

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Cyclic or elementary abelian Covers of K 4

Cyclic or elementary abelian Covers of K 4 Cyclic or elementary abelian Covers of K 4 Yan-Quan Feng Mathematics, Beijing Jiaotong University Beijing 100044, P.R. China Summer School, Rogla, Slovenian 2011-06 Outline 1 Question 2 Main results 3

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

The challenges of non-stable predicates

The challenges of non-stable predicates The challenges of non-stable predicates Consider a non-stable predicate Φ encoding, say, a safety property. We want to determine whether Φ holds for our program. The challenges of non-stable predicates

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Practice Exam 2. Conceptual Questions. 1. State a Basic identity and then verify it. (a) Identity: Solution: One identity is csc(θ) = 1

Practice Exam 2. Conceptual Questions. 1. State a Basic identity and then verify it. (a) Identity: Solution: One identity is csc(θ) = 1 Conceptual Questions. State a Basic identity and then verify it. a) Identity: Solution: One identity is cscθ) = sinθ) Practice Exam b) Verification: Solution: Given the point of intersection x, y) of the

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

About these lecture notes. Simply Typed λ-calculus. Types

About these lecture notes. Simply Typed λ-calculus. Types About these lecture notes Simply Typed λ-calculus Akim Demaille akim@lrde.epita.fr EPITA École Pour l Informatique et les Techniques Avancées Many of these slides are largely inspired from Andrew D. Ker

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude

Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude Approximation of distance between locations on earth given by latitude and longitude Jan Behrens 2012-12-31 In this paper we shall provide a method to approximate distances between two points on earth

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II

Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II Lecture 13 - Root Space Decomposition II October 18, 2012 1 Review First let us recall the situation. Let g be a simple algebra, with maximal toral subalgebra h (which we are calling a CSA, or Cartan Subalgebra).

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates

Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates Kiryl Tsishchanka Areas and Lengths in Polar Coordinates In this section we develop the formula for the area of a region whose boundary is given by a polar equation. We need to use the formula for the

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions.

On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions. On density of old sets in Prikry type extensions. Moti Gitik December 31, 2015 Abstract Every set of ordinals of cardinality κ in a Prikry extension with a measure over κ contains an old set of arbitrary

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Section 9.2 Polar Equations and Graphs

Section 9.2 Polar Equations and Graphs 180 Section 9. Polar Equations and Graphs In this section, we will be graphing polar equations on a polar grid. In the first few examples, we will write the polar equation in rectangular form to help identify

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Completeness Theorem for System AS1

Completeness Theorem for System AS1 11 The Completeness Theorem for System AS1 1. Introduction...2 2. Previous Definitions...2 3. Deductive Consistency...2 4. Maximal Consistent Sets...5 5. Lindenbaum s Lemma...6 6. Every Maximal Consistent

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval

Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential. be continuous functions on the interval Chapter 6: Systems of Linear Differential Equations Let a (t), a 2 (t),..., a nn (t), b (t), b 2 (t),..., b n (t) be continuous functions on the interval I. The system of n first-order differential equations

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Strain gauge and rosettes

Strain gauge and rosettes Strain gauge and rosettes Introduction A strain gauge is a device which is used to measure strain (deformation) on an object subjected to forces. Strain can be measured using various types of devices classified

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Partial Differential Equations in Biology The boundary element method. March 26, 2013

Partial Differential Equations in Biology The boundary element method. March 26, 2013 The boundary element method March 26, 203 Introduction and notation The problem: u = f in D R d u = ϕ in Γ D u n = g on Γ N, where D = Γ D Γ N, Γ D Γ N = (possibly, Γ D = [Neumann problem] or Γ N = [Dirichlet

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Abstract Storage Devices

Abstract Storage Devices Abstract Storage Devices Robert König Ueli Maurer Stefano Tessaro SOFSEM 2009 January 27, 2009 Outline 1. Motivation: Storage Devices 2. Abstract Storage Devices (ASD s) 3. Reducibility 4. Factoring ASD

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

F A S C I C U L I M A T H E M A T I C I

F A S C I C U L I M A T H E M A T I C I F A S C I C U L I M A T H E M A T I C I Nr 46 2011 C. Carpintero, N. Rajesh and E. Rosas ON A CLASS OF (γ, γ )-PREOPEN SETS IN A TOPOLOGICAL SPACE Abstract. In this paper we have introduced the concept

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

The semiclassical Garding inequality

The semiclassical Garding inequality The semiclassical Garding inequality We give a proof of the semiclassical Garding inequality (Theorem 4.1 using as the only black box the Calderon-Vaillancourt Theorem. 1 Anti-Wick quantization For (q,

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Lecture 34 Bootstrap confidence intervals

Lecture 34 Bootstrap confidence intervals Lecture 34 Bootstrap confidence intervals Confidence Intervals θ: an unknown parameter of interest We want to find limits θ and θ such that Gt = P nˆθ θ t If G 1 1 α is known, then P θ θ = P θ θ = 1 α

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

The Pohozaev identity for the fractional Laplacian

The Pohozaev identity for the fractional Laplacian The Pohozaev identity for the fractional Laplacian Xavier Ros-Oton Departament Matemàtica Aplicada I, Universitat Politècnica de Catalunya (joint work with Joaquim Serra) Xavier Ros-Oton (UPC) The Pohozaev

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines

New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines New bounds for spherical two-distance sets and equiangular lines Michigan State University Oct 8-31, 016 Anhui University Definition If X = {x 1, x,, x N } S n 1 (unit sphere in R n ) and x i, x j = a

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Second Order RLC Filters

Second Order RLC Filters ECEN 60 Circuits/Electronics Spring 007-0-07 P. Mathys Second Order RLC Filters RLC Lowpass Filter A passive RLC lowpass filter (LPF) circuit is shown in the following schematic. R L C v O (t) Using phasor

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Main source: "Discrete-time systems and computer control" by Α. ΣΚΟΔΡΑΣ ΨΗΦΙΑΚΟΣ ΕΛΕΓΧΟΣ ΔΙΑΛΕΞΗ 4 ΔΙΑΦΑΝΕΙΑ 1

Main source: Discrete-time systems and computer control by Α. ΣΚΟΔΡΑΣ ΨΗΦΙΑΚΟΣ ΕΛΕΓΧΟΣ ΔΙΑΛΕΞΗ 4 ΔΙΑΦΑΝΕΙΑ 1 Main source: "Discrete-time systems and computer control" by Α. ΣΚΟΔΡΑΣ ΨΗΦΙΑΚΟΣ ΕΛΕΓΧΟΣ ΔΙΑΛΕΞΗ 4 ΔΙΑΦΑΝΕΙΑ 1 A Brief History of Sampling Research 1915 - Edmund Taylor Whittaker (1873-1956) devised a

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Econ 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1

Econ 2110: Fall 2008 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8  questions or comments to Dan Fetter 1 Eon : Fall 8 Suggested Solutions to Problem Set 8 Email questions or omments to Dan Fetter Problem. Let X be a salar with density f(x, θ) (θx + θ) [ x ] with θ. (a) Find the most powerful level α test

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

TMA4115 Matematikk 3

TMA4115 Matematikk 3 TMA4115 Matematikk 3 Andrew Stacey Norges Teknisk-Naturvitenskapelige Universitet Trondheim Spring 2010 Lecture 12: Mathematics Marvellous Matrices Andrew Stacey Norges Teknisk-Naturvitenskapelige Universitet

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Fourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics

Fourier Series. MATH 211, Calculus II. J. Robert Buchanan. Spring Department of Mathematics Fourier Series MATH 211, Calculus II J. Robert Buchanan Department of Mathematics Spring 2018 Introduction Not all functions can be represented by Taylor series. f (k) (c) A Taylor series f (x) = (x c)

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

SOLVING CUBICS AND QUARTICS BY RADICALS

SOLVING CUBICS AND QUARTICS BY RADICALS SOLVING CUBICS AND QUARTICS BY RADICALS The purpose of this handout is to record the classical formulas expressing the roots of degree three and degree four polynomials in terms of radicals. We begin with

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Splitting stationary sets from weak forms of Choice

Splitting stationary sets from weak forms of Choice Splitting stationary sets from weak forms of Choice Paul Larson and Saharon Shelah February 16, 2008 Abstract Working in the context of restricted forms of the Axiom of Choice, we consider the problem

Διαβάστε περισσότερα

Μηχανική Μάθηση Hypothesis Testing

Μηχανική Μάθηση Hypothesis Testing ΕΛΛΗΝΙΚΗ ΔΗΜΟΚΡΑΤΙΑ ΠΑΝΕΠΙΣΤΗΜΙΟ ΚΡΗΤΗΣ Μηχανική Μάθηση Hypothesis Testing Γιώργος Μπορμπουδάκης Τμήμα Επιστήμης Υπολογιστών Procedure 1. Form the null (H 0 ) and alternative (H 1 ) hypothesis 2. Consider

Διαβάστε περισσότερα